1. Introduction
The topic of the symposium to which this article contributes, ‘Kant and Marx’, may initially appear rather puzzling. Kant and Marx seem to operate in quite different registers: one was a moralist, the other was hostile to moral talk; one was a critic of feudalism, the other a foe of capitalism; one challenged despotism and proposed a state with a republican structure, the other called for the dissolution of the state; one praised obedience, the other revolution; one entertained a dualist picture of human beings as partly natural and partly non-natural entities, the other rejected any such dualism. On the other hand, there are significant similarities between these important thinkers: both had a progressive view of history as the expansion of human freedom; both praised self-determination and abhorred paternalism; both called for interpersonal and institutional arrangements in which people treated each other as ends and not merely as means; and both had a cosmopolitan view of the scope of the project of human emancipation.
In this article, I identify a fresh and fruitful way to develop insights from both philosophers. I argue that we can articulate a Kantian conception of human dignity that helps to justify typically Marxian criticisms of capitalism as involving exploitation, domination and alienation, and to develop the Marxian view of socialism as involving a combination of freedom and solidarity. Marx’s own criticisms of capitalism and his occasional remarks on socialism are in need of normative structuring, which a Kantian conception of human dignity readily provides. That conception has great intuitive appeal, and it gains further support from noticing its explanatory power regarding the critique of capitalism and the defence of socialism. Kant’s own account of dignity, on the other hand, should be modified to avoid an unnecessarily narrow view of the basis of human dignity only focused on rational freedom and an insufficient appreciation of some material and social aspects of human flourishing. Thus, a discussion of Kantian dignity and Marxian socialism will simultaneously feature revisions and criticisms of Kant’s and Marx’s contributions, besides a discovery of important ways in which they can be used to support each other and to develop our own views.
This article develops aspects of Kant’s and Marx’s work as powerful resources for a distinctive and appealing normative project, which I call Dignitarian Socialism. Kantian and Marxian insights help articulate two central ideas of this project, which I here state briefly, and develop as the article proceeds.Footnote 1
The first idea is that of the dignitarian approach, which holds that we have reason to organize social life in such a way that we respond appropriately to the valuable features of human beings that give rise to their dignity. To articulate a dignitarian approach, we need to provide an account of the following dimensions.
-
∙ Status-dignity; dignitarian norms; condition-dignity: Status-dignity is a normative standing of some entities such that agents who could affect them ought to treat them with appropriate respect and concern. I focus here on the treatment of human individuals by human agents. How exactly this respect and concern should be enacted is what dignitarian norms specify. Such norms state various negative and positive duties. When these duties are fulfilled, human beings enjoy condition-dignity. The distinction between condition-dignity and status-dignity is crucial to avoid incoherent uses of the notion of dignity – as when some people are said to lack dignity because they are treated unjustly and to be entitled to a different, better treatment because of their dignity.Footnote 2
-
∙ Basis of dignity: Human beings have status-dignity in virtue of some valuable features of them. An account of these features – the constituents of the basis of dignity – informs the articulation of dignitarian norms, as the content of those norms precisely tracks the appropriate responses to those features in various circumstances.
-
∙ Circumstances of dignity: The content of the dignitarian norms also depends on the problems they address. We can identify circumstances of dignity in which the dignitarian norms apply. These circumstances can be more or less general (and the same goes for the norms addressing them), and they include problems warranting feasible and desirable responses in which dignitarian treatment is enacted.
-
∙ Social ideals, projects, enacting dignitarian treatment: Dignitarian norms can orientate agents acting in the real world by constituting a dignitarian social ideal or project. Agents can, and should, act in such a way that they generate and sustain personal and institutional frameworks in which dignitarian treatment is enacted.
These dimensions of a dignitarian approach could of course be articulated in many ways, yielding different dignitarian conceptions. I am particularly interested in a conception that develops the idea of solidaristic empowerment, according to which we should support everyone’s autonomous pursuit of a flourishing life by affirming both negative duties not to destroy or block their valuable human capacities and positive duties to protect and enable their development and exercise. This second idea is the moral core of Dignitarian Socialism.
2. Kantian Dignity
Resources in Kant
Kant’s work provides at least seven powerful resources for articulating the dignitarian perspective.
-
(i) First, dignity is a deontic status, a normative property of human beings consisting in their being entitled to certain types of respectful and helpful treatment. Kant’s Formula of Humanity expresses the core moral idea, which underlies all duties, ethical and juridical. It enjoins you to ‘act so that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means’ (G, 4: 429).Footnote 3 We should shape our practices and institutions so that we do not treat people with malice, with indifference or by taking them as mere tools.Footnote 4 Importantly, this notion of dignity differs from other, convention-based status ones. It does not designate the fact of being seen as having certain claims within certain cultural or legal codes. Kant’s distinction between natural and positive right helps to see this point. There are natural rights which people may have even if there are no legal statutes stating them. In fact, it may be a requirement of natural right that some such legal scheme be created in order to render the various first-order natural rights more determinate and their enjoyment more secure.Footnote 5 The dignitarian status is deeper and provides critical leverage to assess conventional codes.
-
(ii) Second, Kant presents dignity as an inherent status with universal scope. This is a novel idea of human dignity, of an ‘inner worth’ (G, 4: 434) possessed by human being as such. Dignity is based in persons’ capacities for practical reasoning, including those for technical, prudential and especially moral deliberation. It is not a matter of their praiseworthy acts, their social class or their nationality. Thus, human dignity grounds universal human rights – entitlements people have against anyone who can affect them, whoever they are and wherever they are situated in social space.Footnote 6
-
(iii) Dignity is also an egalitarian status. It is held by human persons in virtue of general features of them, and not due to any social rank within existing social structures. A person with dignity ‘can measure himself on a footing of equality’ with ‘all other rational beings in the world’ (MS, 6: 435).
-
(iv) Dignity has great normative force. As an ‘unconditional, incomparable worth’, it generates rights and duties that have priority over competing considerations. Human dignity is ‘above any price’.Footnote 7 What is owed to someone in accordance with their dignity has priority over agents’ existing desires and over cultural or legal conventions.Footnote 8
-
(v) The various norms specifying how to appropriately respond to persons’ dignity have a wide site of application. Some focus on outer behaviour, others on internal attitudes; some focus on coercively enforceable acts, others on behaviour that cannot or should not be enforced externally; some specify duties attached to roles within certain institutions, others hold generally. In the systematic account of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant distinguishes between fundamental principles and principles of application (MS, 6: 216–67, 411). The fundamental requirement is to preserve and promote human beings’ rational freedom (the basis of their dignity). The Doctrine of Right articulates that requirement as it applies to agents’ external actions that are appropriately subject to coercion (MS, 6: 230–1, 237). To justify laws and policies, this doctrine deploys a Principle of Right stating that persons may only act in ways that are compatible with others being permitted to act in the same ways (MS, 6: 230) and a Social Contract Standard requiring lawgivers to only impose rules which all those subject to them could rationally accept (TP, 8: 297; EF, 8: 350–1; MS, 6: 313–15). In the case of the Doctrine of Virtue, the fundamental requirement is the categorical imperative as supreme obligation of virtue (MS, 6: 395), which is further specified through various obligatory ends shaping agents’ maxims (MS, 6: 395, 468–9).Footnote 9
-
(vi) We must distinguish between the most general and fundamental dignitarian principles and their application as specific requirements for institutions, maxims and choices. The latter address the circumstances of dignity, taking into account relevant empirical claims about human beings’ nature and social condition in more or less historically specific contexts.Footnote 10 Besides identifying occasions for their application, empirical considerations help assess the feasibility of dignitarian norms. It is warranted to believe that we can act in the ways we ought to act. But we also want to know how likely are we to succeed if we endeavour to act in those ways. Various psychological and social mechanisms may affect our eventual paths. A responsible pursuit of moral dignitarian projects that is normatively ambitious but not naïve should take empirical inquiry into these mechanisms very seriously.Footnote 11
-
(vii) Kant emphasizes the importance of freedom, praising ‘the idea of the dignity of a rational being, who obeys no law other than that which he himself at the same times gives’ (G, 4: 434). Respect for freedom is central to dignitarian treatment. Thus, support for others must proceed in such a way that the capacity for self-governance is engaged rather than circumvented or belittled. If we help others, we should contribute to their pursuit of happiness as they see it, not as we see it (so long as their plans are not immoral) (MS, 6: 454; see 388, 450). In politics, governmental action should avoid paternalism (TP, 8: 290–1, 298; MS, 6: 318).
-
(viii) Finally, and relatedly, Kant underscores the importance of the capacity for moral reasoning. He sharply distinguishes human beings’ capacities for moral, prudential and technical reasoning, taking the first to constrain the others. Moral reasoners have a distinctive dignity.Footnote 12 They can engage in introspective or intersubjective deliberation and decision-making that track impartially the good of all.
Autonomy as the capacity for moral reasoning is ‘the ground of the dignity of human nature’ (G, 4: 436). It is presupposed by the telic treatment the Formula of Humanity requires. ‘[T]he will of a rational being must always be regarded as at the same time lawgiving, since otherwise it could not be thought as an end in itself’ (G, 4: 434). The relation between appropriate treatment and autonomy is also envisioned in the Formula of the Realm of Ends of the moral law, which presents an ideal social world as ‘a systematic union of rational beings through common objective laws, that is, a realm [Reich], which can be called a realm of ends (admittedly only an ideal) because what these laws have as their purpose is just the relation of these beings to one another as ends and means’ (G, 4:434; translation amended). This formula presents an intersubjective rendering of the Formula of Autonomy based on ‘the idea of the will of every rational being as a will giving universal law’ (G, 4: 431).
