1. The Argument from Conservation
Space colonization has been standardly the province of science fiction. This is still true today, but less so, especially with the advent of commercial space operators like SpaceX. If we were to colonize space—that is, set up a self-sustaining (Earth-independent), hopefully permanent, colony for human life in space—an obvious target is Mars. And eventually we will be able to colonize Mars. But a further question is whether we ought to do so. Ian Stoner (Reference Stoner2017) argues that the answer is no. His argument chiefly turns on what he calls the principle of scientific conservation:
Destructive or significantly invasive investigation of an object of scientific interest is only morally permissible when (a) significantly invasive investigation does not threaten the scientific or non-scientific values instantiated in that object and (b) no adequate alternatives to significantly invasive investigation are available. (2017: 342)
At its most general, Stoner's argument goes like this:
P1. We have a pro tanto moral obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation.
P2. Colonizing Mars would violate the principle of scientific conservation.
P3. There are no countervailing and weightier moral considerations that would override our obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation in colonizing Mars.
P4. If P1 - P3, then we ought not to colonize Mars.
∴ We ought not to colonize Mars.
I contend that Stoner's argument fails. I grant P1, P2, and P4. Instead, I target P3. My thesis is this: there is a countervailing and weightier moral consideration that would override our obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation in colonizing Mars. This consideration is, of course, one point in favor of colonizing Mars. So by way of closing, I explore, in a programmatic way, how one might argue that we do in fact have an obligation to colonize Mars, along with the prospects and problems for such an argument.
Before I press on, three dialectical clarifications are in order. First, Stoner also musters a related argument for his conclusion. This is based on what he calls the tread lightly principle: “[w]hen we visit wilderness, we have a moral obligation to conduct ourselves in such a way that the impact of our presence is indistinguishable, after a suitable period of time, from counterfactual worlds in which we didn't visit that wilderness” (2017: 348). Stoner's argument from this principle is not interestingly different from his argument based on the principle of scientific conservation—both employ similar pro tanto principles—so my case against the argument for the principle of scientific conservation, if successful, will cut against this other argument as well.
Second, Stoner is right when he says that just because compelling reasons to contaminate Mars could exist does not mean we have a challenge to the pro tanto constraints asserted by the principle of scientific conservation. We need, as Stoner adds, “to identify an actual value that outweighs it” (2017: 337n4). He considers five, but I argue that the full force of one of them—namely, colonizing Mars to help ensure survival of the human species—remains underappreciated by Stoner's own analysis. So what emerges in my argument is not simply a disagreement about what is more valuable on the whole—the interests of human beings and our long-term survival versus the conservation and preservation of Mars’ natural state—but whether, and to what degree, colonization of Mars can help us survive long term.
Third, while Stoner is not explicit on this point, I assume that he takes the principle of scientific conservation to hold for perpetuity—in other words, that the principle of scientific conservation remains in force even when we have exhausted all scientific research of the object in question. In this way, for Stoner, Mars will end up like the Great Pyramids. Having been the subject of study for more than a hundred years, it is not clear how much is left to learn about the pyramids. But that does not mean that we can now turn them into hotels. This point matters, since one might wonder whether we can preserve Mars for scientific study for some period of time, and then once that time has elapsed, pursue colonization without being beholden to the principle of scientific conservation. Of course, one could go this route, but if this is all Stoner himself intends, it is hard to see how his thesis has any bite. For then what Stoner grants is permissible is what we were planning on doing all along. We are not yet technologically ready to colonize Mars. (We are only approaching being technologically ready for human beings to visit Mars.) Consequently, on the present proposal, we would start colonizing exactly when we would have anyway—in twenty-five years, say—and right up until we are ready, we can tread lightly in our scientific investigations, building on our knowledge of the past fifty years and learning all we can about Mars without violating the principle of scientific conservation.
Further evidence that Stoner believes we should never colonize Mars comes from his use of the tread lightly principle. Using this principle to argue that we ought not to colonize Mars only makes sense if Stoner intends it to show that we should never colonize Mars. After all, if such a principle were to be violated by our presence on Mars at all, it would be violated whenever our presence began. So for both of these reasons, I assume that Stoner's official thesis is that we should never colonize Mars, and that is the thesis I chiefly address. However, if Stoner's suggestion is instead that we can colonize Mars only once all possible scientific investigation has been completed, even if we are able to colonize Mars well before such investigations are completed, I am inclined to think this is wrong, too. Given certain motivations, it is permissible to colonize Mars as soon as possible.
2. Mars and Existential Risk
I begin by assuming that we have a prima facie obligation to ensure the human race's long-term survival. This assumption is not wholly innocuous, and I return to it in the conclusion. But such a claim, and the arguments produced by consideration of it, are part and parcel of Stoner's preferred practical-controversy-centered mode, which relies on beliefs about specific cases, or pre-theoretic principles, to derive (perhaps surprising) conclusions in applied ethics (2017: 335–36). I also assume (at least for now), that if we colonize Mars, we will optimize the chance of the human race surviving long term. This value—that is, the value of the human race surviving long term—is a countervailing and weightier moral consideration that overrides our obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation in colonizing Mars. By way of motivation, consider the following case I call Cure:
Suppose that a new pyramid is found by Giza in Egypt. It is, naturally enough, an object of immense scientific and archaeological curiosity. But suppose that, among its many valuable features, there lies deep within its structure, a vial of blue elixir locked in a sarcophagus. This elixir, for whatever, reason provides our best shot to cure cancer, but it will hinge on billions of dollars of future investment. Moreover, to obtain the vial, the pyramid and all its other contents must be destroyed.
I have five preliminary points to make about Cure. First, this is a case where the principle of scientific conservation is germane. The pyramid is an object of scientific interest, and its possible destruction is in question. Second, it is a case where the violation of the principle of scientific conservation can be compared against a potentially weighty moral consideration, namely the chance to cure cancer, given the paucity of other options. Third, it is a case where the intended end—curing cancer and saving present and future lives—is not guaranteed by taking the destructive action, just made significantly more likely. Fourth, destroying the pyramid would ‘only’ save a lot of lives. Cancer is not the sort of thing that is an existential threat to the human race. Nonetheless curing it would be of monumental moral importance. Finally, fifth, describing the elixir as the ‘best shot’ to cure cancer is deliberate. This leaves open that there might be other cures for cancer. Likewise, there might be other ways to promote species survival.
I take it that the following is obvious: in Cure, there is a countervailing and weightier moral consideration that would override our obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation with respect to the pyramid, one that permits us to obtain the elixir as soon as we are able. The baseline point I advance is this. If in Cure we have identified a value that overrides our obligation not to flout the principle of scientific conservation with respect to the pyramid, then we have identified a value that overrides our obligation not to flout the principle of scientific conservation in colonizing Mars: the value in optimizing the chance that the human race survives long term. In what follows I defend this claim, looking at objections by examining variations on Cure.
The first thing to note is that, in Cure, we are dealing with something that is arguably of lesser value. In Cure, we destroy the pyramid because it will save lives from cancer and our destroying the pyramid is the only way to do so. But in colonizing Mars, the idea is that we are trying not just to save lives, but also to save the human race. Cancer is, to put it mildly, serious. But it is not an existential threat to humanity. So, if the verdict in Cure is that we have identified a consideration that overrides the principle of scientific conservation, then surely in treating Mars as a hedge against existential threats we will have identified a consideration that overrides the principle of scientific conservation.
It is tempting to think that in Cure we are talking about saving current lives, whereas with Mars we are concerned with ensuring that future humans beings exist, and obligations concerning the former are not cleanly transferable to obligations concerning the latter. This is not a real difference though; we also cure cancer to prevent future people from getting it, and, depending on how things shake out, Mars could be a home for current people, too. We might imagine a case where a previously undetected asteroid threatens the planet, with only ten years to prepare. On such a scenario, colonizing Mars would be as much about saving current lives as it would be about having a home for future generations.
It is also important to note that Mars is a relatively attractive target for a second home. To see this, it helps to compare it with other potential colonization targets, like the moon. A day on Mars is roughly equivalent to one on Earth, just over twenty-four hours long. By comparison, a day on the moon is equivalent to roughly twenty-eight Earth days. This alone would make the adjustment there a challenge. Because of this relatively short day, the day-night temperature swings are less dramatic on Mars. (By comparison, the moon has on average a day-night temperature swing of 572 degrees Fahrenheit.) And a summer day on Mars can get up to 70 degrees Fahrenheit at the equator. This makes living on the surface, while by no means easy, certainly more amenable to human comfort. Mars also has an atmosphere, albeit a thin one. Still, with an atmosphere, we can get some radiation protection, which makes up somewhat for Mars’ having magnetic fields only at its southern hemisphere. An atmosphere also means we can pressurize structures using air from outside. Again by comparison, the moon has an extremely weak magnetic field and virtually no atmosphere. And, perhaps most importantly, Mars has abundant water, not just as vapor in its (thin) atmosphere, but in abundance at the poles and perhaps in ground ice, which—though not entirely uncontroversial (Dundas et al. Reference Dundas, Alfred S., Matthew, Moses P., Shane, Jim N. and Anna2017)—is evidenced by recurring slope lineae (Ojha et al. Reference Ojha, Mary Beth, Scott L., Alfred S., James J., Jennifer, Marion and Matthew2015). I belabor these points because if Mars is going to serve as a backup planet—a place to guard against existential threats—then clearly it needs to be a place on which we can exist. And while it is far from perfect, relative to the other options in the solar system, it is better on the habitability scale.
Now one might allow that Mars would provide a hedge but insist that there are better options that would not require colonization and so would present less of a risk for objects of scientific value. Stoner makes something like this claim when he says,
[t]he range of species-level threats addressed by a Mars colony is relatively narrow…. A Mars colony would not insure against large-scale threats to the solar system, such as nearby supernovae, invading extraterrestrials, or an early expansion of the sun. Nor would it insure against threats we pose to ourselves, such as war and environmental destruction. We carry these threats to ourselves everywhere we go, and we would carry them with us to Mars.
A Mars colony would only insure against externally imposed largescale environmental threats specific to Earth. A colony on Mars would be unmolested by, for example, a Chicxulub-scale asteroid or comet strike on Earth. But is a Mars colony the best way to hedge against this risk?
[N]ote that while it's relatively easy to imagine an asteroid or comet impact knocking civilization back a few hundred years, it is genuinely difficult to imagine a sapiens-extincting impact. Contra Niven, Chicxulub didn't kill the dinosaurs because they lacked a space program; it killed them because they lacked blankets (2017: 339, citations deleted, emphasis in original).Footnote 1
Stoner is right that a Mars colony would not insure against all species-level threats. And he is also technically right that the dinosaurs did not need a space program to survive Chicxulub. Yet all of this misses the point. In the case of nuclear war, it is true that such a war could happen on Mars, just like it could happen anywhere. The point though is that if a nuclear war broke out on Earth, it need not break out on Mars too. (Of course, for nuclear war to be a genuine existential threat, it would have to be global and induce a ‘nuclear winter’ scenario.) In the case of dinosaurs, the comparison is not between blankets and a space program that could harm Mars; if that were the choice, it would be an easy one. Rather, the choice is between (something like) a massive series of bunkers, filled with provisions to last thousands of years and a space program. In that case, the choice is less easy.
Stoner also seems to be assuming that colonizing Mars is the end goal and that only if Mars itself is the best option to save us against existential threats would colonizing Mars be warranted. But this assumption is false. Even if Mars is not the best hedge, it might enable us to get to places that are. This is the basic idea behind ‘bootstrapping’, and it is a core element in most visions of an interplanetary future; Mars—or some other celestial body—is a pit stop that makes getting to another target easier. There are different ways this can be done. Perhaps we will realize that Mars cannot be fully terraformed or that for some other reason it is not the right place for humanity to hang its collective hat on. This does not mean that colonizing Mars to save humanity no longer presents us with a consideration that would override our obligation not to flout the principle of scientific conservation. For it might be the case that we must colonize Mars so that we can find a true, better second home—a home that would hedge against a wider range of existential risks. For example, maybe Mars is crucial because, with its abundant water ice, it can become a propellant depot via in situ resource development. The water ice would then be used to produce rocket fuel. Such proposals are not uncommon as part of plans for intra-solar system development (Mueller et al. Reference Mueller, Tracy R., Wiley J. and Jeffrey S.2012; Musk Reference Musk2017). Mars becomes not just a colony, but a way station. Using Mars in this way may not require full-scale colonization with millions of people, but it will likely require some permanent presence, and in this way colonization runs into the same principle of scientific conservation–style worries Stoner invokes. On the other hand, those worries might be lessened, since with fewer people, there will presumably be less risk of widespread contamination and other issues.
This does, though, beckon a question of efficiency: if the idea is to use Mars largely as a propellant depot, might asteroids or shallow moons, which have gravity wells that are naturally more amenable to space travel, be more viable? (There is an inverse relationship between the depth of an object's gravity well and the energy acquired to access and escape that object.) It depends, since accessibility is not the only relevant factor. Phobos and Deimos, the moons of Mars, have shallow gravity wells and thus will fare better than Mars itself in terms of accessibility, but their overall viability as a propellant depot will also depend on their native resources, like water ice. The same comparison holds for other targets, such as closer near-Earth asteroids. Naturally, such a move would not disarm any possible appeal to the principle of scientific conservation, since these are objects of scientific interest in their own right, where a human presence might have a negative impact. Also, asteroids and the relevant moons will have significantly lower gravity and atmospheric protection from radiation than will Mars, both of which would be harmful to human inhabitants over the long term.
This point aside, I think the intuitions here are fairly clear. To see this, consider Ingredient, a variation of Cure:
Suppose that a new pyramid is found by Giza in Egypt. It is, naturally enough, an object of immense scientific and archaeological curiosity. But suppose that, among its many valuable features, there lies deep within its structure, a sarcophagus that contains an essential ingredient to what we have good reason to believe is the cure for cancer. This ingredient will not on its own cure cancer, but it is an essential component for finding what will eventually be the cure. To develop the cure and find the other ingredient will require billions of dollars of future investment and much challenging work. Moreover, to obtain this essential ingredient, the pyramid and all its other contents must be destroyed.
Unlike in Cure, in Ingredient, we would not destroy the pyramid to get the cure for cancer. We would instead do so to get something that is very important to such a cure. Nonetheless, I venture most would ultimately decide that we have found something that overrides the principle of scientific conservation and thus makes it permissible for us to destroy the pyramid. I think Ingredient parallels the bootstrapping model above in the relevant respects. We are not destroying the pyramid because the pyramid contains the cure to cancer. Likewise, on the current story, we are not colonizing Mars because colonizing Mars is itself the final end goal in our attempt to protect against existential risk. Instead, we colonize Mars because it is part—a key part—of a broader series of goals, or a stepping-stone to some further (potentially final) destination.
Now, in a sense, we should be careful not to put too much argumentative weight on this point in the present context. While bootstrapping facilitates access to more distant colonization targets, distance can make colonization more challenging. And as I discuss in greater detail below, the likelihood of success is relevant when adjudicating whether the pro tanto obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation can be overridden. Nonetheless, the basic point here still holds: if one thinks that in Ingredient we have found a consideration that overrides the principle of scientific conservation, then one should think that we have a consideration that overrides the principle of scientific conservation when it comes to colonizing Mars, even if Mars is just used for bootstrapping purposes.
Stoner (Reference Stoner2017: 340) also discusses investing in detection and redirect capabilities for near-Earth objects, along with seed banks and more robust Earth-based knowledge preservations methods, as alternatives to colonizing Mars. He suggests that it is only because such options are omitted that cost-benefit analysis favor Mars as being how we should discharge our obligation to protect the human race (340). The problem is that for Stoner's objection to stick, it would have to be the case that such solutions would be more instrumentally useful (with respect to survival) than a colony on Mars. Stoner gives us no reason to think that they would be, and it is hard to see how they could be. Near-Earth object detection capabilities are a good thing, but the scope of threats they can handle is limited, namely near-Earth objects. This is true of terrestrial-based solutions more generally, as the efficacy of things like well-stocked ‘refuges’ has been questioned (Beckstead Reference Beckstead2015). By comparison, simply in virtue of its spatial distance from Earth, a colony on Mars could hedge against more, like global pandemics. Stoner might concede that asteroid detection and other terrestrial measures are not as instrumentally useful, but given the weight of the principle of scientific conservation, it would be better on balance to opt for a solution that, while less effective with respect to safeguarding the species, does not threaten objects of scientific interest. While I doubt that Stoner would actually take this line in the end, if he did, all it would reveal is that Stoner and I disagree about the strength of the intuition favoring the principle of scientific conservation. He thinks it is quite strong. I do not. The burden, though, is clearly on Stoner to show that we ought not to colonize Mars, so a lack of consensus is a more serious problem for him than it is for me.
At the same time, since the costs of settling Mars are significant, any lack of consensus surrounding the chances that a Mars colony actually succeeds matters, too. Notice that the point here is not how Mars fairs relative to other colonization targets in the solar system. By this measure, Mars likely is our best bet. We might imagine as an alternative a large space station parked at a Lagrange point between here and the moon. This option would not run into the principle of scientific conservation, but it would be far more spatially limited than Mars, and it would arguably require continual resources from Earth, which would defeat the purpose. Another option that has been proposed is colonizing Venus via aerostat habitats, where at 30 miles above the surface, we can enjoy one atmosphere of pressure, only slightly lower gravity than Earth, and a temperate climate (see, for example, Systems Analysis and Concepts Directorate, 2018). This is all certainly a plus, but there is a big downside: Venus’ planetary resources, unlike those of Mars, are trapped in a hellish, lava-filled pressure cooker. This becomes a problem in the long term, since anything we needed would have to be brought with us or constructed at 30 miles up. But even if Mars is indeed our best colonization target, and thus our best hedge against species-level threats, it still might not be a good hedge. And that is the worry. It might simply be the best of a bad lot. Perhaps Mars is so bad a hedge that, even if it is the best hedge, violating the principle of scientific conservation by colonizing it would not be worth it.
This is an important concern. It is also somewhat difficult to assess, turning as it does on both an unsettled empirical question (just how much more likely are we to survive if we colonize) and an unsettled moral question (at just what increase in probability of success is it permissible to violate the principle of scientific conservation). But headway is possible. Consider the following further case, Risky Cure:
Suppose that a new pyramid is found by Giza in Egypt. It is, naturally enough, an object of immense scientific and archaeological curiosity. But suppose that, among its many valuable features, there lies deep within its structure, a vial of blue elixir locked in a sarcophagus. This elixir for whatever reason provides our best shot to cure cancer, but it will hinge on billions of dollars of future investment. Obtaining the vial will require many years of work and much financial investment, along with the destruction of the pyramid and all of its other contents. On top of this, the project is highly risky given its costs: there is only a 30 percent chance of success. That is, there is a 70 percent chance that we will destroy the pyramid and not get the elixir.
The 30 percent chance of success in Risky Cure is meant to track a conservative estimate of the chance of success of a Mars colony. So if the correct verdict in Risky Cure is that we should go ahead and attempt to get the elixir—and I submit that most would say it is—then we ought to attempt to colonize Mars, despite the (relatively) low chance of success.
How should we think about ‘success’ and ‘failure’ when considering space colonization? Trivially, one factor relevant to success is that the colony continues to do what it was primarily designed to do—namely, serve as a conduit for the continued existence of the human race. In this respect, it could be that any space settlement without an indigenous extant breathable atmosphere will have a low chance of success and a high chance of failure, simply because, absent terraforming, to breathe we will be reliant on technology that is liable to malfunction. Call this kind of success factor a foundational success factor. It is foundational because it concerns the very existence of the colony.
Success and failure does not end here, though. Another factor is the well-being of the colonists themselves. The well-being of the colonists includes not just their physical health but also their personal liberties. This latter issue crops up due to the natural constraints put on settlers by the limits of a space colony—limits that could encourage authoritarianism (Cockell Reference Cockell2016a; Milligan Reference Milligan and Cockell2016), discourage dissent and workers’ rights (Cockell Reference Cockell and Cockell2016b; Schwartz Reference Schwartz and Cockell2016), and discourage reproductive rights (Szocik et al. Reference Szocik, Rafael Elias, Steven, Aleksandra, Kateryna and Dobrochna2018). These kinds of success factors are nonfoundational success factors. To call them nonfoundational is not to say that they are not important, only that in the first instance they concern the conditions of the colony, not the colony's existence. True, some nonfoundational factors could have an impact on the existence of the colony under extreme circumstances. Authoritarianism could cause the colonists to rebel and damage the colonies’ critical support systems. But the point is simply that a colony could be successful by one core measure (it being a conduit for the human race's continued existence beyond Earth) while unsuccessful by another (it being a place to which few would want to vacation).
We need to be clear-eyed about what it would take for a colony to succeed given these factors. If we are not, the 30 percent estimate in Risky Cure will look too high. Yet if we are, the 30 percent estimate might look reasonable and indeed may be too low. To see this, consider another foundational success factor: reproduction. We do not yet know whether we can reliably reproduce in reduced gravity (Szocik et al. Reference Szocik, Rafael Elias, Steven, Aleksandra, Kateryna and Dobrochna2018). But this is something we can game out beforehand. It has been estimated that minimum viable human population for an extraterrestrial colony should include about 5,000 individuals, assuming we want that colony to survive for the long term (Impey Reference Impey2015). For a Martian colony to be a hedge against existential risk, it needs to be self-sustaining and thus capable of internally replenishing its own population. This will not be achieved right away. In the short term, immigration from Earth will be the primary means of establishing a sustainable population. But if turns out that human beings cannot reproduce in low gravity (Mars, recall, it at 0.38 G), we can design ‘reproduction centers’ with a full G of spin gravity, perhaps in Martian orbit. (I presume that if we are technologically capable of building a Martian colony, we are technologically capable of building such an orbital center.) This is less than ideal in numerous ways, but it is hard to see how that alone should weaken the strength of our obligation to colonize Mars, especially when the primary reason for colonizing Mars is to preserve the human species. Much of colonizing Mars will be thrilling and enjoyable, but to assume it will be a complete pleasure cruise is to stack the deck against a Martian colony's ever being counted as a success.
With respect to nonfoundational factors, we should reject the idea that the success of a space colony requires freedoms analogous to those found on Earth. Liberty and freedom may look different beyond Earth, and this is just a fact that any space settler will have to recognize. As Tony Milligan (Reference Milligan and Cockell2016: 12–13) notes, we essentially face a dilemma: if the colony is too illiberal, then establishing it might not be a worthwhile; but if it is too liberal in its freedoms, it is unlikely to survive. So while violent forms of disobedience might not be advisable—lest we risk catastrophic consequences from damaged infrastructure—there are acceptable forms of civil disobedience in space and engineering methods that can be used to mitigate against violent disobedience, in case it happens (Cockell Reference Cockell and Cockell2016b). Indeed, as James Schwartz (Reference Schwartz and Cockell2016) points out, even low-level employees in the air production industry can justifiably strike, given that the duty to provide air (and other essential services) is borne by the wider community.
A final objection one might press is that Mars is an object of greater scientific significance than is the new pyramid, and for this reason, the analogy does not hold, as our obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation is now more pressing. Perhaps Mars is of greater interest. I doubt that it matters, though. For this is not the only difference between the cases. Another difference is this: in Cure, we are saving a lot of lives. In colonizing Mars, whether as a bootstrap or not, we are trying to save the human race. That is a difference that makes a difference. Relatedly, Bostrom (Reference Bostrom2003) argues from utilitarian principles that we ought not to delay colonization as doing so would incur a massive opportunity cost, namely that billions of potential lives worth living would not be realized.
Consider Martian Cure, another variant on Cure:
Suppose that deep within Olympus Mons—the 72,000-foot volcano on the surface of Mars—is a vial of blue elixir locked in bejeweled box left by an ancient alien civilization from a distant galaxy. The civilization inscribed some details of its history on the box. This elixir provides our best shot to cure cancer, though it will hinge on billions of dollars of future investment. However, there is a further catch: the bejeweled box—our only other piece of evidence of this civilization—must be destroyed to obtain the vial.
As in Cure, in Martian Cure we have our best chance to cure cancer. Yet now we are contemplating destroying an object of arguably greater scientific interest than Mars: our only other piece of evidence of an ancient alien civilization. That this is of greater scientific significance is underscored by the fact that whereas we have other planets to study, without the box we only have one other piece of evidence for aliens, namely the vial. Even so, in Martian Cure it is arguable that we have a consideration that would override the principle of scientific conservation with respect to the box. If that is right, then the fact that the pyramid is of lesser scientific significance than Mars cuts no ice.
3. When to Colonize
Stoner's argument fails. There is a consideration that warrants overriding the principle of scientific conservation when it comes to colonizing Mars: the opportunity Mars provides as a hedge against existential risk. On its own, this gets us close to the claim that we do have an obligation to colonize Mars. I conclude by exploring in a programmatic fashion what would take us all the way to such a claim.
A sketch of a reasonably compelling argument for our having an obligation to colonize Mars proceeds in two stages. The first stage looks like this:
M1. We have an obligation to ensure the long-term survival of the human race.
M2. If we have an obligation to ensure the long-term survival of the human race, then we have an obligation to perform the actions and undertake the projects that, among all the feasible actions and projects, will make the long-term survival of the human race most likely.
∴ We have an obligation to perform the actions and undertake the projects that, among all the feasible actions and projects, will make the long-term survival of the human race most likely.
Given the conclusion of the first stage, here is the second:
M3. Colonizing Mars is among the feasible projects that will make the long-term survival of the human race most likely.
∴ We have an obligation to colonize Mars.Footnote 2
The ‘feasible’ clause in M2 and M3 allows that there might be targets for colonization that are better than Mars insofar as our long-term survival goes. For instance, suppose that Proxima Centauri b—an exoplanet in the habitable zone orbiting Proxima Centauri, the star closest to the Sun at 4.22 light years away—has a rocky surface, liquid water, a breathable atmosphere, and a temperate climate. The existence of Proxima Centauri b would not show that M3 is false, because colonizing Proxima Centauri b is currently not feasible and may never be. (If it ever is in the far future, this might be due precisely to our having colonized Mars first.) What counts as feasible is largely an empirical matter, but there are also moral and pragmatic constraints, too.
Suppose one thought that to ensure humanity's long-term survival we should refrain from expanding our population beyond Earth (as would be the case if we colonized Mars) and instead focus on contracting our population. The problem here is, if not moral, certainly practical; Malthusian-style solutions are not something many will be running to get behind.
I have tried to show that Stoner's case against colonizing Mars fails by motivating M3 and by arguing that if M1 is true, then the value of the human race surviving long term is a countervailing and weightier moral consideration that overrides our obligation not to violate the principle of scientific conservation. To go further, though, and establish that we do in fact have an obligation to colonize Mars, we will need to do at least four things.
First, we will need to provide a robust defense of M1. This is a nontrivial task. Saying exactly what is wrong with human extinction takes work (Finneron-Burns Reference Finneron-Burns2017), as does saying what moral reasons we have, if any, for promoting the long-term survival of humanity (Frick Reference Frick2017). In fact, if an obligation to extend humanity is simply an obligation to future generations, then the nonidentity problem might render M1 incoherent (Parfit Reference Parfit1984). The application of the nonidentity problem here is not entirely straightforward (Schwartz Reference Schwartz2019), but it presents at least a prima facie difficulty.
Second, while M2 seems innocuous, M3 will also require a more detailed defense—certainly more detailed than has been provided here. For instance, to defend M3 fully, it would be ideal to have an empirically grounded comprehensive assessment of both the costs and benefits of colonizing Mars with regards to protecting against existential threats, weighed against the costs and benefits of the other suite of activities we will want to pursue, like reducing our stockpile of nuclear weapons and implementing climate change mitigation and adaption strategies.
Third, the present argument elides the difference between prima facie obligations and all-things-considered obligations (Ross Reference Ross1930). Prima facie obligations can be overridden; it is an obligation such that, absent conflicting obligations, would be an all-things-considered obligation. So, to make the case that we have an all-things-considered obligation to colonize Mars, we would have to show that M1 still holds after balancing it with any other conflicting prima facie obligations. I have attempted that with the principle of scientific conservation, but there might be other considerations.
Finally, and related to my first point, in saying that ‘we’ have an obligation to colonize Mars, the argument's conclusion technically leaves open exactly what this obligation entails for present-day society and, relatedly, just how strongly this obligation weighs on us today. In Cure we are dealing with something (cancer) that is an actual, present, eminent threat. So we are inclined to say that it is permissible, if not obligatory to destroy the pyramid for the cure now, or as soon as we are able. By contrast, while it is possible for us to discover a planet-killing asteroid tomorrow, and it is possible for a global nuclear war to break out overnight, these threats are not actually present in this way. So even granting an obligation to colonize Mars at all, we might still wonder whether this obligation requires us to act as soon as we are technologically able, especially if that time comes before we have exhausted all possible noninvasive scientific investigations of Mars.
This is a fair point. However, protecting against possible existential threats is not a can to be kicked down the road. The reason we would colonize Mars as soon as we are technologically able is precisely to avoid doing it when our collective backs are against the wall. We would not want to start our colonization efforts only when we do know of a planet-killing asteroid and thereby risk having not nearly enough time to complete our efforts. You do not buy health insurance only when death is at your door. The same thinking goes for the species.
That said, this kind of forward thinking does not exactly track how we in fact tend to behave. Consider this: colonizing Mars is a project with a long time horizon. Regardless of how we do it, realizing a full-fledged (that is, self-sufficient) colony on Mars will take a while. The time frame depends on numerous factors, including transit constraints given that minimum-energy launch windows for a Mars transit occur every two years, the minimum viable human population for a colony, and whether full terraforming is required, with long-end estimates for the latter itself being tens of thousands of years (McKay and Marinova Reference McKay and Margarita M.2001). Human beings, though, are not good at waiting, and we tend to care more about what happens to us now than about what happens to future generations. This tendency is at play in both hedonic and nonhedonic valuing. When the value of an activity is hedonic, we often exhibit near bias: we prefer painful activities to be distant and pleasurable activities to be near. When the value of an activity is nonhedonic, we do so in a way that biases the perceived social distance between you and who else might benefit from those activities (Greene and Sullivan Reference Greene and Sullivan2015; Greene, Reference Greenen.d.). Space colonization will have both hedonic and non-hedonic value; it will be fun and exciting (though also dangerous and perhaps terrifying), but it will also be valuable given its importance to future generations. Yet now the time scales involved present a further problem. We assign a positive discount rate to future well-being: the value of someone's well-being in (say) fifty years is only worth a fraction of the well-being of a present person. So the question we are inevitably faced with is this: Why would I start colonizing space now when the well-being of those who would be actual space colonists, living on Mars, is worth so little to me relative to my present peers? The thinking goes like this: ‘Sure, maybe we can visit Mars, but I would rather spend the vast amount of money it would take to colonize Mars on present concerns and present people’. The idea here is akin to the one we have when we prefer a quick weekend getaway to a local winery in two weeks to a three-week trip to Bali in ten years.
One complication with this question is that even if we assume that the weekend winery getaway and the trip to Bali are equally likely to occur, this assumption might not hold for colonizing Mars. Perhaps institutional support will erode over time, as when one presidential administration decides no longer to continue the commitments of a past one. (Witness, for example, Richard Nixon's cancellation of the Apollo program.) In fact, according to Alan Jacobs and J. Scott Matthews (Reference Jacobs and J. Scott2012), when it comes to present-directed policy bias—that is, how citizens weigh short-term outcomes more heavily than long-term outcomes in policy choice—the primary factor is uncertainty surrounding the processes of policy causation and political commitments over the long run.
I do not know whether such reasoning, and the temporal and social biases that underpin it, is rational. In one respect it does not matter. These biases are a pervasive feature of human psychology and as such present an inherent and forceful impediment to getting space colonization off the ground. We will always tend towards buck passing, even if we know that we ought not to. Just consider how we approach climate change. In another sense though, it does matter. For if this reasoning is rational, then even if there is an obligation to colonize Mars, this obligation isn't necessarily one that must be borne by us in present day. How to approach resolving this matter and related issues is, however, a problem for another day.