Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-8gtf8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-20T23:03:44.016Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Jesse Norman, Adam Smith: What He Thought, and Why It Matters (London: Allen Lane, 2018), pp. 400, 25€ (hardcover). ISBN: 9780241328491.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 June 2020

Leonidas Montes*
Affiliation:
Universidad Adolfo Ibañez and Centro de Estudios Públicos, Santiago
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Reviews
Copyright
© The History of Economics Society 2020

The publication of Jesse Norman’s Adam Smith: What He Thought, and Why It Matters triggered a myriad of reactions in newspapers and magazines. Just to name a few: the book has received engaging and challenging articles from Deirdre McCloskey, Jean Tirole, Martin Wolf, John Kay, Arthur Herman, and Milton Ezrati, among others. And even the blurb for the book was written by Amartya Sen. But so far, I have not seen any reviews in academic journals. After sharing some impressions about this new publication, I will argue that this is neither fair nor prudent.

Let me begin with the author. Jesse Norman is a British Conservative Party politician who, within the turmoil of Brexit, has been recently appointed Paymaster General and Financial Secretary to the Treasury. Norman studied at Eton and then at Oxford University. He worked in the City at Barclays for seven years, quit in 1997 to pursue an MPhil and PhD in philosophy, and stayed in academia, teaching at University College London. In that period he co-wrote with Janan Ganesh Compassionate Conservatism (Reference Ganesh and Norman2006), and his influential The Big Society: The Anatomy of the New Politics came out in 2010. That year, after his intellectual flirtations with politics, Norman became a Member of Parliament (MP). In 2013, fully engaged in parliamentary activities, he managed to publish Edmund Burke: The First Conservative. This book, it must be said, is not only good reading; it must also be regarded as an academic accomplishment.

Great Britain has a tradition of politicians seriously engaged with the intellectual world of ideas. So it is a pleasing coincidence that Norman also wrote a book on the great philosopher and MP Edmund Burke. And now, still combining the active life of a politician with that of a serious intellectual adventurer, Norman has done the same with Adam Smith. After reading Norman’s new book, one can be sure that Norman himself also belongs to the tribe of “that unprosperous race of men commonly called men of letters” (Smith, WN I.x.c.37, p. 148).

Norman’s recent book on Adam Smith is an attempt to revisit the complexities and challenges that the father of modern economics poses. Norman reminds us that Smith, the author of Wealth of Nations (Reference Smith, Campbell and Skinner1776), is neither the prophet of laissez-faire nor the father of homo economicus or of the gospel of any one kind of economic thought. Smith is also the author of The Theory of Moral Sentiments and a philosophé and a literati with broad interests. As such, Smith has much to say about the challenges we currently face.

The book begins with Smith’s life. Although other fine biographies of Smith already exist (just think about the late and “never to be forgotten” Nicholas Phillipson and his magnificent Adam Smith: An Enlightened Life), this introductory part is engaging and serves as a necessary background for the next two parts. Part 2 is about Smith’s “Thought,” and part 3 about his “Impact.” This division, with its ten subsections, is well tied up and reads smoothly.

In Part 2 Norman dispels the five most common and recognizable myths about Smith: Das Adam Smith Problem, self-interest, Smith as pro-rich, Smith as anti-government, and Smith as economist only. Norman also argues that Wealth of Nations is a defense of the poor, a kind of “moderate” egalitarianism, as Elizabeth Anderson (Reference Anderson and Hanley2016) has recently argued. Another important aim in this part is to criticize a plain, pure, and dogmatic “Smithian libertarianism.” And when he turns to the section on economics, Norman begins with general economic equilibrium theory in order to dismiss the narrow neoclassical reading of the father of economics. Following the modern history of economic thought, the author duly praises Vernon Smith and other current conceptual and theoretical improvements. Part 2 is, in my view, well developed and academically persuasive, while also being accessible to a general reader.

Part 3 is about what we can learn from Smith today. It delves into the importance of the real Smith and his serious and persistent attack on crony capitalism. This section also deals with trade and, most importantly, describes the moral foundations of commercial society.

This book is rich in connections to diverse authors, facts, and situations. Besides, it must be acknowledged that Norman’s reading of Smith rests upon serious scholarship. The notes and the bibliography are good evidence of the latter. Specialists may dispute details here and there, but the book is a well-founded reading that deserves recognition for the undeniable quality of its content and scholarship.

Deirdre McCloskey wrote that “the British politician and philosopher Jesse Norman has written that rarest of things, a wise book accessible to the general reader” (McCloskey Reference McCloskey2018). It is wise indeed. As historians of economics, we should also be aware that promoting the ideas of great thinkers, when it is done seriously, is publicly meaningful. There is merit in making Smith’s ideas accessible for our present and future debates. And this merit is enhanced, as Adam Smith would have wished, by the process: all the questions about our current social, economic, and political challenges are developed with “propriety.”

Although Norman argues that Smith “is not the property of any one ideology or political movement” (p. 301), liberals, progressives, and classical liberals will disagree with some arguments in this book. Some might even think it is a conservative reading of Smith. However, I believe that the author gives a personal and realistic interpretation of Adam Smith with a clear intention and purpose: we should pay more attention to him. Indeed, the book is not only about Smith’s ideas but about Smith’s significance for today’s affairs.

Now let me briefly elaborate why I believe it is not prudent for academics to ignore this publication. This book not only contains an engaging narrative of the life, ideas, and relevance of the father of economics, but it is also about the times we live in. The “meaning and understanding” (Skinner Reference Skinner1969) of this book go beyond what academics engaged with intellectual history and even the importance of context might expect or even bear. Ideas are not the monopoly of the guardians of ivory castles. They are also important for our present and the future. In this sense, Norman opens up the legacy of Adam Smith for a general reader without disappointing a picky academic.

Jesse Norman concludes that, today, “in a world of uncertainty, extremism and misunderstanding, we need Adam Smith, and the wisdom to follow his thought in its full implications, now more than ever” (p. 303). Indeed, the world desperately needs enlightening about the importance of the great thinkers and their ideas for the current debate. As the philosopher politician Jesse Norman reminds us, Adam Smith is a prime candidate.

References

REFERENCES

Anderson, Elizabeth. 2016. “Adam Smith and Equality.” In Hanley, Ryan, ed., Adam Smith: His Life, Thought, and Legacy. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 157172.Google Scholar
Ganesh, Janan, and Norman, Jesse. 2006. Compassionate Conservatism: Why It Is, Why We Need It. London: Policy Exchange.Google Scholar
McCloskey, Deirdre, 2018. “Adam Smith: Father of Economics’ Review: Obvious, Simple and Wise.” Wall Street Journal, September 7.Google Scholar
Norman, Jesse. 2010. The Big Society: The Anatomy of the New Politics. Buckingham: The University of Buckingham Press.Google Scholar
Norman, Jesse. 2013. Edmund Burke: The First Conservative. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin. 1969. “Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas.” History and Theory 8 (1): 353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Adam. [1776] 1981. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Edited by Campbell, R. H. and Skinner, A. S.. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar