Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-s22k5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-09T13:38:40.290Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Building verbs in Chuj: Consequences for the nature of roots

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 March 2018

JESSICA COON*
Affiliation:
McGill University
*
Author’s address: McGill University, 1085 Ave. Dr. Penfield, Montreal, QC H3A 1A7, Canadajessica.coon@mcgill.ca
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper offers an in-depth look at roots and verb stem morphology in Chuj (Mayan) in order to address a larger question: when it comes to the formation of verb stems, what information is contributed by the root, and what is contributed by the functional heads? I show first that roots in Chuj are not acategorical in the strict sense (cf. Borer 2005), but must be grouped into classes based on their stem-forming possibilities. Root class does not map directly to surface lexical category, but does determine which functional heads (i.e. valence morphology) may merge with the root. Second, I show that while the introduction of the external argument, along with clausal licensing and agreement generally, are all governed by higher functional heads, the presence or absence of an internal argument is dictated by the root. Specifically, I show that transitive roots in Chuj always combine with an internal argument, whether it be (i) a full DP, (ii) a bare pseudo-incorporated NP, or (iii) an implicit object in an antipassive. In the spirit of work such as Levinson (2007, 2014), I connect this to the semantic type of the root; root class reflects semantic type, and semantic type affects the root’s combinatorial properties. This work also contributes to the discussion of how valence morphology operates. In line with works such as Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou & Schäfer (2006), I argue that valence morphology applies directly to roots, rather than to some ‘inherent valence’ of a verb.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2018 

1 Introduction

This paper examines roots and verb stem formation through a detailed look at verb stems in Chuj, a Q’anjob’alan Mayan language of Guatemala. Following a range of recent work, I assume that verbs are created in the syntax by combining a root with one or more functional heads (see, e.g., Halle & Marantz Reference Halle and Marantz1993, Marantz Reference Marantz, Dimitriadis, Siegen, Surek-Clark and Williams1997, Arad Reference Arad2003, Borer Reference Borer2005; and Lois & Vapnarsky Reference Lois, Vapnarsky, Lois and Vapnarsky2006, Lois Reference Lois, Shklovsky, Mateo Pedro and Coon2011 on Mayan in particular). The issue I address here is the division of labor between the root and the functional heads. I argue first that roots in Chuj are not strictly acategorical, but belong to specific root classes. In Chuj, these are minimally transitive (√ TV), intransitive (√ ITV), positional (√ POS), and nominal (√ NOM). However, root classes do not map directly to surface lexical categories (i.e. nouns, adjectives, verbs), but require the addition of functional morphology in order to form surface stems. In other words, a transitive root is not a transitive verb, an intransitive root is not an intransitive verb, and – as we will see below – positional roots do not directly correspond to any surface category (England Reference England1983, Haviland Reference Haviland1994, Henderson Reference Henderson2017).

Here, we focus specifically on the formation of verb stems. Minimally, in addition to the root, Chuj verbs involve a fuctional head which I label v/Voice $^{0}$ . Following Harley (Reference Harley, D’Alessandro, Franco and Gallego2017), I assume that in some languages,  and Voice $^{0}$ heads are bundled into a single, fused head, as shown in (1).

Differences in the choice of v/Voice $^{0}$ head partially determine argument structure properties of the resulting stem. In other words, following Hale & Keyser (Reference Hale and Keyser1993) and subsequent work, argument structure is built up in the syntax.

I show below that the fused v/Voice $^{0}$ head has properties standardly associated with both  and Voice $^{0}$ . As  it selects a root and categorizes the stem as a verb, and, in some cases, it may also assign accusative case to the internal argument.Footnote [2] Like Voice $^{0}$ , the bundled v/Voice $^{0}$ is responsible for introducing the external argument (Kratzer Reference Kratzer, Rooryck and Zaring1996), and certain v/Voice $^{0}$ heads may also assign abstract (inherent ergative) case to this argument (see, e.g., Mahajan Reference Mahajan, Laka and Mahajan1989, Nash Reference Nash and Kusumoto1996, Woolford Reference Woolford1997), discussed further below. However, I argue that it is the root itself that determines whether it semantically composes with (i.e. selects) an internal argument, and that this requirement cannot be undone later in the derivation. This division of labor between roots and functional heads with respect to argument introduction and licensing is summarized in (2).

Following work such as Levinson (Reference Levinson2007, Reference Levinson2014), I propose that differences in the combinatorial properties of roots are connected to their semantic differences (see also other references and discussion in Alexiadou, Borer & Schäfer Reference Alexiadou, Borer and Schäfer2014). Specifically, I argue that the core Chuj root classes described below can be at least partially distinguished based on their semantic types, as shown in (3).

Transitive and intransitive roots always combine with an internal argument to yield an event predicate, discussed further below; transitive roots may then be directly selected by transitive v/Voice $^{0}$ , which introduces the external argument. This is in line with the proposal by Davis (Reference Davis, Mendikoetxea and Uribe-Etxebarria1997) that all predicates are based on roots that are associated with a single, internal argument. I assume that unlike √ ITV roots, the events denoted by √ TVs are compatible with external causation by an agent (Levin & Rappaport-Hovav Reference Levin and Rappaport-Hovav1995), although I leave aside how this should be formalized. Following Henderson (Reference Henderson2017), positional roots denote measure functions of type ${<}e,<s,d>>$ and require further derivation in order to be inflected, discussed briefly in Section 2.4.

The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. Section 2 provides necessary background information on roots and stem formation in Chuj. In Section 3, I focus on one particular v/Voice $^{0}$ head in Chuj: the incorporation antipassive suffix -w. This suffix attaches to a variety of roots, always forming an agentive intransitive stem (glossed -ag), as shown by the forms in (4).Footnote [3] Although the roots in (4a–c) belong to different categories, the result in all cases is an intransitive verb stem with a single, agentive, argument. These different but related uses of the suffix -w have been noted in Chuj (Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013), as well as for the cognate form in Popti’ (Day Reference Day1973, Craig Reference Craig and Martin1979).

I argue below that -w is a v/Voice $^{0}$ head that attaches to a root and introduces the external argument in its specifier position. However, unlike regular transitive v/Voice $^{0}$ , -w does not assign inherent ergative case. Intransitivity of the resulting stem is indirectly ensured via the limited number of licensing heads in the clause (i.e. only finite Infl $^{0}$ is present). I provide a syntax and semantics for -w stems, arguing that the presence or absence of an internal argument is a direct requirement of the type of root: transitive roots like xik in (4a) must combine with a complement; nominal and positional roots in (4b–c) do not.

In Section 4, through a comparison with other voice and valence morphology in Chuj, I further develop the argument that part of the information that the root provides is whether or not it combines with an internal argument. I characterize this as a semantic requirement, relating to the semantic type of the root (as in (3) above). For transitive roots, I show that there are three options for verbal surface stem formation: (i) a transitive stem with a full DP internal argument; (ii) an incorporation antipassive with a bare NP internal argument ((4a) above); and (iii) an absolutive antipassive with an implicit and existentially bound internal argument. Chuj’s rich morphology shows us that there is no option in which a transitive root does not semantically compose with some sort of complement. Although the focus here is on Chuj, this outcome has potential consequences for the nature of roots cross-linguistically, as well as the role of valence morphology in the derivation, discussed in Sections 4 and 5.

2 Roots and stems in Chuj

Chuj is a member of the Q’anjob’alan branch of the Mayan language family spoken by around 70,000 people in the department of Huehuetenango in Guatemala (Piedrasanta Reference Piedrasanta2009, Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013). Data presented here, unless otherwise cited, are from the San Mateo Ixtatán variant. For general Chuj background, see also Hopkins (Reference Hopkins1967), Domingo Pascual (Reference Domingo Pascual2007), García Pablo (Reference García Pablo2007), and Buenrostro (Reference Buenrostro2013).

As in other Mayan languages, roots in Chuj are overwhelmingly CVC in shape (although other forms, especially for nominal and adjectival roots, also exist; see Hopkins Reference Hopkins1967: Chapter 2). Here, we will be concerned primarily with four classes of roots, distinguishable by their formal inflectional and derivational properties: (i) transitive roots (√ TV); (ii) intransitive roots (√ ITV); (iii) positional roots (√ POS); and (iv) nominal roots (√ NOM).Footnote [4] Examples are shown in (5).

Nominal roots may typically appear underived directly in nominal contexts (e.g. in argument position, possessed, following prepositions, with classifiers) and are not discussed in detail here. In the remainder of this section, I review some formal diagnostics for distinguishing among the first three categories.

As foreshadowed above, it is important to highlight the distinction between these four classes of roots, on the one hand, and classes of inflectable stems, on the other (see also Haviland Reference Haviland1994, Henderson Reference Henderson2017). For example, all four types of root have the ability to appear in intransitive stem forms, but they each require different types of morphology in order to do so. We thus draw a distinction between intransitive roots (roots that behave as a class in terms of morphology needed to form stems) and intransitive stems (inflectable verb stems that combine with a single argument).

The basic template for a Chuj verb stem is shown in (6). Obligatorily, we find a root, which I argue combines minimally with a v/Voice $^{0}$ head. These v/Voice $^{0}$ heads typically have the shape of a single consonant in Chuj, although they are null in several specific environments, discussed below.

Core argument structural properties are determined by the root together with the v/Voice $^{0}$ head in (6), which form the main focus of the sections below. The stem if suffixed by a ‘status suffix’ and preceded by person $/$ number ( $\unicode[STIX]{x1D719}$ ) and TAM (primarily aspectual) inflection, discussed below. See England & Zavala (Reference England, Zavala and Aronoff2013), Bennett, Coon & Henderson (Reference Bennett, Coon and Henderson2016), and Aissen, England & Maldonado (Reference Aissen, England and Maldonado2017) for recent overviews of Mayan grammar.

2.1 Intransitive stems

Intransitive roots can be described as roots that appear without an overt v/Voice $^{0}$ suffix in intransitive stem forms, as in (7). Here and below, I do not parse out a null v/Voice $^{0}$ morpheme, but I assume that a ‘Ø’ v/Voice $^{0}$ head is present.

Intransitive stems are marked by the intransitive status suffix -i in perfective and imperfective aspects (7a–b), and the irrealis -ok in the prospective aspect (7c).Footnote [5] The status suffix -i is dropped when the stem is not phrase final (see Dayley Reference Dayley1981, Henderson Reference Henderson2012, Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013), unless its omission would result in a final complex coda (Mateo Pedro Reference Mateo Pedro2011), discussed below (see footnote 9). Compare (8a), in which -i is dropped, with the form in (8b), in which the subject appears preverbally and -i is not dropped.

The single argument of the intransitive stem is cross-referenced with an absolutive morpheme, known as ‘Set B’ in Mayanist literature. The Set B marker attaches to the stem-initial aspect marker, as shown in the forms in (7) above. As in other Mayan languages, there is no overt third person singular Set B marker.

Other types of roots may also appear in intransitive stem forms, but require the presence of overt derivational suffixes, to which we return below. The intransitive stem template is shown in (9). Intransitive stems share a common inflectional exterior: TAM, Set B (possibly null), and the status suffix -i (possibly dropped). √ ITV roots appear directly in this frame (9a), while other types of roots must be derived via overt morphology in order to appear in the intransitive stem (9b).

2.2 Transitive stems

Transitive roots may appear directly in transitive stem forms, as in (10).

The transitive root appears with the transitive status suffix -V’ in perfective, imperfective, and prospective aspects; the suffix is -a’ for roots with non-back vowels [a], [e], and [i], and harmonic with the root vowel for roots with [o] and [u] vowels. As with the intransitive suffix, the transitive status suffix is dropped when the stem is not phrase-final. Transitive stems appear with two person $/$ number-marking morphemes: objects are marked with Set B clitics (null for third person) and transitive subjects are cross-referenced with Set A (ergative) prefixes.

In Mayanist literature, a division is drawn between ‘root transitive’ stems, like the ones in (10), and ‘derived transitive’ stems (see, e.g., Coon Reference Coon2016). Root transitives are formed directly from transitive roots, while derived transitives are formed from other types of roots and appear with a special status suffix, -ej, shown in (11).

These derived transitives include both transitives derived by overt morphology, as in (11a), as well as a number of zero-derived forms, often denominals, as with the nominal root tz’ib’ ‘letters, writing’ in (11b). Note that the transitive suffix -V’ does not co-occur with -ej, and -ej is not dropped phrase-finally.

Root and derived transitive templates are given in (12).

2.3 Verbal stem summary

The TAM markers and ‘status suffixes’ seen to this point are summarized in the table in (13).Footnote [6]

The suffixes in (13) are listed together here for ease of reference, but note that they do not form a unified category, and it is not clear that they serve a specific derivational ‘function’. While -i and -V’ appear only in phrase-final position, -ej is never dropped. The intransitive suffix is replaced with -ok in irrealis contexts like the prospective ol, but the other two suffixes are not. Furthermore, while both -i and -ej appear on stem forms that have been derived, -V’ only appears immediately following transitive roots.

This is in keeping with the description of so-called ‘status suffixes’ in works such as Henderson (Reference Henderson2012). As Henderson notes, Mayan status suffixes do not alter the transitivity of a stem, but rather ‘reflect valency information already available from the lexical content of the predicate, or from a combination of lexical information and derivational morphology’ (Henderson Reference Henderson2012: 747). While the choice of status suffix depends on properties like transitivity, TAM, and clause type, this information is generally also represented elsewhere – for example in the stem-initial TAM marker. Following Clemens & Coon (Reference Clemens and Coonto appear), and consistent with the order of morphemes on the stem, I locate the status suffix in the head of a projection at the top edge of the verbal maximal projection, above VoiceP, in a projection labelled ‘ssP’. I tentatively assume that the choice of suffix may be determined by selection, but leave a full analysis of the role of status suffixes as a topic for future work. We return to verb stem structure below in Section 3.

2.4 Positional roots

Positionals form a distinct class of roots throughout the Mayan family, distinguishable by their special stem-forming morphology as well as their meaning (see, e.g., Haviland Reference Haviland1994, Henderson Reference Henderson2016, Reference Henderson2017). Semantically, they typically make reference to position, shape, aggregation, or surface quality. Henderson (Reference Henderson2016: 585) writes that positionals ‘lexicalize interval states (sitting, standing, lying down, etc.) as well as gradable properties (broken, fat, flexible, etc.)’. For Tsotsil, Haviland (Reference Haviland1994: 733) refers to an apparent ‘preoccupation with space, shape, and configuration’, reflected in the large class of positional roots. For Chuj, Hopkins (Reference Hopkins1967: 76) notes that positional roots may be ‘distinguished from other form classes by a number of derivational reduplication processes which occur with no other form class’.

Positionals are a class of roots, but there is no special class of positional surface stems (see, e.g., England Reference England1983, Haviland Reference Haviland1994, contra Evans & Levinson Reference Evans and Levinson2009). Positional roots in Chuj may be identified by their ability to form stative (aspectless or ‘non-verbal’) predicates through the addition of the suffix -an, often accompanied by a directional particle, as in (14).

Henderson (Reference Henderson2017) argues that positional roots in Kaqchikel denote measure functions and that they must always be derived into a relational expression before they may be inflected. Indeed, in order to form eventive transitive or intransitive predicates, positional roots in Chuj must always appear with one or more of a number of derivational suffixes, followed by the appropriate status suffix (-i for intransitives or -ej for transitives). In other words, positional roots follow the templates for derived intransitive and transitive stems in (9b) and (12b) above.Footnote [7]

While the tripartite division among intransitive, transitive, and positional roots above is a useful point of departure, in some cases, a given root may not belong clearly to one or another class, or may belong to multiple classes (Haviland Reference Haviland1994, Lois Reference Lois, Shklovsky, Mateo Pedro and Coon2011). This is particularly true in the case of transitive and positional roots, which appear to share certain derivational possibilities across the Mayan family (see Haviland Reference Haviland1994, Coon & Preminger Reference Coon, Preminger, Avelino, Coon and Norcliffe2009, and Henderson Reference Henderson2016, Reference Henderson2017), as well as in Chuj in particular (Hopkins Reference Hopkins1967). Nonetheless, canonical positional roots may be distinguished from transitive roots by the former’s inability to form transitive stems without the presence of overt derivational morphology. I focus on canonical cases here, setting aside the puzzle of what Haviland (Reference Haviland1994) terms ‘mixed categories’ for future work.

2.5 Summary

In addition to providing an introduction to roots and stem-formation in Chuj, this section underscores the importance of distinguishing between, for example, an intransitive root and an intransitive stem. As seen above, Chuj roots may be classed according to their formal derivational behavior, and, to some extent, their semantics (see (3) above). However, roots do not inflect directly for person $/$ number and temporal information. Rather, additional morphology is required to form stems, and a single root may enter into a variety of different stem forms through the addition of the ‘derivational’ (v/Voice $^{0}$ ) and ‘status’ suffixes seen above. Thus, while roots in Chuj clearly belong to root classes, these classes do not directly correspond to surface lexical categories. Below, I argue that a transitive root (√ TV), for example, requires exactly as much derivation to form a verbal surface stem as a nominal root (√ NOM) does. In the sections that follow, we look in more detail at morphology used to form verb stems in order to address the question of what information is contributed by the root and what is contributed by the functional heads.

3 Agentive intransitives

In this section, we examine the derivation of agentive intransitive stems (i.e. intransitives with an agentive subject) through a look at two constructions in which the suffix -w attaches directly to roots: unergatives (Section 3.1) and the ‘incorporation antipassive’ (Section 3.2). I argue here that -w serves the same function in each: it categorizes the stem as a verb and introduces – but does not assign ergative case to – an external argument. The result is that nominal and positional roots form verbal (agentive intransitive) stems in the same way that transitive roots do. This is illustrated by the intransitive stem forms in (16), repeated from (4) above.

A crucial difference among the forms in (16) is in the presence or absence of an internal argument: the transitive root in (16a) obligatorily appears with a nominal complement, even in an intransitive stem form (Section 3.2; see Maxwell Reference Maxwell1976), while the stems formed from nominal and positional roots in (16b–c), discussed in Section 3.1, do not. I argue that this difference is the result of different semantic requirements of the roots: transitive roots must combine directly with a nominal complement, while nominal and positional roots may not. Section 3.3 examines √ ITV roots, the only class of roots to which -w may not attach.

3.1 Unergatives

Many agentive intransitives in Chuj are formed from nominal roots with the suffix -w.Footnote [8] Examples of denominal -w verbs and their corresponding nominal roots are shown in (17).

Note that verbs borrowed from Spanish – for example karrel from the Spanish infinitive form correr ‘to run’ – enter Chuj as nominals and must be derived into verb forms (also discussed in Haviland Reference Haviland1994 for Tsotsil and Coon Reference Coon2013 for Ch’ol). These borrowed forms suggest that the -w process is at least semi-productive, and not restricted to frozen lexical items (cf. Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013). However, the process is not entirely productive (i.e. many nominal roots may not appear with -w), and, as the forms above indicate, the meaning of the resulting verb stem is not necessarily predictable from the meaning of the nominal root. I take this to be compatible with the proposal that the v/Voice $^{0}$ head instantiated by -w merges directly with the root, formalized below, within the domain of special meaning (Arad Reference Arad2003).

Examples of underived nominal roots in nominal environments are shown in (18); the corresponding intransitive -w stems are in (19).Footnote [9]

Intransitive verb forms are also derived from positional roots (Section 2.4), as in the table in (20). The verbal stem form indicates some kind of movement in the position denoted by the positional root.

Recall that positional roots in Chuj may be identified by their ability to form stative predicates with -an. Examples of positional roots in stative -an stems are given in (21); the same roots in intransitive verb stems with -w are shown in (22).

These stems fit the pattern of intransitive stems in Chuj identified in Section 2.1 above: they have a single argument, marked with Set B $/$ absolutive (null for third person singular). They also appear with the intransitive status suffix -i in the perfective and imperfective aspects (22a), and with the irrealis -ok in the prospective (22b). I propose that  stems like the one in (23a) have the structure in (23b).

Specifically, the suffix -w occupies a bundled v/Voice $^{0}$ head (Pylkkänen Reference Pylkkänen2002, Harley Reference Harley, D’Alessandro, Franco and Gallego2017), which merges directly with the root, categorizing the stem as verbal and introducing the external argument in its specifier position (along the lines of Kratzer Reference Kratzer, Rooryck and Zaring1996). The ‘status suffix’ occupies the highest head in the verbal projection, labelled ssP (Clemens & Coon Reference Clemens and Coonto appear). The root undergoes successive head movement through v/Voice $^{0}$ to , resulting in basic verb-initial order (discussed in Section 3.2), and forming the verb stem; the order of morphemes is in line with the Mirror Principle (Baker Reference Baker1988). The TAM particle is located in Infl $^{0}$ (Aissen Reference Aissen1992), which cliticizes to the verb stem.

While both agentive intransitive -w and regular transitive v/Voice $^{0}$ heads introduce an external argument in their specifier position, agentive intransitive -w differs in a crucial respect: transitive v/Voice $^{0}$ assigns inherent ergative case to the argument in its specifier, while -w v/Voice $^{0}$ does not (see, e.g., Woolford Reference Woolford1997, Legate Reference Legate2008 and works cited there on inherent ergative).Footnote [10] Following Coon Reference Coon2017, I assume that Set A (ergative) agreement goes hand-in-hand with inherent ergative case assignment; the ergative prefix represents the spell-out of features of the external argument on the verb stem as the result of feature-sharing triggered by inherent case assignment.Footnote [11] As expected, ergative agreement is absent in agentive intransitive forms like (23a). Instead, in -w forms, the single absolutive argument must be licensed by finite Infl $^{0}$ , as shown in (24). Following Coon, Mateo Pedro & Preminger (Reference Coon, Mateo Pedro and Preminger2014) for Q’anjob’al, first and second person Set B morphemes like the one in (19b) are pronominal clitics – they are triggered by agreement with finite Infl $^{0}$ and attach to the TAM head.Footnote [12]

The derivation of an intransitive -w stem in (24) may be contrasted with the proposed derivation of a full transitive in (25); see Coon et al. (Reference Coon, Mateo Pedro and Preminger2014), Armstrong (Reference Armstrong2015), and Clemens & Coon (Reference Clemens and Coonto appear).

Note that in the -w stem above, Infl $^{0}$ licenses the absolutive external argument; in a transitive construction like (25), Infl $^{0}$ licenses the absolutive object (here, I set aside the question of whether the object raises above the subject, as in Coon et al. (Reference Coon, Mateo Pedro and Preminger2014), focusing just on which heads license which arguments). The proposal here is in keeping with the fact that absolutives are consistently licensed by Infl $^{0}$ , that agreement with Infl $^{0}$ results in the Set B clitics, and that both derived and underived intransitive verbs have absolutive (Set B) subjects. These structures will be relevant to the proposal for antipassives discussed in the following section.

3.2 Incorporation antipassives

Chuj has been described as having two types of antipassive (e.g. Maxwell Reference Maxwell1976, Dayley Reference Dayley1981, Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013): (i) an absolutive antipassive and (ii) an incorporation antipassive, -w.Footnote [13] Here, we focus on the latter, returning to the absolutive antipassive in Section 4. A transitive ${\sim}$ incorporation antipassive pair is shown in (26).

In the transitive in (26a), the subject is marked with the Set A (ergative) prefix and, in the absence of post-verbal material, we would find the transitive status suffix -a’ (cf. Tas ix-a-xik-a’? – ‘What did you chop?’). The object in the transitive in (26a) appears with a noun classifier, te’, the classifier for wood-based elements (Hopkins Reference Hopkins2012b, Royer Reference Royer2016). As described for Chuj and other Q’anjob’alan languages (e.g. Craig Reference Craig1986 for Popti’; Zavala Reference Zavala and Senft2000 for Akatek; Royer Reference Royer2016 for Chuj), noun classifiers appear either preceding nominals in referential contexts (27a), or alone functioning as referential pronouns (27b). Although they are not limited to definite contexts (Craig Reference Craig1986, Royer Reference Royer2016), I translate them with the English definite determiner for simplicity, and I assume that they occupy D $^{0}$ .

The transitive in (26a) above has two full arguments, and like other transitive stems, the subject is marked with a morpheme from the Set A (ergative) series (here ko-). Incorporation antipassive forms like the one in (26b), on the other hand, only ever appear with a single person $/$ number-marker on the verb. In (26b), the Set B (absolutive) morpheme -onh cross-references the subject. Although an apparent object appears, here k’atzitz ‘wood’, unlike in (26a), it does not appear with its classifier.

As others have noted (Maxwell Reference Maxwell1976, Dayley Reference Dayley1981, Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013), incorporation antipassive stem forms like the one in (26b) appear with a non-oblique post-nominal ‘object’, but there are restrictions. First, the nominal must be bare and non-referential, and it must appear immediately adjacent to the verb stem. The ‘object’ in an incorporation antipassive may not appear with numerals (28a), demonstratives (28b), or noun classifiers (28c).

The incorporated object may also not be possessed, nor may it be a pronoun, as shown by the ungrammaticality of the forms in (29).

However, as Maxwell (Reference Maxwell1976) describes, the object is not restricted to a bare nominal. Certain modifiers may appear with the objects in the incorporation antipassive construction, as in (30).Footnote [14]

Because only a limited number of modifiers may appear in this construction, Maxwell proposes that forms like niwak kaxlan ‘fat chicken’ in (30) are actually compounds. I suggest instead that modifiers that appear in these constructions are Chuj’s true adjectives and sit below D $^{0}$ , while others are relative clauses (‘the one that is X’); this analysis is compatible with diagnostics for distinguishing adjectives from relative clauses in Martínez Cruz (Reference Martínez Cruz2007). Forms like niwak kaxlan in (30) are thus bare NPs (or nPs) of type ${<}$ e,t ${>}$ . Either possibility is compatible with the analysis below.

The apparent object in an incorporation antipassive construction is ‘discourse opaque’ (see Farkas & de Swart Reference Farkas and de Swart2003). As shown by the sequence in (31), the incorporated NP may not be picked up by pronouns later in the discourse. Recall that noun classifiers serve a pronominal function in Q’anjob’alan languages; here, anh is the classifier used for nouns denoting plant-based elements (Craig Reference Craig1986, Hopkins Reference Hopkins2012b, Royer Reference Royer2016).

Following Maxwell (Reference Maxwell1976), we may conclude that these apparent objects in the incorporation antipassive construction are not ‘true nominal arguments’, from either a syntactic or a semantic point of view. I propose a syntax for these constructions in Section 3.2.1 and then turn to the semantics in Section 3.2.2.

3.2.1 Syntax of incorporation antipassives

Recall from the proposed structure in (25) that in a regular Chuj transitive construction, the ergative subject is licensed in situ by v/Voice $^{0}$ , while the transitive object is licensed by finite Infl $^{0}$ . Ergative (Set A) agreement goes hand-in-hand with licensing by v/Voice $^{0}$ , while absolutive (Set B) clitics are the result of licensing by Infl $^{0}$ . Building on Baker (Reference Baker1988), Massam (Reference Massam2001), and others, I assume that the bare ‘incorporated’ (non-argument) object in a Chuj incorporation antipassive construction does not need to be licensed by a functional head (i.e. receive abstract case).

The syntactic picture, then, is much the same as for the unergatives in (23) above, except that here the transitive root selects a nominal complement. The v/Voice $^{0}$ head -w merges the subject in its specifier, but again does not assign inherent ergative case; the single (case-requiring) argument is the subject in Spec,v/VoiceP, which is licensed by Infl $^{0}$ .Footnote [15]

Note that the incorporated object is represented as a complement to the root (see Harley Reference Harley2014). This is an important component of the proposal developed in this paper, in which the requirement to combine with a complement is a necessary semantic property of certain roots, and cannot be undone by higher functional material, discussed further in Section 4.

This structure is consistent with the observation in Buenrostro (Reference Buenrostro2013) that some combinations of root and NP complement receive special meanings in the incorporation antipassive construction. This is expected if the NP combines with the root internal to the first phase (i.e. the domain of special meaning; see, e.g., Arad Reference Arad2003). In (33), for example, the combination of il ‘see’ and the bare object ak’wal ‘night’ results in an idiomatic reading ‘to keep vigil’ (i.e. after someone dies or is very ill).

In further support of the structure in (32), note that if, as proposed here, the suffix -w attaches directly to a root, and not to an already-formed transitive stem, then there should be no way to create an incorporation antipassive from already-derived transitive forms. This prediction is borne out; (34a) is a derived transitive (see Section 2.2), formed from the intransitive root way ‘sleep’. It appears to be impossible to form an incorporation antipassive from a derived transitive stem, and (34b) is ungrammatical regardless of the ordering of suffixes.

