1. Introduction
National courts increasingly apply international norms to resolve disputes which have been submitted to them.Footnote 1 This trend seems to uphold the auguries of that scholarship which, since the mid-1970s, has emphasized the central role of domestic judges in ensuring the effectiveness of the international legal order and in contributing to the evolution of its norms.Footnote 2
The administration of international law by domestic courts, however, keeps running into apparently insuperable hurdles when it comes to scrutinizing the legality of the executive conduct in the fields of defence and foreign affairs. Indeed, there remains concern that judicial intervention in such matters might affect essential interests of the state or even imperil its very existence.Footnote 3
A typical expression of this concern is represented by the courts’ proclivity to dismiss at the outset disputes relating to international matters by resorting to doctrines which prohibit ruling on ‘political questions’ (according to the common law wording)Footnote 4 or ‘political or governmental acts’ (according to that of civil law).Footnote 5 It is well known that these doctrines envisage the existence of a political power whose exercise is exempt from judicial review.Footnote 6 Although the scope of these doctrines has undergone considerable downsizing due to the gradual emergence of the rule of law; the immunity of political power is still affirmed with respect to military and foreign policy matters.
The roots and scale of this phenomenon have led some authors to argue that non-justiciability in these areas constitutes an unavoidable need, even in democratic regimes.Footnote 7 Yet this position is belied by the fact that in many countries (e.g. Germany,Footnote 8 the Netherlands,Footnote 9 Israel,Footnote 10 and SpainFootnote 11) judges regularly discuss and decide disputes regarding the external acts of the executive. Moreover, recent judgments by US and UK courts on issues related to the so-called ‘war on terror’ suggest that the boundaries of non-justiciability are rather unstable and often create the conditions for deep incursions by the judiciary.Footnote 12
Judicial abstention in foreign affairs, therefore, far from being inevitable, is the result of choices made in each legal system. Aware of this, the most influential internationalists have been leading a long battle against these doctrines.Footnote 13 In this regard, it is worth recalling the resolution adopted in 1993 by the Institut de droit international (‘The Activities of National Judges and the International Relations of Their State’) whose Article 2 reads,
National courts, when called upon to adjudicate a question related to the exercise of executive power, should not decline competence on the basis of the political nature of the question if such exercise of power is subject to a rule of international law.Footnote 14
This assertion is fully shareable. It is difficult to see, in fact, why the rule of lawFootnote 15 must fade before the international action of the executive, especially when the latter is governed by specific rules of international law. It seems, however, that international law scholarship has overlooked two aspects of the question.
First, this subject has been dealt with mainly from the perspective of the domestic order. In particular, it has been argued – also by internationalists – that doctrines of judicial abstention lack constitutional underpinningsFootnote 16 and might be incompatible with the fundamental right of access to justice.Footnote 17 These argumentations are demonstrably correct and in the present work will be considered as given. Still, international law scholarship has not sufficiently highlighted the pressures exercised against these doctrines by the international as well as the community legal order (the latter being relevant, obviously, only for EU member states). Second, it has rarely been shown how to prevent judicial intervention in international matters from turning into ‘judicialization’ of foreign policy.
Hence, ideally by moving along the path traced by those who have already (of course, more authoritatively) dealt with this issue, the present work aims to analyse these two aspects in greater depth.
After a short introduction on the political act/question doctrines (section 2), I shall conduct a brief overview of the recent case law where judicial abstention resulted in a failed enforcement of international law (section 3). I shall limit this survey to cases involving the application of international norms protecting fundamental values such as peace, the environment, and human rights. Subsequently (section 4), I shall explain why and how the pressure exerted on the domestic legal system by international order may determine the abandonment of the political act/question doctrine. In section 5 I shall discuss the role which can be played, in this regard, by the EU legal order. Finally, having briefly recalled the prudential reasons which underlie judicial abstention in the field of foreign affairs (section 6), I shall try to illustrate how courts can settle these issues without refraining from exercising their duty of judicial review (section 7). Section 10 concludes.
2. A (brief) introduction to the political act/question doctrine
As the name itself suggests, the political act/question doctrine is grounded in the assumption that some issues belong exclusively to the political arena and consequently cannot undergo judicial scrutiny. It would be overly ambitious to embark here on a detailed comparative analysis of what this means in each national legal system. With some degree of approximation, however, it is possible to identify three rationales generally employed by domestic courts in order to justify judicial abstention.
First, it is affirmed that courts are forbidden to rule on issues which are constitutionally entrusted to the political branches of government.Footnote 18 In this regard, it is worth noting that such a prohibition does not need to be expressed but it can be interpretively drawn – as happens in most casesFootnote 19 – from constitutional norms (written or not) which allocate powers among the branches of government.
Second, it is argued that there are actions which are taken by government bodies in the exercise of a fourth function, the political one, which pertains to the state community as a whole.Footnote 20 Accordingly, these acts are not subject to jurisdictional control because courts cannot gain a position of otherness with respect to them.Footnote 21
Third, it is maintained that in some matters there are no judicially manageable standards to apply and the only judgement which can be made is on the political wisdom of the choices made by the government.Footnote 22 With regard to such questions, therefore, judicial review – rather than forbidden – is simply not practicable.
As I have indicated in the introduction, each of these arguments has already been dealt with and confuted by other (more authoritative) authors.Footnote 23 Accordingly, I shall not linger on them.
3. The non-justiciablity of defence and foreign affairs in the recent case law
Nowadays the effects of judicial abstention on the domestic enforcement of international law have reached a scale which was unforeseeable in the past. This evolution stems from the considerable increase in legal suits where individuals invoke international norms against the executive bodies. This trend, in turn, originates from the convergence of two factors.
First, contemporary international law, while largely retaining its feature of law between states, is designed primarily to satisfy individual needs.Footnote 24 Second, civil society has increasingly been boosting the application of international law before domestic courts. Non-governmental organizations (NGOs), indeed, often sue government bodies – and sometimes non-state actors as well – alleging that they have breached international norms protecting fundamental values such as peace, the environment, and human rights.Footnote 25
To give an account here of all the circumstances where the use of these doctrines has led courts not to apply international law would be impossible. I shall limit myself, therefore, to references to the most significant decisions from 2000 to today.
The largest group of cases concerns what is regarded by many authors as the political act par excellence: the declaration of war. The question concerning its lawfulness has arisen with particular reference to the second war in Iraq. Its outbreak, in fact, has been followed by several legal proceedings where its international (and/or constitutional) legality was challenged.
In some circumstances, the matter came up directly. It is worth recalling at this point the judgments handed down by the Queen's Bench Division in the CND case,Footnote 26 by the District Court for the District of Nebraska in Callan v. Bush Footnote 27 and by the South Korean Constitutional Court in O-Hoon Lee v. President of the Republic.Footnote 28 In each of these cases the plaintiffs sought to obtain a judicial declaration that the war in Iraq was (or would have been) contrary to international law. The courts, however, refused to be involved in this affair and considered the question non-justiciable.
In others, the international illegality or otherwise of the war in Iraq was only indirectly relevant. In the Watada trial, for instance, a US official who refused to take part in ‘Operation Iraqi Freedom’ attempted to defend himself from the charge of desertion by affirming that this military operation amounted to a crime of aggression, forbidden by a peremptory norm of international law.Footnote 29 Another example is provided by the Comité contre la guerre en Irak case, discussed before the French Conseil d'Etat, where some pacifist organizations sought the annulment of the decision of the minister of defence to grant the use of French airspace to the Anglo-US aircraft deployed in the Second Gulf War.Footnote 30 Although the plaintiffs did not directly attack the declaration of war, the courts nonetheless preferred to abstain.
The non-justiciability of defence and foreign policy was affirmed in many other circumstances.
Very similar to the first group of cases are, for instance, those relating to the international legality of the nuclear military policy fostered by the government. Just as happened with regard to the war in Iraq, this question was raised either directly (R. v. Environment Agency ex parte Marchiori Footnote 31) or indirectly (In re Nuclear Weapons Footnote 32) and in both cases it was considered non-justiciable.
Moreover, judicial review was denied in relation to the choice of the method of warfare whose unlawfulness – with particular regard to the bombing of civilian targets – has been invoked either in an action for annulmentFootnote 33 or in a suit for damages.Footnote 34
Furthermore, it is worth recalling the US case law relating to the Alien Tort Statute. As is known, since the Filàrtiga caseFootnote 35 plaintiffs from all around the world have been invoking the Alien Tort Statute in order to obtain damages for human rights violations perpetrated by state and non-state actors (so-called ‘international human rights litigations’Footnote 36). Yet, when claims for compensation have been made against former US ministers and military officers, they have been rejected at the outset through recourse to the political question doctrine. This happened, for example, in Schneider et al. v. Kissinger et al.,Footnote 37Gonzalez-Vera et al. v. Kissinger et al.,Footnote 38 and Bancoult et al. v. Macnamara et al. Footnote 39
Finally, in some cases, US courts resorted to the political question doctrine in order to shirk ruling on the liability of transnational corporations for international crimes perpetrated along with foreign governments.Footnote 40 In particular, this doctrine has been called on successfully by multinational enterprises accused of having co-operated during the Second World War with the Nazi regime and its allies (see e.g. Iwanowa v. Ford Motor Co.,Footnote 41Burger Fischer v. Degussa AG,Footnote 42In re Nazi War Cases against German Defendants Litigation Footnote 43) and by a government contractor (Corrie et al. v. Caterpillar Inc.Footnote 44).
4. The pressure exerted by the international legal order
In the aforementioned decisions judicial abstention meant that courts did not apply international norms which were binding on the forum state. In this way the very rationale of the application of international law by national tribunals – that is, the need to avoid the forum state's international responsibility – was thwarted.Footnote 45
Awareness of this might lead judges to put aside the political act/question doctrine. In this respect, it is necessary to distinguish the case where a court is confronted with an international obligation owed to a single state or to a plurality of states individually considered, from the case where it is called on to honour an obligation due to the international community as a whole (erga omnes obligations) or to a group of states for the protection of a common interest (erga omnes partes obligations).
Paradoxically, courts will be more likely to set apart judicial abstention in the first case than in the second one. When one or more states have a specific interest in the fulfilment of the obligation at issue, in fact, domestic courts may be discouraged from abstaining by concern over exposing their own state to strong reactions by the injured state(s), such as the resort to countermeasures.Footnote 46 This situation is exemplified by the French Conseil d'Etat's ruling in Royaume-Uni de Grande-Bretagne et d'Irlande du Nord et Gouverneur de la colonie royale de Hong Kong v. Saniman.Footnote 47 On that occasion, the United Kingdom had challenged the French government's decision to refuse to extradite Saniman, claiming breach of the 1957 European Convention on Extradition and the 1876 Franco-British Extradition Treaty. While until then French courts had regarded the refusal of the extradition as non-justiciable,Footnote 48 the Conseil d'Etat ruled in favour of the applicants. As is clearly shown by the conclusions submitted by the Commissaire du gouvernement, Christian Vigoroux,Footnote 49 this judicial turnaround was determined by the need to ensure compliance with international duties in the field of judicial co-operation in criminal matters.Footnote 50
Since a strong reaction is all but a foregone conclusion when it comes to erga omnes or erga omnes partes obligations,Footnote 51 in these cases courts will be more prone to refrain from ruling. Nevertheless, even when there is no state entitled to act in self-help, the need to avoid the condemnation of the international community might cause judges to prevent the commission of an international wrong by the forum state. In this regard, it is worth mentioning the judgments rendered by the US Supreme Court in the so-called Guantánamo cases.Footnote 52 As is well known, in fact, despite the heavy political overtones of these cases, the Supreme Court regarded them as justiciable and upheld the enemy combatants’ procedural rights.Footnote 53 It is safe to assume that this outcome had been in some way influenced by the international blame surrounding the Bush administration's policies in the war on terrorism and the war in Iraq.Footnote 54 The most meaningful decision, in this regard, is that handed down in the Hamdan case.Footnote 55 Unlike the other rulings, in fact, in Hamdan the Supreme Court did not limit itself to assessing the lawfulness of the government action in the light of domestic law (i.e. the Uniform Code of Military JusticeFootnote 56) but considered the question also under the lens of the international law (i.e. Geneva Conventions and customary international lawFootnote 57). In so doing, US judges intended to send a clear message to the rest of the world, indicating that there are no ‘legal black holes’Footnote 58 in US jurisdiction and that international standards apply in Guantánamo Bay as well.
5. The non-justiciabilty of foreign affairs power and the EU legal order
The EU legal order may play a fundamental role in the progressive erosion of the political act/question doctrine.
The European Court of Justice has never endorsed the theories of non-justiciability applied in some member states.Footnote 59 While it has rarely lingered on the reasons for this refusal, this aspect has been thoroughly dealt with by Advocates General. Particularly helpful, in this regard, are the opinions submitted by Advocates General Darmon and Poiares Maduro, in Maclaine Watson Footnote 60 and Kadi Footnote 61 respectively.
In the first case, an agency brokerage sought damages from the European Community, claiming that it was injured by the latter's conduct in regard to the negotiation, entry into force, and implementation of the Sixth International Tin Agreement. The defendants asked the Court to hold the suit inadmissible because it concerned the international activity of Community institutions. According to them, this ground of inadmissibility was envisaged by a principle common to the laws of the member states. In its conclusions, Darmon tackled this issue with great precision, carrying out a detailed comparative analysis on the justiciability of foreign policy acts in each member state.Footnote 62 In the light of this discussion, the Advocate General concluded that the defendants’ argument was a ‘manifest overstatement’Footnote 63 and urged the Court not to adopt a concept analogous to that of ‘acts of government’.Footnote 64 Unfortunately, the Court did not have the opportunity to rule on this case because the action was later given up by the plaintiff.
In the historic Kadi case, applicants pleaded for the annulment of EC regulations implementing the UN Security Council targeted sanctions. The Council, the Commission, and the United Kingdom invoked the political question doctrine and argued that the Court should have refrained from ruling on the case.Footnote 65 Advocate General Poiares Maduro bluntly rejected these arguments:
The implication that the present case concerns a ‘political question’, in respect of which even the most humble degree of judicial interference would be inappropriate, is, in my view, untenable. The claim that a measure is necessary for the maintenance of international peace and security cannot operate so as to silence the general principles of Community law and deprive individuals of their fundamental rights.Footnote 66
This approach, as is well known, has been faithfully followed – although with less emphatic overtones – by the European Court of Justice (ECJ).Footnote 67
It can be affirmed, therefore, that in the EU legal order the principle of the rule of law is guaranteed without exception. This could have considerable backlashes on the scope of the political act/question doctrine. On the one hand, in fact, according to the ECJ's case law, individuals who have suffered the infringement by a national authority of a right guaranteed by Community law are entitled to a judicial remedy;Footnote 68 hence, when it comes to the breach of an EU norm, national courts are obliged to put aside domestic doctrines of abstention and to rule on the merits. On the other hand, the ECJ might directly pronounce itself on the legality of a political act if called upon to decide on a preliminary ruling concerning its conformity to the EU law.
An important test of the EU legal order's ability to erode the scope of judicial abstention will concern the national measures implementing UN Security Council resolutions. Both in FrenchFootnote 69 and ItalianFootnote 70 case law these measures are regarded as not amenable to judicial review.
6. The prudential reasons underlying judicial abstention in foreign affairs matters
It has been authoritatively demonstrated that theories of judicial abstention are lacking constitutional foundation.Footnote 71 Furthermore, I have tried to argue that these doctrines are subject to progressive downsizing due to the pressure exerted by the international as well as the EU legal order. These arguments, however, do not exhaust the question. Judicial silence, in fact, stems less from a normative command than from prudential reasons.Footnote 72 With regard to disputes relating to international matters, in particular, it is possible to find three main concerns underlying judicial abstention.
First, there is the anxiety not to hinder government action in the international arena. In this field, it is believed, the executive must make quick and delicate choices which cannot undergo judicial review.Footnote 73
Second, there is the need to avoid the manipulation of the judiciary by the world of politics. It is not uncommon, in fact, for political movements to conceive resorting to courts as a means to be employed along with the traditional tools of political struggle.Footnote 74 At the outbreak of the wars in the former Yugoslavia, Afghanistan, and Iraq, for instance, demonstrations for peace were accompanied by legal action aiming at a judicial declaration of their illegality. The same goes for the several cases where tribunals were called on to rule on the unlawfulness of the possession of nuclear weapons. This trend cannot be welcomed as such with favour. In democratic regimes, the judiciary is not a means of political struggle but must limit itself to protecting individual rights by applying the law.
Third, and finally, there is the demand to ensure that in international relations the state speaks with one voice, namely that of the executive.Footnote 75 This need is particularly acute in those areas where there is the risk that the position taken by courts in the context of a domestic proceeding contrasts with the stance adopted by the executive in the international order (e.g. invalidity and termination of treaties, recognition of states, and so on).
It is hard to question, in general, these concerns. Still, it is not clear why they must necessarily lead to a complete waiver of the rule of law. A comparative analysis of judicial practice – even from countries where the abstentionist paradigm is adopted – shows that non-justiciability doctrines are not the only way to prevent institutional clashes between judiciary and executive. These clashes, indeed, could also be avoided if courts conformed to some guidelines which I shall try to illustrate in the following paragraphs.
7. How to avoid institutional clashes between judiciary and executive
7.1. Replacing non-justiciability doctrines with an articulated theory of governmental discretionary power
As underlined several years ago by French scholarship, in the case of dismissal of the non-justiciability doctrines, the freedom needed by the executive in some areas (including defence and foreign affairs) may be otherwise assured by developing a comprehensive theory of discretionary power.Footnote 76 The differences characterizing the concept of ‘discretionary power’ in each legal system impede a thorough discussion of the issue. However, it is possible to draw – even in the light of the existing case law – three general principles.
First, when government action is not governed by human rights norms, the courts’ scrutiny must be limited to a marginal control, namely a control concerning the absence of bad faith or gross negligence in the executive's conduct. This approach has been endorsed, for instance, by the British Court of Appeals (Civil Division) with regard to the failed exercise by the British government of diplomatic protection in favour of its citizens (and long-term residents) detained in Guantánamo.Footnote 77
Second, when the executive is constrained by human rights norms (including humanitarian norms), courts must verify whether the infringement of individual rights is justified in the light of the pursuit of a public interest (or of military necessity) by resorting to the proportionality rule. It is worth recalling, in this respect, the case law of the Israeli Supreme Court. The continuing occupation of the Gaza Strip and the employment of the army in the fight against terrorism determined the bringing of several lawsuits disputing the respect of human rights and humanitarian law by the Israeli Defense Force.Footnote 78 In each of its judgments the Supreme Court carefully balanced human rights and national interest in order to avoid, on the one side, the protection of the former leading to ‘a national suicide’Footnote 79 and, on the other, the need to safeguard national security turning into an unlimited licence to harm the individual.Footnote 80 Similar examples may be drawn from BritishFootnote 81 and USFootnote 82 case law, as well as from that of the ECJ.Footnote 83
Third, when the executive allegedly violated human rights norms which suffer no exception (e.g. those forbidding acts of torture), the judge's role is limited to ascertaining whether this violation occurred. If it occurred, courts have no alternative but to declare the unlawfulness of the government conduct.Footnote 84 It is helpful to mention, again, Israeli case law. The Supreme Court held that the violent interrogation of a suspected terrorist is not lawful, even if doing so may save human life by preventing impending terrorist acts.Footnote 85 Dealing with the knock-on effects on national security of this ruling, Judge Barak explained,
We are aware that this decision does not make it easier to deal with that reality. This is the fate of democracy, as not all means are acceptable to it, and not all methods employed by its enemies are open to it. Sometimes, a democracy must fight with one hand tied behind its back.Footnote 86
7.2. Filtering ‘political’ suits through the standing requisite and a correct application of international law
Dismissing a political suit as non-justiciable is not the only way to prevent courts from being ‘politicized’. An effective filter against non-genuine lawsuits can be applied by judges, first, through a rigorous assessment of the plaintiffs’ standing and, second, by a correct appraisal of the substantive content of the international norm invoked.
With regard to the first method, it should be noted that several norms of contemporary international law, while promoting the protection of values common to the whole of mankind, still keep a traditional inter-state structure. Accordingly, compliance with these norms may be claimed only by states (or, if it be the case, by international organizations).Footnote 87 A classic example is the norm prohibiting the use of armed force. No doubt every individual benefits, ultimately, from the maintenance of peace in international relations. This does not imply, however, that international law recognizes an individual right to peace whose infringement may be claimed before domestic courts. The only right that international law acknowledges, in fact, is the state's right ‘not to be attacked’. Therefore a lawsuit aiming to obtain a ruling on the international unlawfulness of a declaration of war should be rejected, because applicants lack locus standi and there is no need to resort to non-justiciability.Footnote 88 This approach has been endorsed by the Dutch Supreme Court,Footnote 89 the Nagoya High Court (Japan),Footnote 90 and the Danish Supreme Court,Footnote 91 as well as by the minority of South Korea's Constitutional Court in the aforementioned O-Hoon Lee case.Footnote 92 Moreover, in the above-quoted Callan case the District Court of Nebraska identified the plaintiff's lack of standing as an alternative ground for dismissal.Footnote 93
The question becomes different, however, when national legal systems provide the individual with the right to invoke the violation of such a norm.Footnote 94 This can occur, for instance, when domestic law acknowledges a soldier's right not to obey an unlawful order. In a judgment recently rendered by the German Federal Administrative Court (Bundesverwaltungsgericht),Footnote 95 for instance, the refusal of a German officer to contribute to the military operations in Iraq has been held to be a legitimate conscientious objection, protected by Article 4(1) Grundgesetz (‘Freedom of . . . conscience . . . shall be inviolable’), since the war in Iraq raised serious doubts in terms of international law.Footnote 96
As to the second point, it is necessary to carry out a preliminary observation. Despite the indisputable role played by legislature and judiciary, national executives still perform a pivotal function in the creation of international law, either through the negotiation and conclusion of treaties or by the formation of practice and opinio juris required for the development of customary international law. Contemporary international law, therefore, may still be described as the set of limits which states (and chiefly their executives) willingly accept in order to achieve certain common interests.Footnote 97 In other words, it imposes duties that national governments are able and intend to honour. Hence it is unlikely that a proper administration of international law would be detrimental to government interests. In this regard it could be helpful to recall the outcomes of the lawsuits alleging the non-compliance with international law of the policy of nuclear deterrence adopted by some Western countries. These suits, when deemed justiciable, have always been rejected on the merits. In the famous 1983 Pershing II case,Footnote 98 for example, the Bundesverfassungsgericht was called on to judge whether the government's decision to authorize the installation of Pershing II and Cruise nuclear missiles on German territory was compatible with international law. According to the applicants, after the Second World War a customary norm had evolved forbidding the possession and use of nuclear weapons. The German Constitutional Court observed that the main nuclear powers of the time (the Soviet Union, the United States, and the United Kingdom) still retained their nuclear arsenal and concluded that such a rule could not have been formed, lacking both diuturnitas and opinio juris.Footnote 99
In sum, some of the most politically loaded suits promoted by individual activists or NGOs are not grounded in international law as it really is, but on international law as the plaintiffs wish it to be. Accordingly, a judge wishing not to be lured into the political thicket must limit him- or herself to applying international norms as they really are, locking the door to the creation of new individual (or collective) rights or to an evolutive interpretation of pre-existing international standards. By so doing, courts will never be in a position to impinge on sensitive interests in the foreign affairs area.
7.3. Reconciling judicial intervention in foreign affairs with the principle of ‘speak with one voice’
Courts have already worked out ways of reconciling the principle of ‘speak with one voice’ with the judicial duty to interpret and apply international law.
In this regard, the domestic case law relating to invalidity and termination of treaties is illuminating. A study conducted in the late 1980sFootnote 100 – but whose results can be still considered validFootnote 101 – has revealed that, in this matter, courts act according to two principles.
First, whenever a tribunal is called on to enforce a treaty, it has the power and the duty to determine whether the latter is valid and in force, but the effects of this assessment will be limited to the specific case.Footnote 102 Second, the executive decision to terminate a treaty manifests, at international level, the state's intent ‘to free itself once and for all from its contractual commitment’.Footnote 103 Accordingly, the judges of that state will no longer be able to give effect to the denounced treaty.Footnote 104
In this way, the principle of ‘speak with one voice’ does not automatically translate into judicial silence but rather calls for a more equitable co-ordination of the tasks (and the powers) of the courts and those of the government.
This case law provides us with two indications of a general character. On the one hand, it suggests that judicial decisions on these issues have effects limited to the specific case and cannot determine an intrusion on the prerogatives of the government in foreign affairs. This principle is likely to find application in areas other than the invalidity and termination of treaties. Consider the case where a court needs to verify the statehood of an entity in order to apply the rules on state immunity. If the court holds this entity to be a state because it effectively and independently governs a territorial community, this does not mean that the former is recognizing the latter. The recognition of states remains the exclusive prerogative of the government while the court's ruling will affect only the dispute at issue.
On the other hand, it clarifies that when governments express the will of their states through lawful acts yielding legal effects in the international legal order (e.g. the formal denunciation of a treaty), courts of these states will be obliged to conform. Consider again the government decision to recognize a foreign state. The effect of estoppel flowing from that decisionFootnote 105 constrains all the recognizing state's legal operators, including its own judges. The latter, in other words, will be bound by the recognition given by their government. The same cannot be said, however, with regard to the decision not to recognize a state, which, as is well established,Footnote 106 has no effect at the international level.
8. Conclusions
In First National City Bank v. Banco Nacional de Cuba, Justice Powell recognized that ‘[u]ntil international tribunals command a wider constituency, the courts of various countries afford the best means for the development of a respected body of international law.’Footnote 107 The persisting inability of international tribunals to ensure a centralized enforcement of international law, on the one hand, and the increasing application of international law by domestic courts, on the other hand, prove this statement to have been somewhat prophetic.
Yet the fulfilment of this process is substantially hindered by judicial application of the non-justiciability doctrines. Authoritative (international and public law) scholarship has already shown that these doctrines lack stable constitutional foundations. In the present work I have tried to establish that when it comes to the application of international and community norms these doctrines undergo progressive erosion due to the pressure exerted by international as well as EU legal orders.
I have attempted to demonstrate, moreover, that the prudential concerns accompanying judicial intervention in international matters may be smoothed without resorting to judicial abstention but rather by assuring that judicial review does not overstep certain limits.
These considerations support a definitive abandonment of the political act/question doctrine. Such an evolution, of course, will inevitably produce different effects according to the characteristics of each legal system. In any case, it would represent a decisive step in the direction shown, some forty years ago, by Justice Powell.