Introduction
In the last decade, UK law on vicarious liability has undergone rapid development. Much academic commentary about this development has been negative in tenor. Concerns have been raised that the doctrine's scope has become uncertain and that its application has resulted in bad decisions.Footnote 1 Although certainty might be a necessary casualty of changing laws, an enduring worry about vicarious liability is that the uncertainty surrounding the doctrine reflects the absence of proper justifications for it.Footnote 2 Of course, it is clear that the doctrine allocates responsibility for worker wrongs in order to compensate tort claimants and that compensated claimants are likely to feel a sense of vindication. Academic commentators have few gripes about the pursuit of such aims. However, tort law is ‘two-sided’Footnote 3 in nature so that reasoning about liability rules must comprehend the position not only of claimants but of defendants as well. This has been the root problem in justifying vicarious liability, because the reasons for its imposition upon employers have failed to convince.
This paper argues that, while a liberal notion of agency provides good justification for the vicarious liability of businesses operated by owner-managers who have personal relations with workers and of other organisations with analogous structures, it falls short in relation to medium- and large-size organisations. These ‘bureaucratic’ organisations feature multiple levels of management, ‘chains of command’, and variegated decision-making procedures. Senior management directives imposed on workers, without doubt, conclusively establish the existence of ‘authority’, but authority becomes more difficult to prove when decision-making is devolved and workers are imbued with decision-making discretion. Of course, scholars and judges have attempted to characterise the vicarious liability of bureaucratic organisations as a form of enterprise liability. This entails the imposition of liability upon organisations undertaking risky business activities for their own benefit, and from which it is deemed ‘fair’ to exact compensation for injuries. However, enterprise liability explains only a sub-set of cases. It suffers from the substantial flaws of being inapplicable to non-profit employers, such as public authorities and charities, and, when viewed as a ‘licence fee’ upon organisational activities, of actually tolerating employee wrongdoing.Footnote 4
This paper isolates elements of judicial reasoning found in modern cases of organisational vicarious liability. From factors including structure, hierarchy, and control, it constructs a model of the ‘deterrable organisation’Footnote 5 and demonstrates how courts might achieve reform of worker behaviour through the imposition of vicarious liability. Three themes inform the model. The first relates to strict liability, which is liability regardless of fault. The imposition of strict liability creates incentives to be proactive in setting proper standards of conduct. The second theme is about ‘delegation’. Because vicarious liability does not require proof of organisational fault, it pushes responsibility for investigations of worker wrongdoing, and for reform of conduct, onto organisations themselves. This structuring of responsibility mirrors decentred regulatory practices. The third theme relates to ‘deterrability’, which arises from organisational attributes that courts rely upon in order to reduce the frequency and seriousness of worker wrongdoing. The model hypothesises that organisations are deterrable because they can act on threats of legal liability by planning activities, devising proper standards of conduct which override individual discretion, and compelling workers to adhere to them.
Having set out a model of the deterrable organisation, the paper turns to consider scholarly concerns about deterrence reasoning, the ostensible problems being that subjects of law are not well-informed about legal rules, that they ignore incentives to comply, and that those incentives are dampened by liability insurance. Although these concerns turn out to be of modest relevance to medium- and large-size organisations, the paper assesses potential weaknesses in the deterrable organisation model and acknowledges ways in which the reform of worker behaviour might be frustrated. The conclusion is that, although organisations are deterrable, there will be insufficient deterrence unless steps are taken to reinforce the operation of the model by a more targeted use of powers to award remedies.
In constructing its argument, this paper adopts a Dworkinian interpretive approach. This widely-adopted approach to theorising about private lawFootnote 6 encompasses three stages. At the pre-interpretive stage, we identify ‘the rules and standards taken to provide the tentative content of the practice’ in question.Footnote 7 At the interpretive stage, the ‘interpreter settles on some general justification for the main elements of the practice identified at the pre-interpretive stage’.Footnote 8 This involves putting forward an ‘interpretive proposal’, which attempts to provide the best possible way of seeing the rules and standards. This way of seeing, or justification, ‘need not fit every aspect or feature of the’ rules and standards, but must fit them sufficiently so as not to constitute the invention of something new and unintended.Footnote 9 If satisfactory, the interpretive proposal should help us to understand the law better.Footnote 10 At the post-interpretive stage, the interpreter ‘adjusts’ her sense of what the rules and standards really require ‘so as better to serve the justification’ which has been proposed and assist in making the rules or standards work better.Footnote 11
1. Liberal agencyFootnote 12
Our discussion commences with the first paradigm of vicarious liability. Prior to the late seventeenth century, English courts imposed vicarious liability on the basis of what the master ‘commanded’ the servant to do.Footnote 12A In modernising the law, Lord Holt insisted upon the presence of an agency relationship between master and servant but recognised, for example in Turberville v Stamp, that implied authority would be sufficient to support liability.Footnote 13 In this, he is said to have introduced a rule of responsibility based upon ‘convenience and public policy’.Footnote 14 Within a century, vicarious liability rules became focused upon the key concept of the ‘relationship of employment’.Footnote 15 Even so, the ‘scope of employment’ was determined by examining what activities the employee was authorised to engage in.
It remains necessary to undertake this inquiry in classical vicarious liability cases because the mere fact of employment says nothing about whether the employee was acting on instruction or was off on a frolic. The normatively salient link between the owner-manager and the employee, where an act of the latter causes harm to the claimant, is the authorised activity.Footnote 16 The concept of agency used is not ‘technical’ in the sense of being premised upon agreement to act and specification of the agent's area of authority. It turns, instead, on the idea of one person ‘acting through another’ in order to fulfil her purposes.Footnote 17
In recent times, judges have moved away from the language of the older authorities, in order to accommodate a widening of ‘employer’ responsibilities so as to include activities undertaken by non-employees. Courts consider the worker's ‘field of activities’ and their connection to the commission of the tort.Footnote 18 However, extended consideration of this approach in Bellman v Northampton Recruitment Ltd Footnote 19 reveals two important things. First, the ‘field of activities’ concept inevitably requires reference to issues of authority, because one can discern the ‘field’ only according to what the employer was intending to accomplish by engagement of workers. Secondly, the relevant notion of authority extends beyond both actual and ostensible authority, so that it comports with the traditional, liberal notion of agency.
The potential remains for the vicarious liability of small companies,Footnote 20 small partnerships,Footnote 21 and individual employers on the basis of liberal agency where there are personal relations between relevant parties. The justification applies, for example, where a worker commits a tort with a sufficient connection to a family plumbing business's field of activities because its manager has set the worker on a particular course,Footnote 22 perhaps wearing a distinctive uniform, driving a logo-emblazoned van,Footnote 23 and acting with the owner-manager's attitudes and values.Footnote 24 But the owner-manager's actual grant of authority is not definitive of the extent of the business's vicarious liability because the presence of some minimal degree of authority in the worker is likely to create expectations among counterparties as to standards to be upheld and responsibilities undertaken, and because the owner-manager must be assumed to understand the tendencies of workers to take shortcuts and exploit opportunities for self-gratification.
Although Gray is right to explain vicarious liability by reference to ideas of liberal agency, he does not see modern cases of responsibility for the acts of intentional wrongdoers, such as those involving sexual abuse of children, as being consonant with the doctrine's agential foundations.Footnote 25 This is because the worker does not act both for the employer's purposes and benefit.Footnote 26 Undoubtedly, this is true – so far as it goes. But Gray argues, further, that employers ought not to be made responsible for the commission of torts in such circumstances. Consistent with corrective justice values, he propounds the view that tort law ought to be confined either to cases of fault-based liability or those in which the employer is morally blameworthy for the commission of employee wrongs.Footnote 27 At least a couple of objections arise. First, the argument ignores tort law's two-sided nature, which necessitates that judges consider both agent actions and the interests of persons harmed by those actions in coming to decisions about liability. In tort cases, ‘the interests of victims are given at least as much weight as those of agents’.Footnote 28 Second, Gray clings to notions of fault developed in a simpler age and seeks to apply them not only to cases involving small organisations characterised by personal relations with workers, but to cases involving bureaucratic organisations too. In treating these cases alike, he elides important differences between them that ground the case for a second paradigm of vicarious liability.
2. The organisational turn in the case law
The classical rules of vicarious liability were sufficient in times of agricultural production, small-scale business, and size-limited partnerships because owner-managers interacted directly with workers. Then came the industrial revolution and the growth of bureaucratic organisations. New justifications for vicarious liability were required. Until Various Claimants v Catholic Child Welfare Society (CCWS),Footnote 29 the normatively important features of organisational vicarious liability remained unclear. The embrace of a new kind of vicarious liability in CCWS reflects the transition to a corporatised world characterised by collective action, continuous planning and operations to scale.Footnote 30 The larger size and scale of industrial, commercial, and governmental activities has led to the growth of multi-level management, featuring the indirect communication of decisions down the hierarchy of authority and/or devolved decision-making. In medium- and large-size organisations, directors and senior managers interact primarily with middle-managers and no longer see or know anything of individual workers.Footnote 31 Proving authority to act is complicated by the sharing of tasks among workers and by the existence of areas of decision-making discretion. Workers imbued with decision-making discretion might need to determine what to do after reconciling direct requests, company policies, past practices, customer expectations, and so on. In the circumstances, assignment of liability for wrongdoing on simple agency grounds frequently is ‘inadequate because most injuries result from a complicated combination of acts by various agents’ or from the exercise of discretion.Footnote 32 The difficulty in proving agency is greatest when worker actions diverge from the norm and are characterised by courts as wrongs.
The advent of bureaucratic organisations is not the only change in the world of work that has impacted upon vicarious liability rules. For decades, employers have been outsourcing work when this either is more efficiently undertaken by suppliers of specialist inputs or else helps to avoid unwanted employment responsibilities.Footnote 33
Reflecting these structural changes, the modern law of vicarious liability has become more capacious through: extension of liability to persons ‘akin to employees’ and then to certain independent contractorsFootnote 34 (explaining use of the term ‘worker’ in this paper);Footnote 35 the development of a ‘sufficient connection’ testFootnote 36 which extends responsibility for the commission of torts beyond cases of authorisation to encompass unauthorised acts occurring in broadly-conceived ‘fields of activity’;Footnote 37 and the adoption of rationales for liability aimed at addressing new organisational practices.Footnote 38 These changes have been accompanied by a greater focus on organisational capacities to coordinate work and constrain worker conduct. The result is a more complete type of organisational responsibility. But the question is how this is to be justified.
This paper aims both to model and critique organisational vicarious liability. In doing so, it focuses on how courts have justified modern developments. Their decisions have turned upon the following elements: First, courts have been right to observe that most defendants are organisations.Footnote 39 They include not just companies, but government departments, statutory authorities, partnerships, non-profit organisations, and unincorporated associations. Courts have been willing to impose liability upon unincorporated associations where they act ‘like’ corporate bodies,Footnote 40 as was the case with the Institute of Brothers in CCWS.Footnote 41 Secondly, organisations are characterised by hierarchical relationships between senior managers and individual workers.Footnote 42 Thus, in CCWS the ‘brothers were subject to … directions as to their employment [with third party schools] and the general supervision of the Provincial, their superior within that hierarchical structure’.Footnote 43 Thirdly, these hierarchical relationships provide organisations with the ability to exercise control over work.Footnote 44 More specifically, they exercise ‘managerial control’,Footnote 45 which facilitates measures to discipline workers and/or reform the ways in which they undertake work. For example, in Armes v Nottinghamshire County Council the local authority retained statutory powers of inspection, supervision, and removal with respect to children residing with approved foster parents.Footnote 46 Fourthly, courts have noted that workers frequently are an ‘integral part’ of organisations while undertaking tasks that result in wrongdoing.Footnote 47
Beyond these elements of organisation, courts rely also upon reasoning that is more philosophical in nature. Two major theories have attracted their attention. First, enterprise liability. Using their own terminology, courts find it significant that the organisation or ‘enterprise’ conducts a ‘business’ activity and ‘benefits’ from work undertaken. The benefit need not be financial in nature but can comprise anything of value to the organisation. Thus, in Cox v Ministry of Justice the prisoners’ work in the kitchen ‘form[ed] part of the operation of the prison, and [was] of direct and immediate benefit to the prison service itself’.Footnote 48 The problem is that the benefit can be obtained only through the creation or exacerbation of risks to others.Footnote 49 As such, it is ‘fair’ to impose liability on the organisation for the negative consequences of its activities.Footnote 50
Secondly, courts assert that vicarious liability is imposed upon organisations because they can ‘do something’ about workers’ conduct.Footnote 51 They embrace a deterrence rationale based on judicial ‘power to order defendants to pay damages’ and the consequent ability to ‘deter the defendant and other similarly situated actors from engaging in conduct they deem undesirable; at least insofar as the threat of damages awards affects actors’ decisions’.Footnote 52 For example, Sir Anthony Clarke MR in Gravil v Carroll stated that the imposition of vicarious liability upon a rugby club for player wrongdoing was justified by ‘deterrence of the club by bringing home the liability … so as to prevent or minimise the risk of foul play in the future’.Footnote 53 His Lordship discussed specific actions that the club could take to this end. While in other cases deterrence is not referred to by name, it is the substantive explanation for what courts seek to achieve. Thus, in Various Claimants v Wm Morrison Supermarkets plc, Justice Langstaff (at first instance) noted that an employer could design preventative systems that workers could be directed to observe.Footnote 54 Such statements tell us that courts are not indifferent to the impact of vicarious liability. It is reform of worker behaviour that they desire.
3. Existing explanations of vicarious liability
In ‘interpreting’ judicial reasoning, Dworkin urges us to search for the best way to justify it, to see it in its ‘best light’. The question arises whether enterprise liability presents organisational vicarious liability in its best light.Footnote 55 Enterprise liability has a respectable pedigree,Footnote 56 having been developed in the scholarly literature during the first half of the twentieth century, and been used as a justification for US law on products liability and vicarious liability.Footnote 57 It is concerned with ensuring that organisational defendants, such as manufacturers and large firms, cannot escape responsibility for injuries caused by profit-making activities. Beyond this basic idea, different branches of the theory encompass different – and partly conflicting – sub-goals, the main ones being: the spreading of costs of injury to consumers in the sale of goods and/or to insurers via higher premiums;Footnote 58 the internalisation by organisations of the costs of their activities, so as to ensure that the most appropriate (not excessive or damaging) levels of activity are undertaken;Footnote 59 and the deterrence of future wrongdoing.Footnote 60 Courts have not explored these different sub-goals in any depth – although they have tended to adopt the deterrence view. Indeed, until recently, courts had not even considered what an ‘enterprise’ is, fostering uncertainty about vicarious/enterprise liability's scope and explanatory power.Footnote 61
These concerns aside, enterprise liability suffers from two flaws that undercut its justificatory power and call for a new model of organisational vicarious liability. The first flaw arises from its inability to encompass organisations that do not operate pursuant to ordinary profit motives. While the owners and managers of businesses operated for profit derive personal benefits from imposing risks on others,Footnote 62 this is not the case with non-profit bodies. Those in charge of government departments, public authorities, and charities are ‘other-regarding’, and have as their primary concern the needs of third parties.Footnote 63 The ‘benefits’ of risk imposition arising from their activities accrue to third parties and not to those in charge.Footnote 64 So, whereas the imposition of risk-for-profit at the heart of enterprise liability has an exploitative quality to it, this does not characterise the activities of non-profits. The second flaw is that enterprise liability is not treated always as a theory directed towards reform of organisational activity. Indeed, some see it as little more than a ‘licence fee’ on activities which, although desirable, cause occasional injuries.Footnote 65 This treats worker wrongdoing as a matter of indifference.Footnote 66
The best that we can say about enterprise liability is that it looks in the right direction by providing an explanation of vicarious liability that is not reliant upon agency, but which takes into account the organisational status of defendants and provides support for the imposition of liability upon profit-making businesses. However, initial steps have been taken towards identifying a more comprehensive theory. Stone adverted to important internal features of large business organisations by describing them as ‘bureaucracies’, characterised by information flows, managerial control, and the ability to plan for the future. In an increasingly bureaucratic world, wrongdoing was attributable to ‘flaws in the organization's formal and informal authority structure, or in its information pathways’.Footnote 67 A potential solution was to impose ‘direct and selective constraints on how … managers work out various internal relationships’.Footnote 68 In another take on these issues, Deakin predicted that the ‘fragmentation of enterprise’ through practices such as out-sourcing would entail a move towards ‘organisational liability’.Footnote 69 He wrote also about organisational amenability to deterrence incentives and about the exercise of ‘managerial control’ to reduce risks.Footnote 70 These writings provide helpful insights into what a theory of organisational vicarious liability ought to look like.
4. Organisational vicarious liability
For present purposes, it is best to consider the justification of vicarious liability in medium- and large-size organisations by taking an initial step back from these theoretical prompts in order to consider first principles. The standard judicial refrain is that tort law (taken as a whole) has the twin aims of compensating tort victims and deterring future wrongdoing.Footnote 71 Vicarious liability fulfils the compensatory aim in an uncomplicated way. As for deterrence, the assumption is that rules of law have a positive effect on behaviour. They are predicated on legal subjects having knowledge of the rules and of the consequences of breaching them. In tort law, the deterrence argument appears to be soundest with respect to torts that provide explicit definitions of wrongdoing, such as battery and assault. This is because tort rules of this nature perform a guidance function.Footnote 72 The deterrence argument appears sound, also, with respect to negligence because courts spell out precautions for particular types of risk-taking. But what about vicarious liability, which is a rule of strict liability? Here the deterrence justification presents a puzzle because, in determining cases, courts do not formulate specific behavioural guidelines or precautions to be taken. All that they do is to state that, if a worker commits a tort in the field of employer-assigned activities, the employer will be held strictly liable for sufficiently-connected harms to third parties. Can such a rule deter wrongdoing?
Organisational vicarious liability embodies a form of ‘mediated deterrence’ because the organisation is made responsible for altering the behaviour of its workers.Footnote 73 The idea to be tested is that this is a cogent practice because organisations are ‘deterrable’ parties, vicarious liability being a means of inducing from them the development of proper standards of worker conduct. This might occur through: specific deterrence, pursuant to which organisations that have had vicarious liability awards made against them take action to prevent the future commission of torts; and/or general deterrence, whereby vicarious liability awards impact upon organisations more generally because they either fear future claims or want, simply, to be good corporate citizens.Footnote 74 Being of a forward-looking nature, vicarious liability arises irrespective of whether organisations actually take sufficient care. By eliminating any no-fault escape route, the doctrine creates ongoing incentives for organisations to prevent the commission of worker wrongs.
In modelling the deterrable organisation, three foundational themes require exploration. These concern strict liability, the delegation of standard-setting that occurs under strict liability, and the nature of organisation. After exploring these themes, the paper examines empirical evidence on deterrence and assesses the ‘blockages’ that could frustrate its goals.
(a) Strict liability
Ever since courts eschewed actual authorisation of tortious acts as a necessary predicate to vicarious liability, the doctrine has been one of strict liability. This has been a source of difficulty for theorists who believe that modern tort law is grounded in, and justified by reference to, fault.Footnote 75 In order better to understand the nature and effect of vicarious liability, it is important to explore what strict liability entails. Typical statements include Lord Hobhouse's declaration in Lister v Hesley Hall Ltd that vicarious liability is ‘strict’ because ‘there has been no actual fault on the part of the employers’,Footnote 76 and Lord Nicholls’ averment in Dubai Aluminium Co Ltd v Salaam that ‘[v]icarious liability involves the notion that, vis-à-vis third parties, the employer, although personally blameless, … is liable for the fault of another’.Footnote 77 Such statements cannot mean that vicarious liability arises only in cases of blameless employers. Indeed, contrary to what some judges and commentators assume, strict liability is not liability in the absence of fault. It is ‘liability regardless of whether the defendant engaged in conduct that breached a legally specified standard’.Footnote 78 Under strict liability, the court does not inquire into fault because this is unnecessary.Footnote 79 The vicariously liable employer's conduct might have been ‘innocent’, but that is not inevitable – as was acknowledged in Bernard v Attorney General of Jamaica, where Lord Steyn observed that there will ‘be cases of vicarious liability where employers were at fault’.Footnote 80 Indeed, Abraham asserts that vicarious liability is imposed on some types of defendant as a surrogate for findings of expected negligence.Footnote 81
One of the primary reasons for the attractiveness of vicarious liability is that it removes the need to prove fault.Footnote 82 This is helpful especially when defendants are complex organisations and claimants have no knowledge of their internal workings. Worker negligence typically involves a combination of individual slips, latent conditions, and local factors.Footnote 83 Latent conditions frequently result from senior management decisions,Footnote 84 but it can be difficult to obtain evidence of fault at this level of decision-making. Indeed, whether torts committed are accidental or intentional, it might be difficult for claimants to access information about ‘what went wrong’Footnote 85 because organisations refuse to cooperate or because it is difficult to extract salient features from the evidence. Where professional assistance is required to construct a case of organisational fault, this is likely to be costly for claimants.
Where evidence of what went wrong is available, there is still another step that a court must take in deciding whether an organisation was at fault. This is to specify the appropriate standard of care that should have been observed and to determine whether the defendant's conduct fell below it. In straightforward cases (even those involving vicarious liabilityFootnote 86), courts specify precautions that should have been taken. But this becomes more difficult as organisations become more bureaucratic. As such, another reason for imposing strict liability is that it places an onus upon organisations to do all that they can to promote proper standards of conduct and prevent worker wrongdoing.Footnote 87 This is more likely to be an effective strategy when organisations understand that they inevitably will be made liable for the consequences of worker wrongdoing.Footnote 88 Fixing them with responsibility should result in either lower activity levelsFootnote 89 or more effective precaution-taking.Footnote 90 As to the latter, vicarious liability ‘focuses energies on prevention, on systematic and proactive efforts rather than discrete reactions to specific known instances of misconduct…’.Footnote 91
(b) Co-option/delegation
Whereas fault-based rules require that claimants obtain information about the internal workings of organisations and ways of addressing risks, strict liability makes this irrelevant. Under vicarious liability, responsibility for standard-setting is ‘delegated’ to organisations themselves.Footnote 92 If organisations want to avoid liability, the onus is upon them to take action. ‘[A] strict liability standard [overcomes] the information asymmetry problem. With a strict liability standard, only the … firm need know what the [necessary] level of care is and whether the firm has met it’.Footnote 93
The cogency of delegation becomes apparent upon consideration of the parallels between it and modern regulatory practice. The context is one of a society characterised by ‘coordination problems’,Footnote 94 which arise because persons live and work together in close cooperation. This entails a high degree of interdependence within workplaces and wider communities. Interactions in these settings present significant risks of harm-doing, and a basic function of tort law is to stimulate the development of standards of conduct that mitigate risks.Footnote 95 Many view the ‘organisational transformation of society’ as presenting an appropriate means of doing this.Footnote 96 Indeed, a ‘decision concerning an organisation is … more likely than one pertaining to an individual to reverberate through the system, affecting in various ways other organisations and, through them, multitudes of individuals’.Footnote 97 Medium- and large-size organisations have important capacities for planning and coordinating the work of large numbers of people, and conduct operations on a recurring basis.Footnote 98 Tort suits against them become ‘occasions for judges … to regulate behaviour on a forward-looking basis’, thus making tort law an ‘important component of the … administrative state’.Footnote 99
The goals of regulation are similar in many ways, encompassing the proper understanding of risks of activity,Footnote 100 forward planning, and the formulation of general standards of conduct.Footnote 101 Formerly, regulation was conceived of as involving vertical relationships between regulatory agencies and subjects of regulation under the ‘command-and-control’ model. This model features legislation either prohibiting conduct outright or formulating standards for its occurrence, inspections by regulatory agencies which enforce standards through prosecutions and civil suits, and the drawing up of schedules of penalties for non-compliance.Footnote 102 The effectiveness of the command-and-control model has declined in a world of fast-changing markets,Footnote 103 high volumes of manufacture, distribution and transacting,Footnote 104 faltering regulatory agency expertise, and limited enforcement budgets.Footnote 105 Without the adoption of innovative methods of regulation, there would be large gaps in standard-setting. ‘In many cases, therefore, the regulatory choice is … whether to prevent a given activity entirely … or to rely upon market participants to set appropriate standards through the decisions they make in seeking to act in accordance with regulatory principles or rules’.Footnote 106
Modern, decentered approaches to regulation involve governmental and non-governmental actors operating at different levels, many standards being determined either by industry associations adopting codes of conduct or by individual organisations taking a systems approach to risk managementFootnote 107 and devising relevant policies and procedures.Footnote 108 Direct state intervention occurs only when private actors fail to comply with their own standards.Footnote 109 For this reason, much of the ‘governance that shapes the daily lives of most citizens today is corporate governance [rather] than state governance’.Footnote 110 This institutional arrangement complements tort law's pursuit of deterrence goals. Almost all medium- and large-size organisations are subject to elements of decentred regulation and have systems of standard-setting in place.Footnote 111 It is to these same systems and people – management, compliance personnel, lawyers and employees – that organisations turn in order to prevent worker torts. Their ‘internal monitoring capacities and sanctioning resources are harnessed on behalf of external control’.Footnote 112
(c) Organisation
We move on now to the last of our themes exploring organisational deterrence. According to the model under consideration, medium- and large-size organisations are ‘deterrable’ because they have advanced capacities to respond to tort law's demands and to implement appropriate standards of conduct. Discussion will focus here upon medium-size companies (MSCs) because they are representative of vicarious liability defendants. Let us hypothesise an MSC manufacturing several products, which has a few hundred employees whose work is coordinated through its managerial structure. The MSC operates in a network of companies, each of which specialises in activities along the chain of manufacture and distribution. At first, we assume the MSC to be a ‘high reliability organisation’ (HRO), which is self-reflective, always considering how best to respond to risks.Footnote 113 Later, in testing the durability of our model, we will relax this assumption.
Rational subjects of the law strive to adhere to legal rules on account of their law-abiding character and desire to do the right thing.Footnote 114 They are likely to be wary of the criminal law, with its prohibitions designed to protect important public interests. It would be hoped that they would pay just as much heed to tort rules. But the lesser stigma attached to tort liability might mean that profit-oriented companies pay heed to vicarious liability judgments only if doing so is ‘good for business’. Indeed, we shall make this assumption of our otherwise high reliability MSCFootnote 115 in order better to test the strength of the deterrability argument. Even under this assumption, constructive responses to vicarious liability judgments should be expected because they are rational and good for business. The company will want to avoid regulatory concerns, contain its financial liabilities, preserve its reputation, and focus upon core business issues.Footnote 116
The discussion proceeds by considering actions that should take place after a judgment has been given holding an MSC vicariously liable for the commission of a tort. Each of the major steps in the journey from judgment to prevention of future wrongdoing is examined. The focus is upon specific deterrence. According to Hodges, a ‘prerequisite for a deterrent effect is that actors must … have the capacity to anticipate that certain actions will cause harm and the potential for liability, and be able to take steps to avoid that harm’.Footnote 117 We will see that the deterrable organisation model suggests that deterrence results from the forward-looking nature of organisational decision-making,Footnote 118 the structures through which decisions are implemented, managerial ability to compel workers to comply with decisions, and the ability to formulate norms of behaviour for workers under organisational control.
(i) Receipt of judgment and sense-making
The immediate significance of a vicarious liability judgment will depend upon various factors, including the award's size and expected operational impact.Footnote 119 Large awards have the potential to raise alarm bells, but so too do modest awards which portend a wide sphere of liability. In the case of large awards, senior management is likely to order a review of the company's liability position as part of its risk planning process, an investigation of fault, and the drawing up of reform plans.Footnote 120 Less significant awards will be handled, initially, by in-house lawyers and/or the regulatory compliance team.Footnote 121 They will construe the judgmentFootnote 122 and prepare advice about what it entails for the company's compliance officers and middle-managers.Footnote 123 In both scenarios, a liability award acts as a ‘disturbing event’ which serves to alert the company to the existence of a dysfunction, which triggers its ‘standard operating procedures’Footnote 124 and initiates a process of deterrence.
(ii) Investigating fault and responsibility
When a court finds fault in a company, often this will indicate the need for changes to business practices. As such, a norm or standard will be formulated for future action. The company's lawyers/compliance team will inform middle-managers of the need for adherence to the new norm. In the typical case of vicarious liability, where an award of compensation is made without enquiry into fault,Footnote 125 an investigation by the company might be warranted in order to determine what went wrong. This might be conducted, in the case of intentional misconduct, by lawyers, compliance officers, and/or human resources personnel, and, in the case of accidents, by compliance officers and/or health and safety representatives. Unions might become involved.Footnote 126 Properly-trained investigators will consider whether the conditions that led to wrongdoing are systemic and likely to repeat themselves. Where repetition is likely, the organisational response might entail alterations to structures, systems, and processes.
(iii) Organisational learning and change
Company investigations into systemic problems and/or individual fault connote a learning process. The company seeks to educate itself about what has gone wrong so as to avoid future problems. Most MSCs are organised into functional units such as senior management, research and product development, production, marketing, and sales.Footnote 127 Specialisation of function in each unit usually ensures high technical expertise and substantial operational experience. A significant proportion of decision-making powers are delegated from senior management to middle managers.Footnote 128 Middle managers have oversight of limited numbers of individuals, and their main responsibility is to coordinate work.Footnote 129 But they have an implicit obligation also to ensure that operations evolve as the business environment changes. This means being open to innovation and doing things differently. Success brings greater resource to the unit. Indeed, managers who are able to improve performance will be rewarded personally. As such, they should have a natural incentive to formulate solutions to the problems which vicarious liability judgments signal. The experience of dealing with problems becomes part of corporate memory. Lessons learned are recorded in policies and operational manuals and/or invoked in training programmes.Footnote 130
(iv) Formulation of a response
Typically, the formulation of responses to legal problems involves identifying potential solutions, evaluating them, and choosing one for managerial authorisation.Footnote 131 The ability to implement initiatives applicable to large groups of people is where organisations excel. Organisations restrain, direct, and control the actions of workers through rules, policies, processes, supervision, reporting, training, and culture.Footnote 132 These ‘integration mechanisms’ are designed to orient action towards company goals, to limit individual discretion, and to embed standards of interaction. These standards promote the coordination of activity in order to achieve unity of effort and efficiencies in worker interactions.Footnote 133 As such, organisations operate as ‘regulative frameworks’.Footnote 134
Embedded standards of interaction are prominent especially in manufacturing and other sectors that require operational precision.Footnote 135 They are less prominent in the services sector and in industries undergoing rapid change, where less-structured operations prevail, decision-making authority is pushed down to those most informed of local conditions,Footnote 136 and coordination is achieved through informal processes of ‘mutual adjustment’.Footnote 137 However, even in these organisations some operational issues remain under senior management controlFootnote 138 – especially as regards compliance with criminal law, governmental regulation, and health and safety standards. HROs frequently take a prescriptive approach, in order to meet regulatory requirements, and establish clear worker responsibilities.
Fisse and Braithwaite believe that ‘it is possible for corporations to be held to different and higher standards of responsibility than individuals because of their … capacity as organisations’.Footnote 139 They have the ability to use integration mechanisms not only to promote workplace efficiency, but to reduce areas of individual discretion and prevent the commission of torts. Specific actions they might take in response to vicarious liability judgments include:
• changes in rules and procedures: senior management must design systems to counter inevitable human errors as well as person-specific behavioural tendencies spanning from laziness to predatory sexual conduct.Footnote 140 In cases where individual workers transgress and commit torts, senior management should ensure the existence of an effective system of internal discipline.Footnote 141 Disciplining workers is a necessary concomitant of the company's establishment and promotion of norms of conduct.Footnote 142 While it is not possible always to prevent wrongdoing, the mere fact that the company will pay for worker wrongs provides ongoing incentives to try;
• changes in personnel etc: the success of a company depends on hiring staff with appropriate skills and aptitudes and screening out those with unwanted traits. Many developments in vicarious liability have taken place in the context of the sexual abuse of children. Here we must digress from our manufacturing MSC in order to consider what the deterrable organisation model says about problems arising in schools and childcare organisations. Workers who commit abuse conceal their misdeeds, making it difficult to take action against them. Yet courts insist that organisations have a key role to play in preventing abuse. Precautions include background checks, psychological testing, implementation of formal procedures for undertaking risky activities, monitoring of workers, checks on vulnerable children, procedures for making complaints and investigating them, warnings and other kinds of reproach, transfer or removal from places of work, and dismissal;
• changes in lines of accountability: the company should be able effectively to monitor middle-managers with delegated powers and operations managers responsible for risky processes and the conduct of individuals.Footnote 143 In the case of simple physical processes, managers supervise personnel directly. In cases involving more sophisticated ways of working, there might be a need to educate and train workers, to introduce improved procedures, and/or reporting. Evidence suggests that, frequently, knowledge of gaps in safety standards and other problems is present before wrongs occur, but that it fails to make its way to managers.Footnote 144 This emphasises the importance of proper internal disclosure and accountability systems by which information makes its way from worksites to managers;
• changes in incentive systems: although this paper is written from an organisational/systems perspective, it is notable that economic analysts of law pay considerable attention to the use of incentives within organisations. They argue that strict liability is the best mechanism for inducing efficient levels of risky activity because it ensures that all costs of activity are absorbed by the relevant ‘enterprise’.Footnote 145 Enterprises will want to avoid risky activities that are unprofitable. Beyond this, the ‘employer's influence over advancement and compensation decisions provides an[ ] important incentive device… [A]s long as the employee values the employment relationship, these incentives can act as an effective constraint’ upon employee behaviour;Footnote 146
• organisational culture: in addition to the creation of formal standards and the operation of group dynamics, organisations seek positively to influence worker conduct through ‘organisational culture’. A strong culture ensures that managers and workers are ‘on the same wavelength’. It subsists in shared values and understandings transmitted through recruitment and training as well as socialisation processes, including job rotation, social events, and casual conversations.Footnote 147 ‘[O]nce internalized, implicit understandings direct and coordinate employees’ behavior and cause them to internally monitor their own behavior and that of others’.Footnote 148 In this way, organisational culture reinforces perceptions that participants are pursuing common goals, which encourages them to adhere to rules and procedures, and strengthens group dynamics;
• changes in industry partnerships: often companies work in networks,Footnote 149 which are contract-based agreements for the supply of goods and services. These arrangements might be implemented for reasons related to the availability of know-how and/or efficiency of operations. Sometimes, however, the motivation for entering into network agreements is to escape responsibility for employment obligations and this ‘benefit’ has resulted in widespread outsourcing and offshoring. Despite the contractual nature of networking agreements, an MSC might be in ‘control’ of industry partners dependent on it for business.Footnote 150 It might be able to influence standards adopted by network partners through contracting and supervision processes.Footnote 151 Widening the net of vicarious liability so as to include some responsibility for the torts of independent contractors could lead to changes in contracting relationships which improve standards and reduce worker wrongdoing.
(v) Internal transmission: managerial authority
A chart of managerial responsibility outlines where individuals are placed within the MSC's decision-making and command structure.Footnote 152 Decisions run down the chain of command, creating a managerial ability not only to coordinate action but to impose decisions upon the unwilling. Assuming that senior management desires change, it can achieve this by using its authority to alter rules, policies, processes, and so on.Footnote 153 In the usual case, there is no need to exercise authority in a heavy-handed way because subordinates understand that they cannot make their own, personal choices, and must comply with management initiatives.Footnote 154 Indeed, a positive organisational culture will smooth the way to compliance. In our hypothetical MSC, the Chief Executive Officer and board of directors are at the managerial apex. They set the company's policy direction with the advice of senior managers, experts, and technicians. Given that our MSC manufactures several products, it is likely to have multiple functional units that align product-types and markets.Footnote 155 The middle-managers leading these units will adopt the integration mechanisms best suited to achieve change and/or reduce individual worker discretion.Footnote 156
(vi) External transmissions: reputation and mimicry
Even beyond ‘general deterrence’, change within one organisation has the potential to spur changes in othersFootnote 157 because they are ‘nested’ within society and experience pressures to conform to best practice. Best practice is disseminated through various channels, including professional/trade association guidelines,Footnote 158 insurer initiatives, publicity, movement of staff, and so on.Footnote 159 Scott found these mimetic processes in operation after alterations to equal opportunity and medical malpractice laws.Footnote 160 Change rippled through organisations as managers and others sought to make sense of new laws and engaged in problem-solving activities that influenced whole organisational fields.Footnote 161 This demonstrates the potential in a corporatised world for judicial signals to initiate wide change.
(vii) Relaxing the high-reliability assumption
We have now considered the steps that the ideal, profit-focused MSC should take in response to a vicarious liability judgment. As stated, the ideal is an HRO, which is self-reflective, always considering how best to respond to risks. But not all companies are HROs. As such, we should relax this assumption now and consider where gaps might arise in processes of organisational deterrence. We commence with some observations about the reality of deterrence. Judicial belief in the possibility of deterrence is a product of judges’ ‘internal’ views that laws help guide future conduct. In cases where persons fail to observe tort rules, they are subject to penalties that include injunctions and damages awards. The threat of liability ought to bring about changes in behaviour. But there is an ongoing debate about the empirical validity of the idea that tort deters.
Opportunities for deterrence are influenced by both the type of tort (doctrine) in issue and the type of defendant. As noted, some torts offer more guidance than others. Definitional torts are more helpful than is negligence. Furthermore, it would appear that industrial and other recurring activities are more amenable to deterrence because defects usually are capable of ‘technical’ fixes. By contrast, the activities of sexual predators are problematic, given the vagaries of individual preferences and motivations to act.Footnote 162 Yet, tort law does not operate in a vacuum. It is one of a range of mechanisms by which the state seeks to shape conduct. Tort law has a role in reinforcing the criminal and regulatory law and can make a difference to outcomes – given the ways in which organisations, such as schools and councils arranging foster care, can act to prevent abuse, and given anecdotal evidence of the ways in which they have reacted to liability ‘scares’ in the past.
Again, tort law's efficacy as a deterrent will depend upon who the defendants are. Individuals are prone to indiscretions and lapses that cannot be eliminated completely. Organisations and professional persons are more likely to act in rational waysFootnote 163 and should be more easily deterred by tort rules.Footnote 164 They have access to legal advice, professional association guidance (in some cases, mandatory standards are imposed),Footnote 165 and training opportunities. Indeed, it would appear that most employer organisations know of their vicarious liability for worker wrongs.Footnote 166 Greater difficulty might lie in ascertaining the details of the torts for which they could be held liable. But even here, they would have a reasonable understanding that worker activities that endanger safety and wellbeing can be subject to claims. And organisations have the capacity to bring about changes in worker behaviour.
But what does the evidence tell us about the reality of deterrence? The evidence is not entirely helpful. Many shortcomings boil down to a lack of meaningful data, to the operation of overlapping rules in criminal, regulatory and and tort law, and to problems in proving relationships of cause (rule or no rule) and effect (wrong or no wrong).Footnote 167 In this way, testing of hypotheses about deterrence must be undertaken by using surrogate experimentation. ‘Evidence’ from surrogate testing is tentative, open to refutation, and frequently unreliable. Having said as much, the evidence from meta-studies is that regulatory/tort law does deter, if only modestly,Footnote 168 and that the effect is greatest upon governmental agenciesFootnote 169 and larger companies.Footnote 170 Moreover, deterrence is more likely to be realised with respect to organisations that have been subject to legal actions themselves (specific deterrence) than with respect to those that simply learn from the experience of others (general deterrence).Footnote 171 Larger companies especially are compliant with regulatory/tort norms because they: are monitored internally through corporate governance arrangements and in-house compliance unitsFootnote 172 and externally by stakeholders such as credit-rating agencies and corporate advisory firms;Footnote 173 have a community ‘presence’ and must be mindful of their reputations;Footnote 174 and have the financial wherewithal to implement good norms of conduct.Footnote 175 Small companies are less likely to be deterred because of their lack of knowledge of what the law requires,Footnote 176 lower financial margins,Footnote 177 and tendency to do the minimum necessary to comply with legal obligations.Footnote 178
These findings support the viability of the deterrable organisation model, which concentrates upon ‘bureaucratic’ middle- and large-size entities. But this is not to say that deterrence processes are as effective as the model would assume. What are the problems? We consider here the potential ‘bottlenecks’ and ‘choke points’ in organisational responses to vicarious liability awards.Footnote 179 Responses to deterrence imperatives might be compromised by one or more of the following problems:
• senior managers do not always have either the time or ability to focus upon all operational issues. They must set priorities, as must other organisational personnel, so that responding to vicarious liability judgments might not be treated as especially important;Footnote 180
• senior managers who accept the need for reform might determine that the costs of change will be high and that no commitment should be made to it either because resources are not available, or because alternative ‘business cases’ for the use of funds are more attractive. This type of problem will be acute among organisations in the vicinity of insolvency;Footnote 181
• even if adequate resources are available, organisational staff might not have information required for good decision-making. They might be unable to make sense of vicarious liability judgments or analyse adequately problems affecting their organisations. Indeed, Simon believed such problems to be endemic, leading to his insight that decision-makers suffer from ‘bounded rationality’. However, he believed also that organisations can overcome individual shortcomings;Footnote 182
• even where correct prognoses are made in response to vicarious liability judgments, the forces of inertia might be strong. These might be grounded, for example, in established practices or vested interests;Footnote 183 and
• organisations might try to dodge responsibility for torts by outsourcing work.Footnote 184 The recent widening of vicarious liability so as to create liability for the torts of non-employees – who might be independent contractorsFootnote 185 – is likely to reduce this temptation.
These bottlenecks and choke points need to be addressed and something more will be said about this issue momentarily. But before doing so, we should deal briefly with another objection to deterrence reasoning, which is that insurance ‘cushions’ tort's deterrent effect.Footnote 186 Several responses can be made to this claim. First, following a government austerity drive, many public authorities and state-owned enterprises have reduced their reliance upon commercial insurance and/or have become self-insurers.Footnote 187 Secondly, many companies are insured by ‘captive insurers’ in the same corporate group, these groups being ‘self-insurers’.Footnote 188 Thirdly, organisations with commercial insurance have many reasons to be concerned about their exposure to tort liabilities. Insurers might insist upon risk-management regimes or monitor their conduct.Footnote 189 Their agreements with assureds impose obligations of care.Footnote 190 Excess clauses operate to align the interests of insurers and assureds,Footnote 191 insured amounts being subject to claims limits so that there is a risk that assureds will need to make contributions, and employers found vicariously liable for the commission of torts face reputational damage in the eyes of employees and customers.Footnote 192 Fourthly, insurers undertake educative functions to increase standards of safety, health, and so on, and to reduce the number of claims made. For these reasons, the supposed ‘cushioning’ effect of insurance is over-played and cannot be equated with a smothering of deterrence.
5. Prescriptions
There is always ‘slippage’ in the space between law and compliance. Even so, findings from the empirical literature on deterrence suggest that the deterrable organisation model is likely to need bolstering in order to ensure that organisations take effective action to prevent the commission of worker wrongs. Here we move from the interpretive stage of our consideration of vicarious liability to the post-interpretive stage. This means making prescriptions for improvements to legal practices.
A first prescription affirms the wisdom of widening the net of vicarious liability so as to encompass some non-employees. This ought to be encouraged because it is likely to lead to a renewed sense of responsibility in organisations for wrongdoing which occurs in connection to their activities. Indeed, Arlen and McLeod argue in favour of extending vicarious liability to independent contractors in order to avoid the inherent subsidy which arises when organisations use thinly-capitalised independent contractors to undertake risky work. Such independent contractors operate on the premise of low expected tort liabilities (‘low’ because they will be unable to pay more than nominal sums), which enables them to charge less for their work.Footnote 193 This leads to moral hazard and excessive risk-creation. Arlen and McLeod's analysis supports ‘expanding the reach of entity-level liability to certain organisations which hire independent contractors’.Footnote 194 The key issue in the imposition of vicarious liability is whether ‘an organisation could have structured its relationship with the agent to allow it to influence the agent's behaviour’.Footnote 195 Naturally enough, courts must not go too far in diverting responsibility from independent contractors to deterrable organisations for fear that this would dissuade the latter from using outside experts when necessaryFootnote 196 or that it would create responsibility where control could not be exercised over independent contractor activities.Footnote 197
The second prescription entails use of the right remedies so that deterrence outcomes are maximised. Here we need to keep in mind the fact that vicarious liability is not liability without fault and that it might function as a proxy for fault. This justifies the use of remedies designed to bring about reform of conduct. Existing rules on damages can facilitate this, although there is a question about their efficacy. Where worker conduct is egregious and exemplary damages are awarded in order to punish and deter, the vicariously liable employer must pay the full award.Footnote 198 The size of the award will be calculated according to the resources available to the employer rather than to the tortfeasor.Footnote 199 This could result in very high awards in sexual abuse cases and bring tort law into line with the criminal law in terms of its deterrent potential. Moreover, where the employer is made liable in successive cases of vicarious liability, this creates an opportunity for future claimants to plead systemic negligence against the organisation itself – meaning that claimants are able to plead the commission of torts by both workers and organisation.
Beyond the ability to order payment of damages, the English High Court has several powers that could help to bring about reform of organisations and of worker conduct, including powers to issue injunctionsFootnote 200 and to make declarations. An action for vicarious liability might support the award of a prohibitory injunction against an organisation aimed at preventing the commission of future wrongs. In cases where the evidence adduced reveals lapses in organisational structures and practices, courts might be prepared to go further and grant mandatory injunctions directing organisations to carry out reforms. But courts will do so only when their terms can be made certain enough.Footnote 201 It is likely that courts would be readier to grant declaratory relief pursuant to their inherent jurisdiction,Footnote 202 framed in terms of the need for investigation of structures and practices and for reform.Footnote 203 The main limit to the grant of declaratory relief is that it must serve a real purpose in ordering legal relations between partiesFootnote 204 – which, in the present context, does not present a high hurdle.
At the moment, injunctions and declarations are used infrequently in vicarious liability cases. It might be necessary to consider further ways in which remedies could be structured so as to induce reform and to insist upon follow up, for example through progress reporting. This idea would cohere with developments in the criminal law, where there has been movement towards use of non-monetary orders against organisations so as to bring about their rehabilitation. US prosecutors make use of deferred prosecution agreements in order to induce ‘structural change’. ‘Managers can be fired, new leadership can adopt compliance programs and governance reforms, and independent monitors can review changes to policies and practices’.Footnote 205 Deferred prosecution agreement orders can be made in the UK too, for the purposes of implementing a compliance programme or making changes to an existing compliance programme relating to an organisation's policies or to the training of their employees.Footnote 206 Similar methods of bringing about change have been used occasionally in civil law, although normally at the behest of government agencies enforcing regulatory standards. For example, in In re Oil Spill by the Oil Rig “Deepwater Horizon”,Footnote 207 the US District Court made consent orders aimed at improvement of safety practices, contractor oversight, corporate governance, senior manager training, internal auditing of compliance, and external monitoring of activities. However, such orders are possible only when there is evidence of failures in organisational systems and, in the absence of actions based on systemic negligence, this might require the development of a power in courts to order preliminary investigations into such matters.
Experience from regulatory law suggests that court orders specifying the need for investigations into their structures and/or for changed practices must be subject to follow-up.Footnote 208 Mechanisms could be put in place to ensure monitoring of investigations and/or changes being implemented, which would not require the constant involvement of courts. Instead, these might involve court-appointed expertsFootnote 209 or task forces of organisational personnel.Footnote 210 In other cases, it might be appropriate for claimants to seek undertakings by companies and/or their directors that they will reform relevant operations and to either publicise measures taken or file reports in court. In the latter case, reports filed in court could be retained as records that could prove important in the future should there be further transgressions, facilitating arguments of systemic negligence.
Conclusions
Much of the classical case law on vicarious liability can be justified on the basis of liberal agency. This justification applies to cases in which owner-managers have personal relations with wrongdoing workers. Typically, such relations are found among small companies, small partnerships and individual employers. However, agency is a less cogent justification in bureaucratic organisations, in which there are multiple levels of decision-making, indirect communications to workers, and significant areas of individual discretion.
Courts have begun to offer new justifications for the imposition of vicarious liability which are relevant especially to medium- and large-size organisations. This paper assembled elements of the reasoning used in cases involving such organisations and used them to construct a model of vicarious liability – the model of the ‘deterrable organisation’. The ‘deterrability’ of bureaucratic organisations was seen to reside in their structures and processes, which can be utilised in imposing norms of good conduct upon workers. The ‘delegation’ by courts of responsibility for imposing standards upon workers to organisations themselves coheres with modern notions of decentred regulation – and makes use of the same structures, processes, and personnel.
The organisational deterrence justification of vicarious liability does not preclude reliance upon notions of liberal agency where this is evident in bureaucratic organisations – these are mutually supportive justifications for the imposition of vicarious liability upon organisations. What matters is that, for each case of vicarious liability, one or both of the justifications applies so as to signify the appropriateness of the defendant's liability. The deterrable organisation model fills a gap in justifying vicarious liability in non-agency cases.
Finally, the paper reflected upon evidence about the reality of deterrence involving bureaucratic organisations. It was seen that scholars have greater faith in deterrence processes involving such organisations than they have in those involving individuals. Even so, the deterrence potential of vicarious liability could be strengthened by courts doing such things as making greater use of exemplary damages and of non-monetary orders aimed at bringing about organisational reform.