This restriction is not particular to the derivational suffix -m (which does not appear to be productive); it is true for any derived transitive form (see Section 2.2).Footnote [16] In (35a), pluractional morphology attaches to the transitive root tzil ‘to tear’. Pluractionals may also not form incorporation antipassives, as in (35b), again regardless of morpheme order.

Although there may be various explanations for the ungrammaticality of (34b) and (35b) – for example, that -w must combine directly with roots, or that the -m and -ch morphemes occupy v/Voice $^{0}$ heads and themselves introduce the external argument – any of these is compatible with the proposal here. Namely, the ‘incorporation antipassive’ does not convert a transitive stem into an intransitive stem, but rather combines directly with a root to introduce the external argument. In contrast, the ungrammaticality of (34b) and (35b) is unexpected under an account in which the function of the ‘antipassive’ is to reduce the valence of a transitive predicate.

Finally, a question remains about how to derive the correct surface order. Basic word order in Chuj is verb-initial. As in other Mayan languags, sentences with two post-verbal DPs are rare in Chuj discourse (see England Reference England1983, Aissen Reference Aissen1992, and Clemens & Coon Reference Clemens and Coonto appear for discussion), and in Chuj there is dialectal variation as to whether VOS or VSO is considered most basic (England Reference England1991). Although I do not have sufficient information on word order in incorporation antipassive in the VSO San Sebastián Coatán variant of Chuj, if it behaves like related VSO languages Q’anjob’al and Popti’ (Baquiax et al. Reference Baquiax, Mateo, Mejía and Pérez2005, Craig Reference Craig and Martin1979), it would also require the bare NP to be adjacent in the incorporation antipassive.

I suggest here, following the proposal in Clemens (Reference Clemens2014) for incorporation structures in Niuean, and Clemens & Coon (Reference Clemens and Coonto appear) for Mayan, that the verb undergoes regular head movement to the position that hosts the status suffix above the subject, as in the unergatives above (see also Armstrong Reference Armstrong2015 on Yucatec). The bare NP complement is reordered at PF, due to a high-ranked prosodic requirement that the structurally impoverished (D $^{0}$ -less) object be phrased with the verb. This would not have an effect on surface word order for VOS variants of Chuj, but would be important for VSO dialects, which nonetheless require bare NP complements to be stem-adjacent in the incorporation antipassive.Footnote [17] Further work is needed to confirm whether the prosodic predictions made by this account align with the facts in Chuj; see Clemens & Coon (Reference Clemens and Coonto appear) for discussion.

3.2.2 Semantics of incorporation antipassives

From a syntactic point of view, we have an explanation for why the apparent object in an incorporation antipassive construction like (37) must be a bare NP: a full DP object like anh onh cannot be licensed in this construction.

The v/Voice $^{0}$ head -w merges an external argument in its specifier position but does not assign ergative case. Syntactically speaking, intransitivity is ensured by the inability of a full DP object to be licensed in a construction in which inherent ergative is not assigned to the external argument. The external argument is privileged for licensing from Infl $^{0}$ by virtue of being closer – explaining why the single argument of these constructions is the external argument (see Section 4.1 on passives).

From a licensing point of view, we might then expect that we should be able to omit the internal argument altogether. As shown in (38), however, this is impossible: incorporation antipassive constructions require the presence of the bare NP complement.

I propose that this requirement is a semantic requirement: transitive roots like chonh ‘sell’ must semantically compose with a complement due to their semantic type. This is in stark contrast to the -w stems formed from nominal or positional roots, discussed in Section 3.1. These prohibit bare NP complements, as shown by the ungrammaticality of (39a). The grammatical version in (39b) requires a preposition.

Dancing salsa is a perfectly fine thing to do, as shown by (39b), and we will see in Section 4 below that it is possible to sell things without being explicit about what one is selling (cf. (38)). Nonetheless, -w stems formed from transitive roots require a complement (‘incorporation antipassives’), while -w stems formed from nominal and positional roots (‘unergatives’) prohibit one. The difference then lies not in the -w stem as a whole, but in the nature of the root.

In Chuj, we have already seen at least two options for how the complement to a √ TV root can be realized: as a full DP in a transitive construction, or as a bare NP in an incorporation antipassive. I adopt the fairly standard assumption that DPs are entities of type ${<}$ e ${>}$ , whereas NPs are properties of type ${<}$ e,t ${>}$ . I propose that in Chuj, nominals that lack classifiers are bare NPs, while nominals with classifiers are DPs.Footnote [18] As expected, nominals that appear as predicates obligatorily lack a classifier (40a); nominals in referential contexts require a classifier (40b) (Royer Reference Royerto appear).

I assume a Davidsonian event semantics (Davidson Reference Davidson and Rescher1967), and following Kratzer (Reference Kratzer, Rooryck and Zaring1996) and others, I assume that the external argument is not an argument of the ‘verb’ itself, but is added later in the derivation (i.e. via the v/Voice $^{0}$ head in (25) above). A transitive root like chonh ‘sell’ in Chuj is of type ${<}e,<s,t>>$ (see (3) above). It thus requires two arguments: an event argument (e) and the internal theme argument (x), as in (41).

Below, I walk through the derivation first of the transitive root chonh ‘sell’ in a regular transitive with a full DP internal argument, as in (42a), and then of an incorporation antipassive when the root combines with a bare NP complement, as in (42b).

In a regular transitive construction, like the one in (42a), the DP anh onhclf avocado’ is of type ${<}$ e ${>}$ and combines with the root by Functional Application, saturating the root’s theme argument slot, as shown by the derivation in (43).

In an incorporation antipassive like the one in (42b) above, the same transitive root chonh ‘sell’ combines with a bare NP complement; I propose that this bare NP denotes a property and is of semantic type ${<}$ e,t ${>}$ . The NP complement is thus unable to saturate the argument slot of the predicate chonh, but instead restricts the denotation of the predicate – in this case from events of selling to events of avocado-selling. The NP combines via Chung & Ladusaw’s (Reference Chung and Ladusaw2004) operation of Restrict, as in (44b). The argument position remains unfilled, and in Chuj, it is immediately saturated by Existential Closure, as in (44c).Footnote [19] $^{,}$ Footnote [20]

We have thus seen that a transitive root can combine with two types of internal arguments: (i) a full DP by Functional Application, resulting in a transitive construction, and (ii) a bare NP by Restrict followed by Existential Closure, resulting in the incorporation antipassive. In Section 4 below, we examine a third option in the absolutive antipassive construction. We first turn briefly to intransitive √ ITV roots in Section 3.3.

3.3 Unacccusatives

Up to this point, we have seen the suffix -w appear on three of the four types of roots identified above: it appears on nominal and positional roots to form unergative predicates (Section 3.1), and it also appears on transitive roots to form incorporation antipassives (Section 3.2). Some examples are repeated in (45).

The fourth type of root discussed in Section 2.1 above is the class of intransitive √ ITV roots. I propose here that all √ ITV roots are unaccusative and that unergative surface stems are always derived. Although independent unaccusativity diagnostics do not to my knowledge exist, Chuj verbs that correspond to canonical unergatives in languages for which there are such diagnostics are overwhelmingly derived by some sort of suffix or series of suffixes: either the -w described above or one of several other consonantal suffixes (see Hopkins Reference Hopkins1967).

For example, cross-linguistically, unergatives often (though not always) include manner-of-motion verbs, verbs denoting volitional actions, as well as verbs of bodily function (e.g. Perlmutter Reference Perlmutter1978). In Chuj, such verbs are generally morphologically complex in form. Positional roots derive many manner-of-motion verbs, as seen in Section 3.1 above. Additional derived intransitives belonging to these categories are shown in (49).

While many of the putative unergative stems are transparently derived from other roots, for some the source is not transparent (e.g. taj is a nominal root meaning ‘pine’). The proposal that all unergatives in Chuj are derived is in keeping with proposals in which unergative verbs are derived from nominals roots via abstract verbal structure – even in languages that lack morphological evidence for this derivation (Hale & Keyser Reference Hale and Keyser1993, Reference Hale, Keyser, Alsina, Bresnan and Sells1997); see also the discussion of Ch’ol in Section 3.4.2 below and Davis (Reference Davis, Mendikoetxea and Uribe-Etxebarria1997) on St’át’imcets (Salish).Footnote [21]

The class of √ ITV roots, on the other hand, includes verbs of directed motion like b’at ‘go’, ek’ ‘pass’, em ‘descend’, and och ‘enter’, as well as change-of-state verbs like k’ib’ ‘grow’ and cham ‘die’ – forms that we would expect to pattern as unaccusatives if independent diagnostics were found (see also examples in (7) above). These roots are impossible with -w.Footnote [22]

Note that under the analysis presented here, the impossibility of -w on intransitive (i.e. unaccusative) roots is unsurprising: -w is a v/Voice $^{0}$ head that attaches to a root and merges an external argument; the internal argument in a -w stem is either absent entirely in the case of √ NOM and √ POS roots (Section 3.1) or incorporated in stems formed from √ TV roots (Section 3.2). Intransitive √ ITV roots, on the other hand, are unaccusative and combine only with an internal argument. Semantically, I propose that they are of type ${<}e,<s,t>>$ , like transitive roots, as in (3) above; unlike transitive roots, they may not combine with the transitive-forming v/Voice $^{0}$ head which merges an agent (I do not take a particular stance on the source of this distinction). These conflicting requirements then create a licensing problem. The -w v/Voice $^{0}$ head introduces an external argument but does not assign inherent ergative case. The introduced argument must be licensed by finite Infl $^{0}$ , leaving the internal argument of the √ ITV root unlicensed.

One imaginable possibility would be to incorporate the unaccusative subject, alleviating the licensing problem. In Chuj, unaccusatives are unable to incorporate their subjects (a noted point of variation among languages that allow transitive objects to incorporate, described in Mithun Reference Mithun1984). For example, in (48a), the intransitive root ul ‘dissolve’ appears in an intransitive stem with a full DP subject. The ungrammatical example in (48b) attempts to combine the intransitive (unaccusative) root with a bare nominal subject, and then to introduce an external argument via -w.

Although nothing internal to the analysis here would rule out a form like (48b), the absence of unaccusative subject incorporation is unsurprising from a typological perspective.

3.4 Interim summary and a Ch’ol interlude

3.4.1 Summary

In Section 2, we observed that roots in Chuj may be classified by the morphology required to form different types of stems. These root classes, however, do not map directly to surface lexical categories – all surface categories are derived. A transitive root like xik ‘chop’ forms a verbal stem in the same way that a nominal root like chanhal ‘dance’ does: by combining with a functional head labeled v/Voice $^{0}$ . In Section 3, we identified one particular functional v/Voice $^{0}$ head used to derive agentive intransitive verb stems from different classes of roots: the suffix -w. This suffix attaches to roots and introduces an external argument, but – unlike the phonetically null transitive v/Voice $^{0}$ – it does not assign inherent ergative case to the introduced external argument in its specifier position. This is illustrated by the diagram in (49), in which transitive stems, unergative stems, and antipassive stems are all derived directly from the root.

The difference between an ‘unergative’ stem like chanhal-w- and an ‘antipassive’ stem like xik-w- is thus entirely a difference in the nature of the root itself. While nominal roots like chanhal do not semantically compose with an internal argument, I claim that the transitive root xik must. The licensing limitations of -w stem forms ensure that the internal argument may not be a full DP, and that incorporation antipassive stems may thus appear only with bare NP complements. We observe a final option for Chuj transitive roots in Section 4, but first turn briefly to Ch’ol for evidence of the importance of particular v/Voice $^{0}$ heads to argument structure more generally.

As noted above, this analysis is in contrast to a view of antipassives as elements that reduce the valence of an existing stem. While this would seem descriptively to capture the facts in the case of intransitive -w stems formed from transitive roots, it does not explain the function of -w on nominal or positional roots, nor does it explain why -w cannot attach to derived transitives. Rather than reducing the valence of a stem, -w (and other v/Voice $^{0}$ heads described in Section 4) combines with a root to specify the argument structure of the resulting stem. This is in line with existing work that takes voice alternations to be derived from the root (e.g. Alexiadou et al. Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou, Schäfer and Frascarelli2006).

3.4.2 Ch’ol interlude

Although this paper focuses on Chuj, it is worth considering the cross-linguistic implications. Of course, much existing work on argument structure argues for the existence of null functional heads with various argument-introducing and case-assigning possibilities. What would a language look like if it lacked an agentive intransitive v/Voice $^{0}$ head – Chuj’s -w – altogether? I suggest here that Ch’ol, a Mayan language of the Tseltalan branch spoken in Chiapas, Mexico, may be exactly such a language. Notably, in Ch’ol, there is no such thing as an agentive intransitive verb stem (Gutiérrez Sánchez Reference Gutiérrez Sánchez2004, Vázquez Álvarez Reference Vázquez Álvarez2011, Coon Reference Coon2012, Reference Coon2013). Instead, all intransitive surface predicates in Ch’ol are unaccusative.

Constructions that correspond to unergatives involve roots that are called ‘verbal nouns’ in the Ch’ol literature. These forms pass distributional tests for nouns, and require a light verb in order to function as predicates (Gutiérrez Sánchez Reference Gutiérrez Sánchez2004, Coon Reference Coon2010). Examples are shown in (50).

These roots are ungrammatical in intransitive stem forms. Just as in Chuj, Ch’ol roots can be diagnosed by the morphology they require to form surface stems. In (51a), we find the intransitive root majl ‘go’ in an intransitive (unaccusative) surface stem. The nominal root soñ ‘dance’ is ungrammatical in an intransitive surface stem, as shown in (51b). In Chuj, the suffix -w is required to form an intransitive stem from a nominal root, but this suffix – or a functionally equivalent head – is absent in Ch’ol.

In order to serve as predicates, verbal nouns like soñ may appear with a light verb, such as the transitive cha’l in (52a). Alternatively, soñ may appear in a transitive stem with a denominal suffix, as in (52b). In other words, nominal roots like soñ ‘dance’ may form a verb stem in Ch’ol only if an internal argument is present.

The same can be said for transitive roots and antipassives. The Ch’ol transitive root wuts’ ‘wash’ is shown in a transitive stem form with a full DP internal argument in (53a). Ch’ol does have a construction labelled ‘incorporation antipassive’, shown in (53b), but the lexical stem wuts’-pisil is formally a noun, and again a light verb is required.

Surface verb stems in Ch’ol are always either transitive (like (53a)) or unaccusative (like (51a)). Forms that correspond to unergatives and antipassives – in other words, agentive intransitives – surface in nominal stem forms and require a light verb in order to act as predicates. Under the proposal advanced here, this is entirely consistent with the pattern in Chuj. In Chuj, a single v/Voice $^{0}$ head forms agentive intransitive stems from both nominal and transitive roots (see (49) above); it categorizes the stem as a verb, introduces an external argument, and does not assign ergative case. If Chuj lacked this head altogether, we would expect it to lack the means to form verbal agentive intransitive stems – exactly as in Ch’ol.

4 Absolutive antipassives and the content of roots

Recall from Section 3.2 that in the Chuj incorporation antipassive construction, the patient must be a bare nominal, as in (54a). It may not be reintroduced as an oblique, and it may not be omitted entirely, as shown in (54b).

The incorporation antipassive in (54a) stands in contrast to what has been called the ‘absolutive antipassive’ marked with the suffix -waj, shown in (55). As in the incorporation antipassive, these are intransitive verb stems with an agentive subject, marked by Set B (absolutive) morphology. Unlike the incorporation antipassive, however, the theme may be reintroduced as an oblique with the preposition t’a, as in (55a–b), or omitted entirely, as in (55c).Footnote [23]

We thus now have three options for transitive roots appearing in verbal stem forms with external arguments, summarized in (56).

The root may combine with a full DP internal argument, resulting in a regular transitive stem (Section 2.2); it may combine with a bare NP as an incorporation antipassive (Section 3); and, finally, it may optionally combine with an oblique PP. I argue that this latter option involves a semantically available implicit argument, reflected in the morphology I propose a syntax and semantics for this form below.

Specifically, I propose that the absolutive antipassive suffix -waj should be decomposed into two suffixes: the familiar -w, and a suffix -aj which is an overt morphological manifestation of the existential binding of implicit arguments. We first turn to two kinds of passives in Section 4.1 for evidence of the decomposition of -waj, and then to a proposal for the syntax and semantics of these constructions in Section 4.2.

4.1 Two kinds of passive

The reappearance of -w in the absolutive antipassive suffix -waj does not seem to be an accident. Indeed, although some works list -waj as the antipassive suffix, Hopkins (Reference Hopkins1967) decomposes it into -w plus a suffix -aj:

-aj derives intransitive verb stems from verb stems already derived in -t, -ch, -k’, -m, -n, -w, and -l (Hopkins Reference Hopkins1967: 88).

As the above quotation suggests, and as previewed in Section 2 above, the suffix -w is one of a number of consonantal suffixes that attach to roots in order to form stems: CVC-C (see the template in (6) from Section 2 above). The suffix -aj then attaches to some of these CVC-C bases to form an intransitive stem (which then further requires the presence of the intransitive status suffix -i).

Take for example the stem el-k’- ‘steal’. This stem appears to be derived from the intransitive root el ‘to leave’, followed by the derivational suffix -k’. This stem then forms a derived transitive with the suffix -ej, as in (57a). It also forms an intransitive (unaccusative) with the suffix -aj, which is then followed by the intransitive status suffix -i, shown in (57b). