Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b95js Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T04:46:05.279Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Epistemological Power of Taste

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 July 2021

LOUISE RICHARDSON*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF YORKlouise.richardson@york.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

It is generally accepted that sight—the capacity to see or to have visual experiences—has the power to give us knowledge about things in the environment and some of their properties in a distinctive way. Seeing the goose on the lake puts me in a position to know that it is there and that it has certain properties. And it does this by, when all goes well, presenting us with these features of the goose. One might even think that it is part of what it is to be a perceptual capacity that it has this kind of epistemological power, such that a capacity that lacked this power could not be perceptual. My focus in this essay is the sense of taste—the capacity to taste things or to have taste experiences. It has sometimes been suggested that taste lacks sight-like epistemological power. I argue that taste has epistemological power of the same kind as does sight, but that as a matter of contingent fact, that power often goes unexercised in our contemporary environment. We can know about things by tasting them in the same kind of way as we can know about things by seeing them, but we often do not. I then consider the significance of this conclusion. I suggest that in one way, it matters little, because our primary interest in taste (in marked contrast to our other senses) is not epistemic but aesthetic. But, I end by suggesting, it can matter ethically.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Philosophical Association

It is generally accepted that sight has the power to give us knowledge about things in the environment in a distinctive way. Seeing the goose puts me in a position to know that it is there and that it is, say, brown, large, maybe even that it is angry. And it does this by, when all goes well, presenting us with these worldly features. One might even think that it is part of what it is to be a perceptual capacity that it has this kind of epistemological power, such that a capacity that lacked it could not be perceptual.

My focus here is on the sense of taste—the capacity to taste things or to have taste experiences. It has sometimes been suggested that taste lacks sight-like epistemological power. I argue that taste has this kind of power, but that as a matter of contingent fact, it often goes unexercised. We can know about things by tasting them in the same kind of way as we can know about things by seeing them, but we often do not (section 2). I then consider the significance of this conclusion. I argue that in some ways, it matters little, because our contemporary interest in taste is in large part aesthetic rather than epistemic or practical (section 3). However, I suggest that we should not be wholly comfortable with the way in which taste's epistemic power is undermined, since this can have ethical import (section 4).

1. The Epistemological Power of Taste

When we see, we can come to know how the world is by taking visual experience at face value. For instance, if I see a brown goose, then I am presented with the goose and some of the features that it has: at least its brownness, location, and shape. Absent defeaters—such as the suspicion that I am hallucinating or that I am in fake-goose country—I can simply take things to be how they seem, and know that there is a brown goose before me, or at least that there is something brown and shaped in a certain way. Some (for example, Travis Reference Travis2004) would reject this conception of the epistemological power of sight, but I take it for granted here.

Arguably, it is necessary that a perceptual capacity or sense have this kind of epistemological power. Contrast sight with a capacity to know that there is pollen about because pollen reliably makes you sneeze. This capacity is useful, and it is like a perceptual capacity in that it puts you in a position to know something about your environment. But the way in which it does so is quite different to the way in which a perceptual capacity does. To take the pollen experience at face value lets you know, at best, something about yourself or your body: that you are sneezing or that your nose is itchy. Furthermore, it is only in the context of knowing that the sneezing or itchiness is likely to be caused by pollen that it allows you to know about it.

That the other senses have this power is consistent with some philosophical views. For example, philosophical accounts of olfactory experience according to which odors represent worldly things (such as Batty Reference Batty2010; Mizrahi Reference Mizrahi2014; Roberts Reference Roberts2016) are consistent with the view that smell has sight-like epistemological power. Philosophical accounts according to which auditory experience represents worldly things (for example, Meadows Reference Meadows2018; O'Callaghan Reference O'Callaghan2007; Leddington Reference Leddington2019) are consistent with the view that hearing has sight-like epistemological power. Touch is complicated. On one view (Richardson Reference Richardson2013), it allows us to perceive extra-bodily things indirectly, by perceiving our bodies. Whether this means that touch has sight-like epistemological power only with respect to the perceiver's body is an issue that might be explored elsewhere.

The sense of taste has sometimes been thought of by philosophers as lacking the sight-like epistemological power associated with properly perceptual capacities. On such a view, tastes or flavors—more on that distinction below—can only be thought of as features of sensations or, at best, powers of objects to produce such sensations in us. If that were right, then a taste experience would not amount to being presented with a feature of something in the world, as our experience of the goose's brownness does. It would be awareness in the first instance of a feature of a sensation. One route to such a view of taste might be via its spatial phenomenology: ‘Tradition holds that taste directs attention “inward” to the state of one's own body. When one tastes a flavor . . . that flavor is positioned phenomenologically in one's mouth, nose and throat; the sensation is perceived to be an alteration of the body’ (Korsmeyer Reference Korsmeyer1999: 96). On this ‘traditional’ sensation view, taste experiences are bodily sensations. But the spatial phenomenology of taste does not merit thinking of taste experiences as bodily sensations. While they do direct attention ‘inward’, it is to things that while in one's mouth are distinct from and experienced as distinct from one's body (like a pebble in your hand).

A sensation view is adopted by some for color, too, in which case even sight, at least where color is concerned, would lack the kind of epistemological power under discussion. Since this essay is premised on the idea that sight does have that power, I take it for granted that the arguments for thinking otherwise—such as arguments from variation—are not convincing as defenses of sensation views of sensory qualities in any modality. Instead, I focus on recent treatments of taste specifically, arguing that taste's epistemological power has been underestimated.

1.1. Construing Taste Too Narrowly

If taste has sight's epistemological power then it presents us with worldly features such that, when one is really tasting, taking one's experience at face value, one can on that basis know that something with a relevant feature is present. William Lycan argues (Reference Lycan2018) that there are serious obstacles to thinking that taste can do this, or as he sees it, that taste represents. Lycan's argument is premised on thinking of taste narrowly: ‘it is the specifically gustatory sense-component [that] is rightly though very strictly to be called “taste”’, and a taste, is ‘a point in a 5-space’ (Reference Lycan2018: 30).

On this narrow conception, how something tastes would be a matter only of how sweet, salty, bitter, sour, or umami it is or appears. (See also, for example, Spence, Auvray, and Smith Reference Spence, Auvray, Smith, Stokes, Matthen and Biggs2015). How vanillary or spicy something is or appears would not on this view be a matter of taste at all, since this could not be captured in the ‘5-space’. On this narrow view of taste, such features are instead aspects of the flavors of things, contributed by other sensory modalities such as olfaction. If taste is construed narrowly, then its sight-like epistemological power would be limited to putting us in a position to know about the five ‘properly’ gustatory properties. But Lycan also identifies a more serious problem.

People cannot, it turns out, introspectively tell how things taste to them: they cannot consistently identify the place in the 5-space occupied by something they are tasting (Lycan Reference Lycan2018: 32). This leaves one with two options. First, one can say that taste representations are (very unusually for a mental-state type) personal-level states that are, as a type, typically inaccessible to introspection. Or, one can say that the only personal-level state in the vicinity represents flavor, and that taste (‘proper’) representations are not personal-level.

The first option is to be avoided because it would make taste states a very peculiar kind of mental state. The idea of a mental state type that as a type is inaccessible to introspection is not one we should readily accept. Lycan takes the second option—that the personal level state associated with the sense of taste represents flavor—to be objectionable too, because flavor is such a ‘complex and demanding phenomenon’ (Lycan Reference Lycan2018: 33), and—and to Lycan, ‘worse’—this would mean that the sense of taste was startlingly anomalous among the senses. The representations properly proprietary to this sense would be largely inaccessible, and, as corollary, we would hardly ever be able to tell not merely what but even that we are tasting (Lycan Reference Lycan2018: 34).

It seems to me that Lycan's dilemma is caused by the narrow construal of taste that he, like others, insists on. There is a terminological net in which one could easily get caught here. I do not deny that ‘taste’ can be used in this narrow sense, or more accurately, in narrower senses, associated with the modality (the sense of taste), the object of experience (tastes as properties of things), the experience type (taste experience) and the act of sensing (tasting). Like many terms, ‘taste’ is polysemous, and among its polysemes, some are associated with the narrower construal and some the broader, on which taste and flavor are used interchangeably. The narrower senses that Lycan adopts have their home in those contexts in which we are interested in which sensory system is at work. But outside of those contexts—and we humans are usually outside of those contexts—broader senses of ‘taste’ and ‘tasting’ are the norm. When this is the case, we talk of vanilla and lemon no less than sweet and salty as tasted and as tastes, and as the objects of taste experiences. With this in mind, it seems unobjectionable and wholly unsurprising to think of, to use Lycan's terms, the personal level state associated with the sense of taste as representing flavor, which is to say, taste, broadly construed. But then, Lycan's second option looks unobjectionable and the dilemma disappears.

Recall though that Lycan was also concerned that flavor's complexity and demandingness made this second option a no-go. One aspect of flavor's complexity is that multiple sensory systems are involved in flavor experience. Flavor is sensed not only by means of the taste buds that are sensitive to sweetness and saltiness and so on, but also by means of other receptors and the sensory systems to which they belong. Without the involvement in flavor perception of the olfactory receptors and the retronasal olfactory system, we would not be able to sense vanillariness and lemoniness, for example. Without the involvement of the trigeminal nerve, we would not be able to sense the ‘heat’ of mustard or wasabi. (For a discussion of the role that orthonasal olfaction and other sensory systems can play in flavor experience see Spence [Reference Spence2015].)

Why should that prevent us from thinking that flavor (taste broadly construed) is what the sense of taste (understood broadly) is the capacity to perceive or represent? One reason is metaphysical. On Lycan's view, ‘we could not easily say what a mélange of ortho-smell, retro-smell, taste proper, and trigeminal irritation represents overall’ (Lycan Reference Lycan2018: 32). But it is not clear why we cannot answer ‘it represents flavor’. One option would be to think of flavors as emergent properties, had by substances (often foodstuffs), that are made up of component substances—odorants, tastants, trigeminal irritants—that on their own lack this property-type, and which it therefore requires multiple sensory systems to perceive. To the extent that we can attend to, for example, the sweetness of a strawberry or the bitterness of beer, we can say that the contribution of the different sensory systems leaves its mark in experience, in a way that is analogous to that in which our capacity to attend visually to edges involves the contribution of a lower-level edge detection mechanism in the visual system leaving its mark. Perceptual psychologist Richard Stevenson calls flavor a ‘preservative emergent property’: emergent, in the sense described above, and preservative in that some of the ‘components of flavour remain detectable by the subject’ (Reference Stevenson2009: 109).

The second more specific way in which, according to Lycan, flavor is complex and demanding lies in its failure to ‘reveal its primaries’ (Reference Lycan2018: 34). It is certainly true that no flavor primaries equivalent to red, blue, yellow, and green have been identified. These colors are primaries in the sense that they are at the poles of the hue-specific dimensions of the color space. But without further argument, it is unclear why this should be an obstacle to thinking of flavors as what taste experiences represent. Some accounts of sensory qualities or our experiences of them, such as David Rosenthal's quality space theory (Reference Rosenthal2005), or Alistair Isaac's structural realism (Reference Isaac2014) necessitate the existence of sensory spaces analogous to the color space, for all sensory qualities. If one does not endorse such a theory, one will be unbothered by the absence of a sensory space for flavors. And even if one does endorse such a theory, the creation of a flavor space need not start out from pre-identified primaries. An alternative is to use the method of just noticeable differences to map the experienced relations of similarity and difference between qualities, as some have suggested an odor space could be created (Young, Keller, and Rosenthal Reference Young, Keller and Rosenthal2014). Multidimensional scaling can then be used to reduce the resultant space's dimensions. It is possible in principle that a flavor space could be created in this way and even that (via multidimensional scaling) flavor primaries, or at least the fundamental flavors, could be identified (Isaac Reference Isaac2017).

Lycan's concerns about the complexity and demandingness of flavor can then be addressed. It is both complex and demanding, but not in ways that preclude it from being the object of taste experience, nor therefore in ways that preclude taste from having sight-like epistemological power.

1.2. Flavor as Constructed by the Brain

The role of more than one sensory system in taste—broadly construed—has been the source of a second reason for underestimating taste's epistemological power. As Barry Smith notes, it is a view ‘prominent among many psychologists and neuroscientists that flavours are not something we perceive: they are just psychological constructs . . . or items that arise only in the brain’ (Smith Reference Smith2013: 305). The role of multisensory integration in the perception of flavor can seem to support this view, since it evokes the idea of flavor as something that the brain creates by putting together inputs from different sensory streams. If this subjective or ‘brain-dependent’ view of flavors were correct, then taste could not have the kind of epistemological power that sight has, since it would not be presenting us with features of the world, but only features that our brains have ‘made up’.

But as Smith rightly urges, the science of taste experience ‘leaves room for objective flavours’ (Smith Reference Smith2013: 311). We can understand the multisensory processing involved in taste experience as enabling the perception of rather than constructing flavors. Furthermore, Smith argues, we are better placed to explain the integrative processes involved in our experience of flavors if we think of them as guided by and toward features which are ‘an ecologically valid part of the environment’ (Smith Reference Smith2013: 310). The integration involved in processing input from multiple sensory streams—in any case of multisensory integration—can be guided by various principles. In the case of flavor perception, one such principle is ‘congruence’. If that which the gustatory and olfactory systems detect is ‘congruent’ then a unified flavor experience is more likely to result. But what determines congruence? One very straightforward answer would be that congruence is determined by what is found in our environments. So, for example, sucrose on the tongue will combine with strawberry odorant at the olfactory receptors, because this is a combination frequently encountered in the world—in strawberries. But sucrose on the tongue will not combine with chicken odorant at the olfactory receptors, because that is not a combination frequently found in the world (or at least not in some parts of the world).

If we do not understand congruence in this world-determined way, then, as Smith says, ‘all we can fall back on are sensory congruencies’ (Reference Smith2013: 310). This means positing a metric of ‘congruence’ between sensory inputs independent of what is found in our environments, and which would explain cases like the strawberry/chicken example. But the rationale behind such a metric would remain mysterious. And since we have an alternative, on which congruence is a matter of what is found in the world, there is no good reason to ‘settle for this unexplanatory stopping point’ (Smith Reference Smith2013: 310).

So, the role of multisensory integration in flavor perception—or taste perception, broadly construed—does not entail that and in fact is less easy to understand if we think that flavors are constructed by the brain. Thus, it is no obstacle to taste having the same kind of epistemological power as sight does.

In this section, I have tried to dislodge some recently discussed reasons for underestimating taste's epistemic power: a too-narrow construal of ‘taste’ and a misguided view of the significance of the multisensory nature of flavor experience. There might be better arguments than these for thinking that taste lacks sight's epistemological power. But pending such arguments, we can think of it as having sight-like epistemological power. And, if having such power is necessary for perceptual capacities then taste can remain among them.

2. Taste's Power Unexercised

Though the sense of taste has, inherently, the same kind of epistemological power as our other perceptual capacities, we are frequently prevented from actually coming to know about flavors by tasting. This is contingent: it flows not from the nature of taste itself, but from features of our perceptual and cognitive equipment in interaction with largely human-made features of our contemporary environment.

I consider three kinds of effects on taste that influence whether or how much we end up knowing by tasting. The first is associative learning within taste and between taste and smell. The second is the effect of experience of other sensory qualities on how things taste. The third is cognitive penetration—or at least something like it.

2.1. Associative Learning

Taste (and also smell) is subject to associative learning in a distinctive way. This takes two forms: odor-taste learning, and flavor-flavor learning. This is an example of the former: if you eat or drink something that is vanillary and sweet a few times, then vanilla, on its own, will come to taste and smell sweet (Stevenson, Prescott, and Boakes Reference Stevenson, Prescott and Boakes1995). An example of the latter occurs when, having tasted something cherry and smoky flavored a few times, all cherry-flavored foods come to taste a bit smoky (Stevenson Reference Stevenson2001a). There are reasons to believe that these are effects on perceptual experience itself rather than just on our beliefs about it: they are cognitively impenetrable (Stevenson Reference Stevenson2001b), and the learning involved is implicit (Stevenson and Boakes Reference Stevenson and Boakes2003).

It is plausible that in an untampered-with environment, the associative learning to which taste is subject would facilitate knowing by tasting. In such an environment, the pairings that were learned would be likely to be mostly ecologically valid. When encountering an odorant evoked experience of a (narrowly construed) taste, such as an experience of sweetness or saltiness, it would be highly likely that the thing you were perceiving was sweet or salty, and likewise for flavor-flavor learning. And, since this learning is perceptual learning, in such an environment, it would facilitate the exercise of taste's sight-like epistemological power. Taking experiences that are the result of this learning at face value, we would for the most part be put in a position to know about the flavors that things have.

However, our current gustatory and olfactory environment is very tampered with, to the extent that it is quite difficult to say what counts as an ecologically valid pairing. Though it may be difficult to know what to say about any particular case, the frequent presence of non-naturally occurring mixtures of odorants and tastants in food, drink, and the atmosphere, and the speed with which associations can be created by perceptual learning, likely means that we are subject to a great many taste illusions as a result of this learning mechanism. It is likely the case that frequently things taste sweet or salty—perceptually appear to have those worldly sensory qualities—when they are not, and in the same way they can seem to have features like vanillariness or smokiness that they do not have. When this is so, the epistemological power that, as I have shown, taste has, is prevented from being exercised. If we take our taste experiences at face value, we will end up with false beliefs about the flavors of things, rather than knowledge.

2.2. Crossmodal Effects

Experiences of other sensory qualities at the same time or around the same time as tasting can also affect taste experience. For example, the color or shape of food or drink or the receptacles or packaging it is served in can affect how things taste. Charles Spence gives us a plethora of examples of this kind in his book Gastrophysics (Reference Spence2017). For example, subjects rated a mousse as sweeter when served from a white than from a black plate (Johnson and Clydesdale Reference Johnson and Clydesdale1982) and hot chocolate as chocolatier when served from an orange cup (Spence Reference Spence2017: 47). Chocolate is reported as being creamier when presented in rounded than in rectangular chunks (Spence Reference Spence2017: 45).

Given that we rarely taste with our other senses ‘off’, it seems likely that taste experience is fairly frequently subject to these kinds of crossmodal effects. And—as I discuss below (section 4)—such effects are increasingly used deliberately to affect our experiences, which makes our exposure to them more frequent still. It may be that some of these cases are best understood as cognitive penetration, in which case they can be dealt with as are the phenomena in section 2.3.

As with associative learning, crossmodal effects may, in the right environment, be conducive to getting things right. If, for example, most of the red things in your environment were ripe fruits, then a tendency to rate red things as sweeter than otherwise would be truth-conducive. But it seems highly likely that in many cases in the present environment, crossmodal effects lead us into error with respect to flavors. In light of the discussion in section 1, I am taking it that taste has sight-like epistemological power, and thus that flavors are worldly features of which we can become aware; they are neither features of sensations nor powers of objects to produce them in us. With this view in place, it is reasonable to assume that putting hot chocolate in an orange cup does not change its flavor, such that if it appears more chocolately, that appearance is in some sense in error.

It is less clear than for associative learning that these crossmodal effects are perceptual, in the sense of affecting perceptual experience rather than merely reports of or beliefs about perceptual experience. Perhaps the hot chocolate in the orange cup tastes exactly as chocolately as that which arrives in a white cup, and the color of the cup affects just what the subject thinks and says about how it seems. But whether the effects are perceptual or not, they have an impact on the exercise of taste's sight-like epistemological power. If they are perceptual then they produce illusions, so that to take taste experience at face value will be to be led to false belief. And if they are merely effects on belief and report that leave taste experience unchanged, they prevent us from taking our taste experience at face value in cases when to do so would have led to true belief.

2.3. Cognitive Penetration—Or Something Like It

Another factor that prevents taste's epistemic power from being exercised is the cognitive penetration of taste experience—or at least something like the cognitive penetration of taste experience. Cognitive penetration happens when the occurrence of a perceptual experience depends on the occurrence of some cognitive state—for example, a belief or a desire or an expectation—so that the content of the perceptual state is affected in a way that is semantically coherent. Whether or not such a thing is possible is controversial. Some think that perception is cognitively impenetrable in that ‘it is not possible for two perceivers . . . to have difference experiences with distinct content or character when one holds fixed the object or event of perception, the perceptual conditions (e.g., lighting), the spatial attention of the subject and the conditions of the sensory organ(s)’ (Stokes Reference Stokes2013: 647–48; see also Macpherson Reference Macpherson2012). There is no need to take a stance on this issue here, as I explain below.

There are many documented cases of effects on taste that might be considered cognitive penetration. For example, in one study, subjects were given meat samples and told either that they were factory farmed or free range: ‘those who were told that the meat was factory farmed rated it as tasting . . . saltier and greasier’ (Spence Reference Spence2017: 13). This looks, on the face of it, to be a case in which the content of taste experience was affected by beliefs about the meat's provenance. Consider also the effect that descriptions on menus can have. In 1997, Heston Blumenthal's menu at the Fat Duck included a description of an item as ‘crab ice cream’. Some diners reported that this item was too salty, among other things. When, having worked on a study with Martin Yeomans exploring this effect, Blumenthal renamed it ‘frozen crab bisque’, ratings of saltiness changed (Spence Reference Spence2017: 3–5). Another similar example is the effect of tasting notes—for, for example beer, wine, or coffee—on the experience of such products. Aaron Meskin (Reference Meskin2018) hypothesizes that such notes, for example, describing a coffee as tasting of hazelnuts, generate mental imagery that makes the coffee taste more hazelnutty than it otherwise would.

As discussed above (section 2.1 and 2.2), this is an effect that, were the circumstances right, could help us to know about the world. As Susanna Siegel writes about a different case of purported cognitive penetration: ‘If an x-ray looks different to a radiologist from the way it looks to someone lacking radiological expertise, then the radiologist gets more information about the world from her experience (such as whether there's a tumor) than the non-expert does from looking at the same x-ray’ (Reference Siegel2012: 201).

But clearly this is not always so. Free-range meat is not necessarily less salty than meat that is not free range, and whether a menu item is described as ‘ice cream’ or ‘frozen bisque’ does not affect its flavor. Or rather, it does not once we allow that flavor is a worldly property of which experience can make us aware. So the effect of such descriptions is to lead us into error about the meat or ice cream, rather than to give us more information about it. If cognitive penetration is possible, then some cases like this will yield illusions, making things seem to us to have flavors that they do not have. If cognitive penetration is not possible, then as discussed above (section 2.2), these effects would still have a deleterious impact on the exercise of taste's epistemic power, by making it impossible for us to take experiences had when genuinely perceiving at face value.

In our contemporary environment, food and drink very often comes to us with descriptions or images on menus, packaging, advertising, and display that make cognitive penetration or something like it likely. As such, it seems highly likely that this provides another frequently encountered obstacle to the exercise of taste's epistemic power.

Even though, as I show in section 1, taste can put us in a position to know about the flavors of things, in our contemporary environment, its epistemological power often goes unexercised, or so I have suggested in this section. The studies referred to use statistical analysis of results acquired from groups of perceivers, and so each effect is one to which we can at best conclude that perceivers are subject for the most part. However, that does not undermine this section's conclusion. As far as I know, there is no evidence that there are perceivers who are not subject to these kinds of effects. And to the extent that we are all subject to a range of such effects, the epistemological power of our capacity to taste is undermined in the way discussed in this section. In the rest of the essay, I explore some consequences of this conclusion.

3. Not Significant: Taste as an Aesthetic Sense

It would matter to us a great deal if sight's epistemic power frequently went unexercised. For one, it would matter practically: plausibly, visual experience allows us to do all sorts of things—from picking up cups to reading—because it has the kind of epistemic power we have been discussing here. It would also matter because our interest in sight is frequently epistemic: we are interested in our visual experiences as sources of knowledge. Does it matter if, as I have argued above, taste's epistemic power frequently goes unexercised? In some ways, I do not think it does. On the one hand, that reduces the significance of the preceding: taste's power frequently goes unexercised, but (in these ways) this is insignificant. On the other hand, this lack of significance draws attention to some interesting features of taste and our current attitude to it.

Firstly, it matters less to us practically if taste's power goes unexercised than if the same were true of sight. This point has two components. First, we modern human beings do not have to rely on taste to find nutrients and safe food and second, we also cannot do so (or can do so to a lesser extent). Presumably, things were different for our evolutionary ancestors in both ways. For one, they likely had to rely on taste more than we do to ensure that what they ate was safe and nutritious. We have, and they lacked, other ways of determining that—food labeling, use-by dates, education about healthy eating and safe food preparation. Furthermore, in the untampered-with environment of those ancestors, taste would been an excellent guide to energy and nutrient content. For us, now, things are different. Taste is now a less good guide to nutrient content than it once was. Before the discovery of artificial sweeteners, the vast majority of sweet-tasting things would have been high in calories. But since the discovery of artificial sweeteners over a century ago, and especially since their proliferation in the latter half of that century, we can have ‘the sweet taste without the calories’ (Chattopadhyay, Raychaudhuri, and Chakraborty Reference Chattopadhyay, Raychaudhuri and Chakraborty2014: 611), and increasingly, we have exactly that. For example, since the introduction in 2018 of the Soft Drinks Industry Levy, or ‘sugar tax’, in the United Kingdom, sweet-tasting drinks are likely to be sweetened with, for example, aspartame, sucralose, or acesulfame K rather than sucrose. (For a comprehensive discussion of alternative sweeteners to sucrose, see O'Brien-Nabors [Reference O'Brien-Nabors2016].) Likewise, creaminess and other sensory qualities associated with fat need no longer be indicative of high fat levels. Low-fat versions of foods such as ice creams can be given the taste and ‘mouth feel’ associated with fat by using various fat-replacing additives. (For a review of fat replacers, see Lucca and Tepper [Reference Lucca and Tepper1994]. For more recent discussion of a more specific range of fat replacers see Peng and Yao [Reference Peng and Yao2017]. For fat replacement in low-fat ice cream, see Akbari, Eskandari, and Davoudi [Reference Akbari, Eskandari and Davoudi2019].)