Discovering on what terms others could rationally will us to treat them gives us crucial information to figure out how we should treat them. We do not treat them inappropriately if they could rationally endorse the terms on which we treat them. This point has its political articulation in the Social Contract Standard – ‘an idea of reason, which, however, has its undoubted practical reality, namely to bind every legislator to give his laws in such a way that they could have arisen from the united will of a whole people and to regard each subject, insofar as he wants to be a citizen, as if he has joined in voting for such a will’ (TP, 8: 297).
Because of the supreme importance of moral reasoning, we can give a sharp defence of rights to participate in political decision-making, and to actually shape that process in a deliberative way. We can also explain more clearly why, when identifying the conditions and goods people have a right to access, we should include those supporting agents’ autonomy besides their happiness.
Difficulties and Revisions
Kant’s views on dignity are not without problems. This section identifies three important difficulties and suggests some revisions, which develop the Kant-inspired dignitarian account in new ways.
Narrow view of the basis of dignity
Kant fails to capture all that is intrinsically valuable in human beings and makes them worthy of treatment that is respectful and helpful. According to Kant, the ground of dignity is rational agency, including the capacity to set ends and, especially, the capacity for autonomous reasoning about what is morally right (G, 4: 428–9, 434–6; KpV, 5: 87–8; MS, 6: 434–5, 442–4). But we should be more sensitive and adopt a broader view. Certain capacities for practical reasoning falling short of moral reasoning are significant in their own right. And the same is the case with sentience. We rightly pay attention to them, for example, when considering how healthcare practitioners should treat patients with severe cognitive impairments. Medical treatment here could not go very far in terms of recruiting patients’ rational endorsement, but should still respond to any level of agency that is present and be directly concerned with limiting their misery and facilitating pleasant experiences. Furthermore, a broader view is intuitively more plausible because it would enable recognition of the dignity of non-human animals and the direct duties owed to them. It is implausible to uniformly lump together every entity that is not a ‘person’ with moral agency into the ontological heap of ‘things’.Footnote 13
Insufficient recognition of the importance of well-being
As Kant says, we must respect persons’ freedom. But norms to foster their well-being are important as well, even if they must be constrained by (or at least weighted against) norms not to hamper their freedom. Kant’s use of the phrase ‘dignity’ is however tied to duties of respect for freedom, and not explicitly linked to concern regarding well-being.
Now, duties of concern regarding people’s well-being can (and I think should) be seen as part of what dignitarian norms include. A direct concern for well-being is already involved in Kant’s recognition of the positive dimension of the Formula of HumanityFootnote 14 and in his defence of duties of beneficence, which precisely focus on furthering other agents’ happiness (MS, 6: 385, 393–4, 452ff.). Additionally, Kant’s conception of the ‘highest good’, the ultimate object of morality, includes both happiness and virtue. This conception may be interpreted as saying that (a) well-being is significant as an ethical aim even though (b) it is constrained by another significant aim that has strict priority – achieving moral virtue.Footnote 15
Even if we accept Kant’s critique of paternalism in politics, we do not thereby have to dismiss the importance of happiness for political choice. When we make an autonomous collective choice, we must ask ourselves which amongst the available set of options is best. A natural way to proceed – I do not say the only one – is to choose the set that will make us happier – insofar as no injustice is thereby generated. Regarding persons as ends in themselves includes taking their happiness as significant.Footnote 16
Why should well-being matter within a dignitarian framework? My hypothesis is that well-being (at least in part) coincides with the development and exercise of the capacities that give rise to human dignity. Whether we adopt an objectivist, desire-satisfaction or hedonistic view of well-being (or some combination thereof), states of well-being are likely to feature in the conditions protected and promoted by the fulfilment of dignitarian norms. On an objectivist account (which I favour), well-being involves access to intrinsic goods, which could include the development and exercise of various valuable human capacities. Success in this development and exercise could involve the satisfaction of informed desires of the kind desire-satisfaction theories centre on. And, finally, the enjoyment that comes with these developments and exercises of capacities is of the kind a hedonistic theory might praise (and might, additionally, be highlighted by an objectivist theory that takes pleasure as one of the items in its list of goods – perhaps because of the value of the capacity of sentience or because enjoyment is constitutive of what it is to develop and exercise capacities well).
So, by adding a more explicit and positive focus on supporting people’s pursuit of their well-being to the respect and promotion of their freedom we do not only complement what Kant explicitly says about the targets of moral action and institutions. We also develop the dignitarian framework by showing how it generates concern for well-being as a dimension of appropriate responses to status-dignity. Well-being is part and parcel of dignitarian morality, not a concession it grudgingly makes to objectors. An important corollary for a theory of rights is that there is no insurmountable gap in moving from interests in well-being to rights to access it when the former concern the development and exercise of the capacities in the basis of dignity which ground the deontic space of rights itself. The capacities at the basis of dignity bridge the gap by simultaneously grounding interests in, and rights to, their development and exercise.
Now, if we accept this broader dignitarian outlook, we must see social, legal and political philosophy as asking what, if anything, might justify the coercive imposition of constraints on people’s choices regarding external action, but also how people’s well-being might justifiably be fostered. A theory of justice can, pace one of Kant’s observations, focus on needs besides choices (MS, 6: 230). Thus, I suggest that we interpret the Social Contract Standard as allowing us to draw on shareable reasons of well-being when assessing alternative social institutions, laws and policies. We do not need to rely only on the normative idea of being one’s own master and avoiding submission to the will of others (MS, 6: 238). In fact, we need to appeal to something else if we are to figure out what to choose (together) as the appropriate terms of our social life.Footnote 17 And notions of well-being linked to the development and exercise of capacities that give rise to human dignity fit the bill quite nicely. Kant already draws on considerations of this kind in his ethical doctrine. Saving the differences, it could also be done at the level of the doctrine of right. Or so a full development of the dignitarian approach that includes the ideal of solidaristic empowerment would, in my opinion, require.
Limits of independence
Kant affirms an idea of independence. He often construes it as self-determination, championing agents’ ability to determine themselves to act on the basis of what their own prudential and moral reasoning recommends rather than on the basis of unchecked inclinations (KpV, 5: 117–19, 152, 269), or the opinions and dictates of others (MS, 6: 237–8). The political expression is active citizenshipFootnote 18 and the rejection of paternalistic despotism.Footnote 19 In other cases, Kant links independence with the idea of self-reliance, of not depending on others for the satisfaction of one’s needs (except as a member of a state) (G, 4: 434; TP, 8: 294–6; MS, 6: 237–8, 314–15). This leads Kant to a qualified characterization of beneficence. The worry is that beneficence may be ‘humiliating’ to the people helped (MS, 6: 448–9, 453). It is preferable that the rich help the poor anonymously, without humbling them or making them feel that they are put under obligation. Sometimes people fail to show gratitude because they fear this would signal their dependence on those who help them, and thus their inequality and perhaps lack of dignity (MS, 6: 459).
Kant is right to praise independence as self-determination. In recognizing this independence, we can indeed ‘feel [our] own dignity’ (KpV, 5: 152). Kant is also correct to challenge paternalism, and to spot the significant interaction between conditions of economic dependence and lack of active self-determination. I am less sure that we should accept his tendency to also affirm independence as self-reliance. Self-reliance seems infeasible given our causal dependence on others to achieve most of what we value. And it seems undesirable to construe help as giving rise to humiliation, both because this would deter people from helping each other and thus from getting benefits they need, and because the practices of help could be in themselves valuable instances of telic treatment of persons. As socialists and feminists have argued after Kant, human beings are inescapably interdependent. To manage that interdependence properly, they should recognize solidarity as essential for achieving just social relations. The Kantian ideal of a realm of ends should include a combination of self-determination and solidarity in both interpersonal and institutional settings.
Perhaps these points can be reconciled through Kant’s caveat that economic reliance on others is not a problem if the relation is under the framework of equal citizenship (where the poor are helped as citizens through public services based on general taxation by the government rather than as private persons assisted by other private persons). But even at the political level, citizens will have different amounts of actual power to affect governmental decision-making (some may be more charismatic, or more intelligent, or more knowledgeable, or part of the majority, etc.). Although we should aim at equal empowerment in politics, factual inequalities will remain. A morality of solidaristic use of unequal power seems necessary.Footnote 20
A further point cuts deeper to show the limits of Kant’s idea of independence as self-determination. If we only see the contours of a just society as constituted by the constraint that it should prevent dependence as the subjection to the choice of others, then we will not be fully able to respond to the value of people’s capacities giving rise to their status-dignity. Two societies might be constructible in which nobody subjects others to their will. But one may feature more opportunities, equally distributed, for all to achieve higher levels of development and exercise of their valuable capacities. A political conception singly based in independence (such as Ripstein’s Reference Ripstein2009) cannot explain why the first is preferable. A wider notion of empowerment is needed. This idea focuses on abilities to flourish in various ways, and is a fitting target for solidaristic action and institutions. This is the kind of thought that socialists have come to add since the nineteenth century to the liberal concern with non-domination and formal equality of opportunity. A dignitarian framework can capture this move, but at the (reasonable) cost of going beyond the narrow construal of freedom as independence. This point works in cooperation with the call for more attention to the importance of well-being. And it can mobilize other resources in Kant’s work, such as his postulate concerning property rights – stating that access to material resources is necessary for effective freedom (MS, 6: 230) – as a step in an argument calling for greater empowerment to develop and exercise one’s valuable human capacities. We are already in socialist territory.
3. Marxian Socialism
Capitalism and Socialism
We can go beyond Kant in identifying the radical social consequences of equal dignity. Besides criticizing feudalism and absolutism, we can challenge capitalism. Although the idea of human dignity is the heart of his moral outlook, and he claimed that every human being has equal dignity, Kant did not identify all the radical implications of this idea for the shaping of social institutions and practices (Wood Reference Wood2008: 194–5, 323–4, n. 5). For example, although Kant claimed that in a just society people would have equal formal opportunities to compete for economic advantages instead of being inescapably destined to certain positions such as lords or serfs, or masters and slaves, he also took this society to allow for great inequalities regarding income, wealth and other economic advantages. We can go further and consider whether egalitarianism about status-dignity generates egalitarianism about access to economic advantage. A key task for a dignitarian perspective is to explore how equality regarding status-dignity should translate into various forms of condition-dignity – bundles of equal civil, political and social rights people should enjoy.
In this exploration, Marx’s work provides important insights. With these insights, we can develop the dignitarian account to include a more direct normative focus on well-being besides autonomy, a greater awareness of the social and historical conditions for the fulfilment of dignitarian norms, a fuller understanding of why and how economic life is a crucial site for dignitarian analysis, a greater recognition of the importance of positive duties of solidarity and a discovery of the phenomenon of ideology. This section discusses these insights by addressing two key Marxian themes: the critique of capitalism and the delineation of an alternative, socialist project. The Kantian dignitarian approach outlined in the previous section helps articulate these Marxian themes in original ways by providing an explicit normative structure which is not readily apparent in Marx’s texts.
In the interpretive debates about the normative underpinnings of Marx’s critique of capitalism and his advocacy for socialism, some have argued that Marx did, and others that he did not, have views about justice. I agree with Geras (Reference Geras1985) that Marx did hold quite strong views about justice even though he was not fully aware that he did so.Footnote 21 I also agree with Geras that much of Marx’s hostility to justice talk has to do with a specific (and in fact normatively fruitful) misgiving about proposals of social change that do not pay attention to feasibility considerations. Marx’s work can help us explore the material and social conditions for the feasibility and thus in part for the successful pursuit of a dignitarian project. The degree to which people succeed at becoming virtuous and happy partly depends on the social and material circumstances in which they act, and on what they do in response to them (including changing them over time). Much of our normative thinking should thus be focused on figuring out how to frame our reaction to our social and material circumstances. Interestingly, Kant’s own work on politics, law and history did not ignore them. Marxists can take this exploration further (if they also overcome a self-contradictory wholesale rejection of normative inquiry).
The dignitarianism framework can be developed to yield dignitarian socialism. Before we proceed, we should have working definitions of capitalism and socialism, the two social systems on whose contrast Marx and socialists concentrate. It comprises three key points (I state them starkly, but each involves a possible continuum between more or less capitalist or socialist societies and various combinations):
-
1. In capitalism, the bulk of the means of production – the natural and technological resources workers use to produce – are privately owned and controlled. In socialism, the means of production are socially owned and controlled.
-
2. In capitalism, production is primarily orientated towards profit, while in socialism it is primarily orientated towards the satisfaction of needs.
-
3. In capitalism, a class division develops between capitalists and workers. Capitalists own means of production and most workers do not. To survive, workers must sell their labour power (which they fully own in capitalism as well as in socialism, unlike in slave or feudal societies) to capitalists, and work under their direction for a wage. Socialism dissolves this class division.
The Critique of Capitalism
Kant does not have much to say about the relationship between capitalist employers and waged workers. He does, however, critically discuss slavery and serfdom, saying that they could not rightfully emerge contractually. A contract of slavery would be self-contradictory, as someone who becomes a slave has lost all freedom and with it any duty to keep a contract. A contract of serfdom would also be problematic, as it would generate a relationship in which there are no determinate constrains on how much the lord can get out of the serf, so that the lord could use the serf up without their consent (MS, 6: 283, 330). Kant also explicitly mentions the importance of securing formal equality of opportunity by eliminating hereditary prerogatives (TP, 8: 292). He recognizes that this is compatible with significant economic inequalities of economic advantage, including that between employers and employees, and in fact finds such inequalities unproblematic so long as they reflect the talents and industry of those involved (TP, 8: 292–3). He even claims that those not holding property (including property-less workers) may be denied the right to vote because holding property is a precondition for being one’s own master (TP, 8: 295; MS, 6: 313–15). So, Kant is far from offering a socialist analysis of economic inequality.Footnote 22 On the other hand, Kant tempers this meritocratic acceptance of inequality of condition by also allowing for provisions of governmental assistance for poor people (MS, 6: 325–7). And, quite importantly, Kant recognizes, like Marx, that many problems are to be addressed first as a matter of how the structure of a society is organized rather than as a matter of the adoption of good attitudes by isolated individuals. The following remark on beneficence is one many socialists would endorse:
Having the resources to practice such beneficence as depends on the goods of fortune is, for the most part, a result of certain beings being favored through the injustice of the government, which introduces an inequality of wealth that makes others need their beneficence. Under such circumstances, does a rich man’s help to the needy, on which he so readily prides himself as something meritorious, really deserve to be called beneficence at all? (MS, 6: 454; see KpV, 5: 155, n.)
It is not that interpersonal instances of instrumental or telic treatment are not important. It is, rather, that there are structural instances of those kinds of treatment, and the forms of social relations they involve should be given pride of place in social critique and change because of their enormous symbolic and causal significance. Let me elaborate by considering the three main socialist charges against capitalism, which concern exploitation, domination and alienation.
Exploitation
In the technical Marxian sense, the exploitation of workers consists in the extraction of their surplus labour (the part of their work that goes beyond securing their own reproduction as workers). Class societies involve exploitation. The immediate producers, the workers, engage in both necessary and surplus labour. The latter (or its product) is appropriated by the members of the dominant classes. Masters exploit slaves, lords exploit serfs and capitalists exploit waged workers.Footnote 23 Now, in ordinary language, ‘exploitation’ has a normative connotation. One common rendering is that it consists in taking unfair advantage of others. The exploitation of workers involves a morally problematic transfer of valuable resources (such as the product of surplus labour) from them to their exploiters. But what renders the transfer morally problematic? On the account that I favour, exploitation is a form of wrongful use of superior power (Goodin Reference Goodin1987). It involves taking advantage of others who are weaker by getting them to give you more than they should.
Capitalists exploit workers by using their superior bargaining power (resulting from their private control of the means of production) to extract from them more than they might (and ought to) give if they were not so vulnerable. The Kantian dignitarian account explains what’s wrong with this. One of the most evident ways in which capitalism is an affront to dignitarian ideals is that it enshrines instrumental treatment of others as a typical aspect of production and exchange. As the competitive economic agents that they are, capitalists seek profit, and show concern for the freedom and well-being of their workers only if, and to the extent that, doing so would add to their profit margin. Workers have price, not dignity, for them. This has a systemic dimension as well, as capitalists normally throw their significant weight behind political agents and processes that sustain institutional schemes that cement their privileged position by making capitalist relations of production the law of the land. Capitalist exploitation is a social pattern of reduction of some human beings to mere instruments for the self-regarding benefit of others.
Domination
It could be objected that capitalist exploitation involves no dignitarian injustice because workers freely consent to the terms on which they interact with capitalists. They are not, like slaves, dragged to the factory or the office against their will. They sign contracts. But this objection ignores that the exploitation of workers happens in tandem with their domination. Consent that is given in circumstances of profound vulnerability and power asymmetry does not authorize its outcomes.
For consider, how is it that workers acquiesce to their exploitation? How come they enter contracts in which they produce and give away objects with more value than is expressed in their wages? Is it because they want to altruistically sacrifice their own well-being to make sure that the capitalists live in luxury? According to Marx, two conditions help explain workers’ choice to enter a contract of exploitation: (1) workers in capitalism (unlike in feudalism or slave societies) own their labour power, but (2) they do not own means of production. Given their dispossession (2), workers have no reasonable alternative to using their entitlement (1) to sell their labour power to the capitalists – who do own the means of production.Footnote 24 Because of the deep background inequality of power resulting from their structural position in a capitalist economy, workers accept a pattern of economic transaction in which they submit to the direction of capitalists during the activities of production and surrender a disproportional part of their fruits.
Again, Kant helps us understand what’s wrong here. He deploys the radical idea of a human beings’ ‘innate equality, that is, independence from being bound by others to more than one can in turn bind them; hence a human being’s quality of being his own master’ (MS, 6: 237–8). This idea has important consequences for the assessment of relations of production in capitalism, as these involve domination and the dependence of workers on the discretion of capitalists’ choices at three critical junctures. The first is the one we have already considered, which concerns the labour contract. Due to their lack of control of means of production, workers must largely submit, on pain of starvation, to the terms capitalists offer them. The second concerns the day to day interactions in the workplace. Capitalists and their managers rule the activities of workers by unilaterally deciding what the workers produce and how they produce it. Although in the sphere of circulation workers and capitalists might look (misleadingly, given the first point) like equally free contractors striking fair deals, once we enter the ‘hidden abode’ of production it is clear to all sides that what exists is relationships of intense subjection of some to the will of others (Marx Reference Marx1990: 279–80). Workers effectively spend most of their waking hours doing what others dictate them to do. Third, and finally, capitalists have a disproportionate impact on the legal and political process shaping the institutional structure of the society in which they exploit workers – such as the contours of property and labour law. Even if workers manage to obtain the legal right to vote and create their own trade unions and parties (which labour movements have eventually achieved after much struggle), capitalists exert disproportionate influence via greater access to mass media, the funding of political parties, the threat of disinvestment and capital flight, and the past and prospective recruitment of state officials in lucrative jobs in their firms and lobbying agencies. At the spheres of exchange, production and in the broader political process, workers are subject to the will of capitalists in the shaping of the terms on which they work. This is an affront to their dignity as self-determining, self-mastering agents.Footnote 25
Alienation
The socialist critique of capitalism as a system of social relationships is complex. It also focuses on alienation.Footnote 26 This critical point can also be fruitfully articulated in dignitarian terms.
Marx uses the term ‘alienation’ to cover several phenomena.Footnote 27 Subjectively, alienation can appear as a sense of lack of meaning or worth in one’s life. But for Marx, alienation has an objective aspect. People may be alienated even if they do not feel alienated. The key is the mismatch between people’s existence – the way they actually live their lives – and their essence. Alienation occurs when the former fails to appropriately express the latter. More specifically, in Marx’s view, people are alienated when they do not develop and exercise their human capacities. Marx concentrates on those aspects of human nature relevant for productive activity, such as the capacities for freely chosen and creative work, which is undertaken in cooperative ways, and which meets the needs of others.Footnote 28 Workers are alienated to the extent that their ability to develop and exercise these valuable capacities at work is limited.Footnote 29 If, as seems plausible, these remarkable capacities are in the basis of dignity, then we can say that dignitarian norms are violated when workers are avoidably cornered in capitalism into work that is repetitive, stunting, toxically competitive or that engages little initiative and decision-making.
When Kant discusses happiness, and the imperatives linked to its pursuit, he says that our inquiries would have to focus on figuring out empirically what causes happiness and then (conclude that we should) go for it.Footnote 30 But this ignores that there is a substantive, non-analytic but also not merely empirical or descriptive task of identifying certain ends in life as good, or as being constitutive of the agent’s well-being. Marx’s discussion of non-alienation and self-realization can be used to fill some of this gap.Footnote 31 The Marxian view of self-realization says that people add to their well-being when they succeed at engaging in the free development and exercise of their human capacities in solidaristic cooperation with others. This view provides a partial account of the good worth plugging into our moral framework as part of the metric of advantage informing dignitarian norms.Footnote 32 What we, individually or through our institutions, should not prevent others from accessing, or should enable others to access includes, inter alia, practices in which they can develop and exercise their capacities so as to achieve self-realization. These ideas inform Marx’s characterizations of a socialist society. Self-realization would occur once the ‘realm of necessity’ and the corresponding necessary labour to secure subsistence is circumscribed and people reach also a ‘realm of freedom’ in which ‘the development of human energy which is an end in itself’ unfolds (Marx Reference Marx1991: 957–9). This realm of freedom would involve non-alienated labour. In fact, such labour, enabling the ‘all-round development of the individual’, would become their ‘prime want’.Footnote 33 Socialists call for a human emancipation featuring ‘the development of the rich individuality which is all-sided in its production as in its consumption’Footnote 34 and envision a ‘higher form of society in which the full and free development of every individual forms the ruling principle’ (Marx Reference Marx1990: 739).
The Socialist Project
How could the connection between the Kantian idea of equal dignity and the socialist views on socio-economic justice be developed? We can envision the reshaping of socio-economic relations so that they enact appropriate responses to the basis of the dignity of human beings involved in them. If people have equal dignity because of some features of them, then social relations should be shaped so that these features are given the support they deserve in each person. Consider the predicament of working people. When they are dominated, and exploited, their capacities for self-direction and for cooperating as equals with others are insufficiently respected. They are treated merely as means. And workers are not treated as ends in themselves when the economy is (avoidably) organized so that some of them do not have real opportunities to develop and express their talents for creative and meaningful production – and are thus are alienated. Even if people have different (innate or acquired) talents, and as a result their efforts could not produce as much that is meaningful to them or others, they should still have equal chances to develop and exercise their valuable capacities and benefit from the contribution of others. This is what Dignitarian Socialism would suggest. As the flip side of the dignitarian critique of capitalism, it articulates solidaristic empowerment to recommend that we reorganize society so that it enables and supports each person’s free development and exercise of their valuable human capacities.
The Abilities/Needs Principle
Marx never provided a detailed account of what a socialist society would be like. In fact, he was hostile to advancing blueprints, dismissing this as a form of paternalism (see (ii) below). It is obvious that such a society would involve a shift to the socialist aspects of organization mentioned in the contrasts stated at the start of section 3: the bulk of the means of production would be socially owned and controlled, production would primarily be aimed at need satisfaction, and the division between bourgeoisie and proletariat would disappear. These points are consistent with different specific institutional frameworks. Indeed, there is a lively contemporary debate showing that a centrally planned economy is far from the only option – for example, market socialism, the expansion of co-operatives and the extension of democratic principles to the economy offer alternatives (Wright Reference Wright2010). Given space constraints, I concentrate here on a key idea by Marx, which is that socialist organization would instantiate the slogan ‘from each according to their abilities, to each according to their needs’ (the Abilities/Needs Principle).Footnote 35
The Abilities/Needs Principle can be understood as an elaboration of the dignitarian idea of solidaristic empowerment. As I argue elsewhere (Reference Gilabert2015: 207–8), we can develop it in terms of the following demands:
-
(a) Opportunities for self-realization in work: There should be effective opportunities for productive activity involving self-realization rather than alienation. The available activities would foster the development and exercise of workers’ productive capacities, give them powers of management and enable them to cooperate. These opportunities would be effective in that mechanisms would be in place to offset morally arbitrary differences between workers that affect their accessibility. For example, excellent education would be available to all, and the workplace would be designed so that workers with different talents and bodily restrictions can thrive. These opportunities for activity involving self-realization would meet a human need to engage in it.
-
(b) Positive duties: There should be a social ethos and institutions articulating positive duties to produce to meet other people’s needs. Each should envisage some reasonable level of development and use of their powers to produce in this way.
-
(c) Securing basic needs: Some instantiations of the positive duties mentioned in (b) targeting the satisfaction of basic needs for subsistence and for being able to function as a political equal have especial urgency.
-
(d) Fair reciprocity: There should be an ethos and a scheme of distribution of access to consumption goods that recognizes a responsibility to cooperate in production on terms of fair reciprocity. Nobody should take advantage of cooperative efforts of others without making their own, similar effort if they can. Similar effort is not equivalence in output (which might depend on morally arbitrary differences in native endowments), but a matter of the proportion of contribution given one’s abilities. Those (but only those) who make an equal effort (when they can) should have equal access to consumption goods.
-
(e) Sensitivity to individual differences: Individual differences in abilities and needs are important. The assessment of levels of contribution should be mindful of differences in ability. And people should be able to pursue their well-being in ways appropriate to their singular characteristics. For example, they should be able to make their own choices concerning self-realization, consumption and leisure.
The Abilities/Needs Principle helps envision an economy of mutual affirmation amongst all producers and consumers. It takes the abilities and needs of all as the focus of negative and positive duties. As a result, it gives human dignity full recognition. Importantly, this vision combines freedom and solidarity. This, I think, is a Kantian point. Kant’s moral philosophy obviously affirms rights concerning individual and collective liberty. But it also affirms duties to contribute to the freedom and well-being of others.Footnote 36 With the refinements proposed here, the Kantian dignitarian framework can escape the scorn Marx directed at the ‘Robinsonades’ of modern political theory.Footnote 37
Self-emancipation
Some Kantians could criticize the view just outlined by saying that it risks a paternalistic imposition on workers of work they might not choose, even if it would involve self-realization. In response, notice four points. First, people are given real opportunities to engage in non-exploitative, non-dominating and non-alienating labour; they are not forced to do so. The scheme empowers workers; it does not force them into any final state. Second, the shaping of the economy would be subject to democratic authorization and contestation. Enjoying robust political liberties, people could collectively assess and reform economic arrangements of the kind proposed. Third, we should acknowledge that any society that has not completely eliminated material scarcity will need, and press, people to work. If this is so, it is only fair that they have opportunities to work in ways that engage rather than stunt their valuable capacities for free and cooperative production. Finally, the interest in the good of self-realization is linked to some of the capacities that give rise to status-dignity, and thus to the normative platform from which the paternalism objection itself draws its argumentative force. Responding to the dignity of people includes supporting their pursuit of a well-being involving the development and exercise of their valuable human capacities.
Despite popular misperceptions, Marx, and socialists inspired by him, are quite hostile to paternalism. This is partly why, for example, Marx was hostile to developing detailed recipes for how socialist transformation should proceed. He thought that ‘the emancipation of the working class must be the work of the working class itself’,Footnote 38 and that this self-emancipation would likely exhibit a radical democratic form (as his praise for the Paris Commune suggests).Footnote 39
Ideology and socialist politics
Also important for the Marxian view of politics is the critique of ideology, of attempts to shape the culture of a society so that the domination of some by others is deemed acceptable. Typical of ideologies is the presentation of the contingent as necessary, the historical as natural and the conflictive as harmonious.Footnote 40 Ideology critique has a role in dissolving these constructions. It shows that, often, what is presented as being in the general interest of all in fact only serves the particular interest of the dominant class. Interestingly, this operation can work in tandem with the Social Contract Standard. We can see socialist politics as a radical democracy in which people engage in public debate to figure out together what the idea of the social contract would really amount to for them, and decide by themselves what to do about economic justice.
Ideology critique can even target deployments of the idea of dignity in capitalism which dissociate it from solidarity. Marx in fact criticized conceptions that mischaracterize non-instrumental support for fellow human beings as involving ‘humiliation’ and ‘an offence against the dignity of man’ while condoning their treatment as commodities as ‘the justified, self-confident and self-acknowledged dignity of man incarnate’.Footnote 41 In opposition to a view of dignity that embraces possessive individualism to legitimize the social power and disproportionate benefits enjoyed by the rich, the lucky and the strong, socialists put forward a more humane project that relies on generally shareable reasons to have opportunities for the free and cooperative development and exercise of our capacities, to be offered support by others when we need it, and to give it when we can. This project charts a fitting practical horizon for the hope that human dignity always inspires.Footnote 42