These are not themselves examples of taste's epistemic power being undermined: taste experiences could be largely veridical with regards to sensory qualities such as creaminess or sweetness but nevertheless be a poor guide to nutrient content, just as a perfectly veridical experience of a red tomato can be a poor guide to the tomato's ripeness. Nevertheless, the fact that taste is now a less good guide to the presence of nutrients than it was means that the undermining of its epistemic power has less practical import than it might, as does the fact that our need to use it in this way is much reduced.

Secondly, and probably not unrelatedly, our interest in taste as eaters and drinkers is not primarily epistemic—which is to say, we are not usually or mainly interested, when tasting, in finding out what properties the things we are tasting really have. Instead, we are more often interested in how they seem, whether or not they are that way. This is reflected in the kind of perceptual activity that typically characterizes tasting, and in our language about taste and tasting too.

When we look at things or watch them over time, we tend to do so, throughout, in order to know what those things are like and what they are doing—looking and watching are typically epistemic activities (Crowther Reference Crowther2009). When one tastes something over time, the same is not typically true. As Spence puts it (Reference Spence2017: 163), we make an initial quality check (is it off? Is it what I expected?), and then we simply enjoy the experience: we savor it, without interest in its epistemic import. It is notable that we use this same originally gustatory terminology (‘savoring’) to talk about the enjoying of other kinds of experiences, too.

Our relative lack of interest in taste's epistemic power is also reflected in the way in which we report taste experience. To see this—and its consistency with taste's inherent epistemic power—it is useful to consider an argument that Murat Aydede applies to pain. According to Aydede, pain reports are importantly different to perceptual reports. I would typically withdraw a perceptual report such as ‘I see a dark patch on my hand’ if it turned out that there was no dark patch there. That is because what is reported in such cases is the presence of something in the world that is seen: such a report is committal about the world. On Aydede's view, pain reports such as ‘I feel a jabbing pain in my hand’, while superficially similar to perceptual reports, do not function in this way. Such a report does not attribute a quality (such as tissue damage) to an object (my hand), and so would not be inaccurate if the object lacked the quality. Furthermore, he argues, because pain reports are hardly ever committal about the world, we should not even think of the experiences they report as representations of any worldly quality (Aydede Reference Aydede2009).

For our purposes here, it need not matter whether we accept what Aydede says about pain. What is important is that taste falls between vision and (if Aydede is correct) pain, such that a view he takes to be ruled out for pain remains plausible for taste. Reports of taste experience are frequently but not always committal about the world: ‘it tastes sweet’ we say, and we would often not withdraw the claim were it to turn out that we are subject to an illusion of sweetness. We are in such cases reporting on the occurrence of an experience rather than attributing a quality to something in the world. However, there are also taste reports that are more like typical reports of visual experiences. One context in which taste reports that are committal about the world occur is the nonculinary: consider tentatively licking some soap that you have been told tastes like honey or (once upon a time) a doctor tasting urine for the sweetness indicative of diabetes (see, for example, Kaplish Reference Kaplish2013). More generally, while we may agree with Aydede that we strongly resist the suggestion that we are not in pain when we say we are, we are quite willing to accept that in certain circumstances, something is not F when it tastes that way, or vice versa (witness ‘miracle fruit’ or the effect of a cold on taste experience).

Because there are both taste reports that are committal about the world, and taste reports that are not, this makes it plausible to say about taste what, according to Aydede, it is not plausible to say about pain. Namely, that taste experiences do represent worldly properties but that when we talk about taste we are frequently interested only in reporting the occurrence of those experiences rather than the presence of what they represent.

These factors suggest that rather than being epistemic or practical, our interest in taste is very often aesthetic, where this is understood to mean that our concern is ‘with a thing's looking somehow without concern for whether it really is like that’ (Urmson Reference Urmson1957). I do not mean to suggest that this understanding of ‘aesthetic’ is all there is to having an aesthetic function, or taste's aesthetic function in particular. (For further discussion, see, for example Crane [Reference Crane and Smith2007]; Todd [Reference Todd2014]; Matthen [Reference Matthen2021].) But given that our interest in taste is aesthetic in this restricted sense, it matters less than it might have—and much less than it would for sight—that taste's sight-like epistemic power frequently goes unexercised.

4. Significant After All: Gastrophysical Nudging and the Ethics of Tasting

I have argued that the fact that taste's epistemic power goes unexercised is in some ways insignificant. That lack of significance is itself noteworthy, because it draws our attention to some features of taste and our interest in it: our interest in taste, unlike our interest in sight, is not primarily practical or epistemic but aesthetic. And this might seem to be cause for celebration: lucky are we who can do without the epistemic power of a whole perceptual capacity! But in this final section I recommend caution. The kinds of effects on taste discussed in section 2 are among very many human psychological quirks revealed to us by psychology. Such quirks can (and increasingly are) exploited to affect our beliefs, choices and actions with a variety of aims, benign and otherwise. Behavioral interventions that exploit the effects discussed in section 2 will typically be ones that prevent us from exercising the epistemic power of taste—that is, they prevent us from coming to know how the world is on the basis of taste experience. And precisely because they function in this way, they fall foul of conditions widely agreed to affect the ethical permissibility of behavioral interventions. So while our relative lack of practical and epistemic interest in taste might make us unconcerned about its power being undermined, this undermining nevertheless matters, and specifically, matters ethically. To argue for this claim, I first briefly explain the concept of nudging, and some conditions that affect its ethical permissibility.

In nudging, someone, the nudger, intentionally changes aspects of ‘choice architecture’ to influence people's decisions. ‘Choice architecture’ is the way in which choices are presented to agents (Thaler and Sunstein Reference Thaler and Sunstein2008). Choice architecture is changed in nudging in a way that exploits ‘psychological quirks’ that affect human decision making (Wilkinson Reference Wilkinson2013). Such are quirks are frequently ‘patterns of irrationality’ (Bovens Reference Bovens, Grüne-Yanoff and Hansson2008). For example, people tend to stick with default options, even when they are more costly. So we can be nudged into paying into a pension or donating our organs after death by making doing so the default: something you have to opt out of rather that into. And because the order in which we are presented with items affects how likely we are to buy them, we can be nudged into buying things if they are placed, for example, at eye level so that they are the first thing we see. I call the use of the kind of effects discussed in section 2 (gastrophysical effects) with the aim of affecting decisions in this way gastrophysical nudging.

Nudging has been of great interest because—in utilizing scientific knowledge about our psychological quirks—it promises to be effective, and—in eschewing coercion—it is potentially acceptable to those of a wide range of political persuasions. But that is not to say that anyone thinks that nudging is always morally permissible. There are a number of factors that are relevant to assessing the permissibility of a nudge. Two related factors have to do with liberty and transparency. I want to suggest that precisely because gastrophysical nudges involve preventing taste's epistemic power from being exercised they fall foul of these factors. It is helpful to be clear at the outset that this does not mean that gastrophysical nudges are impermissible, since other factors are relevant to the permissibility of nudges too. But holding these other factors steady, we should prefer a transparent intervention that preserves liberty to one that does not.

4.1. Liberty and Transparency

A nudge's permissibility is partly determined by the extent to which it does not affect the nudged agent's freedom. In fact, according to Yashar Saghai it is partly constitutive of a nudge—as opposed to some other behavioral manipulation, which he calls a ‘behavioural prod’—that a nudge preserves liberty (Reference Saghai2013: 491). But there are two ways in which an interference in decision making might affect an agent's liberty: first, as noted, it might restrict an agent's choice set, which nudges do not, by definition; secondly, it might affect the way an agent reaches a decision in such a way as to be deemed ‘substantially controlling’ (Saghai Reference Saghai2013: 488). If that is the case, then an interference would prove a threat to the agent's autonomy, despite leaving their choice set intact. An interference will not be substantially controlling if it is easily resistible by a normal agent: one with typical powers of awareness and attention for example (Saghai Reference Saghai2013: 489–90). According to Saghai, both forms of liberty preservation are determining factors not merely in the ethical permissibility of a nudge, but in whether an interference in choice architecture counts as a nudge at all (Reference Saghai2013: 491). I set that taxonomical issue aside here.

The second factor relevant to a nudge's ethical permissibility flows straight from the first: transparency. In order to be easily resistible (and thus substantially noncontrolling), it cannot be the case that the interference builds in obstacles to the agent discovering that they are being nudged and thus resisting it. As Bovens argues, the transparency that matters is ‘in principle token interference transparency’ (Reference Bovens, Grüne-Yanoff and Hansson2008: 216), such that the normal person—without any special skills or knowledge—should be able to spot the interference in any token instance of nudging, and thus avoid being nudged. Such transparency would be missing from, for example, subliminal messaging or hypnosis, even were an agency that used it completely open about doing so. If an interference is not transparent then it is not easily resistible and thus is a threat to autonomy, which as I have shown, is relevant to an interference's ethical permissibility.

Where a nudge or other interference falls foul of these factors we can say that it is manipulative. One core conception of manipulation is that of perverting (distorting or corrupting) or subverting (undermining the power of) decision making processes, or rational processes more generally (Wilkinson Reference Wilkinson2013). With this explained, I am now in a position to argue that gastrophysical nudges will fall foul of these ethical permissibility conditions and thus be manipulative, precisely because they involve undermining the epistemic power of taste.

4.2. Gastrophysical Nudges and the Permissibility Conditions

A gastrophysical nudge would involve exploiting gastrophysical effects in order to affect our decisions about what to eat and drink. One example is the use of flavor-flavor learning to get children to eat more vegetables (Havermans and Jansen Reference Havermans and Jansen2007) Researchers exposed children to pureed vegetables paired with a flavoring they liked (sweetness), so that vegetables came to seem to have that flavor. As a result, the children's liking of the vegetable flavors, presented alone, increased significantly. If this result were used in nudging, the desired knock-on result would be increased intake of vegetables, something this study did not explore. Another example would be using odor-taste learning or even crossmodal effects to make something (such as a reduced-sugar cookie or hot chocolate) taste sweeter or more chocolately. (See, for example Crisinel and Spence [Reference Crisinel and Spence2010] for discussion of implicit associations between flavors and sounds that might be exploited to affect how a cookie tastes to a subject, or how they believe or report it to taste.) Such effects can be used in ‘sonic seasoning’, as demonstrated in, for example, ‘Why you Should Listen To Your Food’, an episode of the Sporkful podcast (Saini, Reference Saini2016). If this were successful, then we could be nudged into eating more of the reduced-sugar cookies, or choosing them again, or choosing them instead of some alternative.

The psychological quirks exploited in gastrophysical nudges such as these are in the first instance quirks in perceptual processing, or in the formation of perceptual beliefs. That makes them a bit different to typical nudges or nudge-like interferences, since what the interference will in the first place target is not a choice but a perceptual experience, such as a taste experience of sweetness, or a belief formed on the basis of (apparently) taking one's taste experience at face value. For example, if odor-taste learning really does change perceptual experience, then exploiting the learned association between vanilla and sweetness, or creating an association between vegetable flavors and sweetness, is to make use of taste illusions. If a gastrophysical nudges exploited, instead, crossmodal effects on taste then arguably (see section 2.3) that might not make use of taste illusion, but merely affect our beliefs about how things taste. For example, a café might nudge us into buying more of a low-quality hot chocolate by serving it in orange mugs, so that we believe it tastes more chocolatey to us than it in fact does.

It seems likely that when they are effective, gastrophysical nudges will affect perceptual experience or perceptual belief negatively: that is, by yielding illusion or false belief. In the first of our examples, the vegetables come to taste (gustatorily appear) to have a flavor to the children that they do not have. In a crossmodal example, perhaps the hot chocolate tastes as chocolatey as it otherwise might, but we believe it to be more chocolatey in an orange mug. In turn, the subject's choices are affected: they eat or buy more of the relevant product than they would have, or choose it over others. In either case, the important point is that the nudge will be effective precisely because it undermines taste's epistemic power: either an illusion is induced, in which case the subject would form a false belief if they took their experience at face value, or they would be prevented from taking their (accurate) experience at face value and end up with a false belief that way.

Because they function by undermining taste's epistemic power, gastrophysical nudges fall foul of both of the ethically relevant factors outlined in 4.1. Firstly, gastrophysical nudges would not be transparent. In functioning by creating illusions or false beliefs about experience they would build in obstacles to the subject being able to spot the interference to which they are subject. For one, a person with normal capacities for awareness and attention will not recognize the illusion or induced false belief and so will not be in a position to (for example) reject the vegetables as they otherwise would have done. In addition, the subject faces the additional obstacle of its seeming to them that they are merely responding to how the world is revealed to them in perceiving: that is, it seems to them, when they are subject to the gastrophysical nudge, as if they are merely exercising the epistemic power of taste and on that basis choosing.

In that they are non-transparent, gastrophysical nudges are also difficult to resist: as shown above, it is transparency that allows for easy resistibility. And that means that these they would fall foul of the first our two factors also: they would be ‘substantially controlling’ and a threat to liberty. Again, the fact that these nudges function to undermine taste's epistemic power means that they do this in a distinctive way, and that the way in which they are thus manipulative is likewise distinctive. In the case of typical nudges that primarily target choices or decisions, the threat to autonomy, if there is one, comes in the following form: your will is subject to someone else's will. You choose o or you choose to φ not because you will it but because someone else wills that you will it. Thus the rational process of decision making is perverted or subverted. With gastrophysical nudges, the threat is different. Perception and belief are not subject to the will in the way that decisions are. So when your belief or perceptual experience is subject to someone else's will in a gastrophysical nudge, it is not your will that is thus subject. Rather, that which would usually be a manifestation of sensitivity to how things are in the world has become subject to another's will. It is precisely that rational process that is the exercise of taste's epistemic power is undermined.

In the previous section, I showed that there is a way in which it does not matter that taste's epistemic power is frequently undermined, because our contemporary interest in taste is often aesthetic rather that epistemic or practical. Gastrophysical nudges fall foul of conditions relevant to the permissibility of nudging and are manipulative, precisely because they function by undermining taste's epistemic power. That is enough for us to conclude that there is after all a way in which this undermining matters: it is not all good news. That is not, however, to say that gastrophysical nudges are always ethically impermissible: there are other factors that can make even a manipulative interference morally permissible. But that does not undermine our conclusion: even when other factors render a gastrophysical nudge all-things-considered permissible, it still matters if it is manipulative, and we should still prefer a non-manipulative intervention, holding all other factors steady. It thus matters that taste's epistemic power is undermined in the context of these behavioral interventions, and the fact that contemporary interest in taste is frequently aesthetic should not make us wholly comfortable with its undermining. I end by considering an objection.

4.3. Ordinary Manipulation?

Sunstein points out that we should not object to a nudge on the grounds of manipulation if it does not ‘diverge from the kinds of influence that are common and unobjectionable in everyday life’ (Reference Sunstein2015: 448). As I said above, I am not claiming that manipulative nudges are impermissible, only that whether they are or are not manipulative is relevant to their permissibility. Still, we might wonder, with Sunstein, whether the level or kind of manipulation in gastrophysical nudges is of a kind that we generally find acceptable. If it were, then the ethical significance of the undermining of taste's epistemic power that they involve would be vanishingly small at best, and we might wonder whether it matters after all. I offer three responses to this objection.

First, it is not clear that Sunstein draws the line between acceptable and unacceptable manipulation in the right place. He writes:

Much of modern advertising is directed at System 1, with attractive people, bold colors, and distinctive aesthetics. (Consider advertisements for Viagra.) Cellphone companies, restaurants, and clothing stores use music and colors in a way that is designed to ‘frame’ products in a distinctive manner. Doctors, friends, and family members (including spouses) often do something quite similar. Is romance an exercise in manipulation? Maybe so. Is medical care? Is the use of social media? A great deal of conduct, however familiar, can be counted as manipulative in some relevant sense, but it would be extreme to condemn it for that reason. (Reference Sunstein2015: 445)

But I think many of us are affronted when we discover the use made by advertisers of—for example—music and color to persuade us to buy things, especially when, on reflection, we suspect that we have been led to buy that which we otherwise would not have. Sunstein's parenthetical example—pharmaceutical advertising—sounds especially uncomfortable to a reader from the United Kingdom, where (as in many other places) direct-to-consumer advertising of prescription pharmaceuticals is not legal.

Second, sometimes, when we take something manipulative to be acceptable, we do so because other factors such as benign intent or our having consented to be manipulated make the activity permissible on balance: it is not that the level or kind of manipulation involved is of a kind that we generally find acceptable. Some manipulative gastrophysical nudges might be on balance permissible if, for example, they are effective and the intent behind them is benign, or if we have consented to them. Also relevant in the cases Sunstein mentions is who is responsible for the manipulation in question: perhaps we are tolerant of some kinds of manipulation from friends, romantic partners and caregivers because our relationships with them are ones of trust. We mind less if we and our rational capacities are subject to their will because it is partly constitutive of our relationships with them that they take on our interests as their own. We are not in the same relationship with those who are likely to subject us to gastrophysical nudges: food and drink producers and sellers and public health organizations.

Thirdly and most importantly, it is not clear that the level of manipulation that would be involved in gastrophysical nudges is ‘the kind of influence that is common’ in the contexts mentioned. For one, gastrophysical nudges employ specialist knowledge of quirks in human perceptual processing. There is, intuitively, a difference between presenting an option in an attractive way (getting out the best china, lighting candles, using a friendly tone of voice) and utilizing specialist knowledge of human psychology. All else being equal, the latter constitutes a greater loss of liberty, in part because the more specialist the knowledge required to spot an interference, the less likely it is that we will be in a position to spot it. So, the suggestion that the kind of manipulation involved in gastrophysical nudges is common and unobjectionable does not stand up to scrutiny.

Conclusion

I have argued that taste has the same kind of epistemological power that sight does: when all goes well, one can take taste experience at face value, and thus know about features of the world. In our contemporary environment, that power often goes unexercised, but because our interest in taste is frequently aesthetic rather than epistemic or practical, this matters less than it would in the case of sight. This tells us something interesting about the role that taste has come to have in our lives: it has lost some of its practical usefulness and come to have significantly aesthetic import. But that does not mean that undermining taste's epistemic power does not matter at all. If gastrophysical effects are put to use in nudging then it matters ethically precisely because that would involve undermining taste's epistemic power.

Footnotes

Thanks to two anonymous reviewers for their comments and suggestions and to various audiences who have given me invaluable feedback, including students at my department's weekend away in 2019.

References

Akbari, Mehdi, Eskandari, Mohammad Hadi, and Davoudi, Zahra. (2019) ‘Application and Functions of Fat Replacers in Low-Fat Ice Cream: A Review’. Trends in Food Science and Technology, 86, 3440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aydede, Murat. (2009) ‘Is Feeling Pain the Perception of Something?’ Journal of Philosophy, 106, 531–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batty, Clare. (2010) ‘A Representational Account of Olfactory Experience’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 40, 511–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bovens, Luc. (2008) ‘The Ethics of Nudge’. In Grüne-Yanoff, Till and Hansson, Sven Ove (eds.), Preference Change: Approaches from Philosophy, Economics and Psychology (Dordrecht: Springer), 207–19.Google Scholar
Chattopadhyay, Sanchari, Raychaudhuri, Utpal, and Chakraborty, Runu. (2014) ‘Artificial Sweeteners—A Review’. Journal of Food Science and Technology, 51, 611–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crane, Tim. (2007) ‘Wine as an Aesthetic Object’. In Smith, Barry C. (ed.), Questions of Taste: The Philosophy of Wine (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 141–56.Google Scholar
Crisinel, Anne-Sylvie, and Spence, Charles. (2010) ‘As Bitter as a Trombone: Synesthetic Correspondences in Nonsynesthetes between Tastes/Flavors and Musical Notes’. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 72, 19942002.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Crowther, Thomas. (2009) ‘Watching, Sight, and the Temporal Shape of Perceptual Activity’. Philosophical Review, 118, 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Havermans, Remco C., and Jansen, Anita. (2007) ‘Increasing Children's Liking of Vegetables through Flavour-Flavour Learning’. Appetite, 48, 259–62.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Isaac, Alistair M. C. (2014) ‘Structural Realism for Secondary Qualities’. Erkenntnis, 79, 481510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Isaac, Alistair M. C. (2017) ‘Hubris to Humility: Tonal Volume and the Fundamentality of Psychophysical Qualities’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 65/66, 99111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Johnson, J., and Clydesdale, F. M.. (1982) ‘Perceived Sweetness and Redness in Colored Sucrose Solutions’. Journal of Food Science, 47, 747–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplish, Lalita. (2013) ‘Diagnosing Diabetes: A Wee Taste of Honey’. Wellcome Library Blog, November 14, 2013, http://blog.wellcomelibrary.org/2013/11/diagnosing-diabetes-a-wee-taste-of-honey/.Google Scholar
Korsmeyer, Carolyn. (1999) Making Sense of Taste: Food and Philosophy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Leddington, Jason P. (2019) ‘Sounds Fully Simplified’. Analysis, 79, 621–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lucca, Paula A., and Tepper, Beverly J.. (1994) ‘Fat Replacers and the Functionality of Fat in Foods’. Trends in Food Science and Technology, 5, 1219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lycan, William G. (2018) ‘What Does Taste Represent?’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 96, 2837.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macpherson, Fiona. (2012) ‘Cognitive Penetration of Colour Experience: Rethinking the Issue in Light of an Indirect Mechanism’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84, 2462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Matthen, Mohan. (2021) ‘Can Food Be Art in Virtue of Its Savour Alone?’ Crítica, 53, 95125.Google Scholar
Meadows, Phillip John. (2018) ‘In Defense of Medial Theories of Sound’. American Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 293302.Google Scholar
Meskin, Aaron. (2018) ‘Eating, Drinking and Imagining’. The Junkyard (blog), May 2, 2018, https://junkyardofthemind.com/blog/2018/4/30/eating-drinking-and-imagining.Google Scholar
Mizrahi, Vivian. (2014) ‘Sniff, Smell, and Stuff’. Philosophical Studies, 171, 233–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Brien-Nabors, Lyn. (2016) Alternative Sweeteners. 4th ed. Boca Raton: CRC Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Callaghan, Casey. (2007) Sounds: A Philosophical Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peng, Xingyun, and Yao, Yuan. (2017) ‘Carbohydrates as Fat Replacers’. Annual Review of Food Science and Technology, 8, 331–51.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Richardson, Louise. (2013) ‘Bodily Sensation and Tactile Perception’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86, 134–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roberts, Tom. (2016) ‘A Breath of Fresh Air: Absence and the Structure of Olfactory Perception’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 97, 400–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenthal, David M. (2005) Consciousness and Mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Saghai, Yashar. (2013) ‘Salvaging the Concept of Nudge’. Journal of Medical Ethics, 39, 487–93.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Saini, Anne Noyes. (2016). ‘Why You Should Listen to Your Food’. The Sporkful with Dan Pashman (podcast), January 18, 2016, http://www.sporkful.com/why-you-should-listen-to-your-food/.Google Scholar
Siegel, Susanna. (2012) ‘Cognitive Penetrability and Perceptual Justification’. Nous, 46, 201–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Barry. C. (2013) ‘The Nature of Sensory Experience: The Case of Taste and Tasting’. Phenomenology and Mind, 4, 293313.Google Scholar
Spence, Charles (2015) ‘Multisensory Flavor Perception’. Cell, 161, 2435.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spence, Charles. (2017) Gastrophysics: The New Science of Eating. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
Spence, Charles, Auvray, Malika, and Smith, Barry C.. (2015) ‘Confusing Tastes with Flavours’. In Stokes, Dustin, Matthen, Mohan, and Biggs, Stephen (eds.), Perception and its Modalities (New York: Oxford University Press), 247–74.Google Scholar
Stevenson, Richard. J. (2001a) ‘Associative Learning and Odor Quality Perception: How Sniffing an Odor Mixture Can Alter the Smell of Its Parts’. Learning and Motivation, 32, 154–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, Richard J. (2001b) ‘Is Sweetness Taste Enhancement Cognitively Impenetrable? Effects of Exposure, Training and Knowledge’. Appetite, 36, 241–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, Richard J. (2009) The Psychology of Flavour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stevenson, Richard J., and Boakes, Robert A.. (2003) ‘A Mnemonic Theory of Odor Perception’. Psychological Review, 110, 340–64.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Stevenson, Richard J., Prescott, John, and Boakes, Robert A.. (1995) ‘The Acquisition of Taste Properties by Odors’. Learning and Motivation, 26, 433–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stokes, Dustin. (2013) ‘Cognitive Penetrability of Perception’. Philosophy Compass, 8, 646–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sunstein, Cass R. (2015) ‘The Ethics of Nudging’. Yale Journal on Regulation, 32, 413–50.Google Scholar
Thaler, Richard H., and Sunstein, Cass R.. (2008) Nudge: Improving Decisions about Health, Wealth and Happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Todd, Cain. (2014) The Philosophy of Wine: A Case of Truth, Beauty and Intoxication. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Travis, Charles. (2004) ‘The Silence of the Senses’. Mind, 113, 5794.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urmson, J. O. (1957) ‘What Makes a Situation Aesthetic?’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 31, 75106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilkinson, T. M. (2013) ‘Nudging and Manipulation’. Political Studies, 61, 341–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, Benjamin D., Keller, Andreas, and Rosenthal, David M.. (2014) ‘Quality-Space Theory in Olfaction’. Frontiers in Psychology, 5. https://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00001.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed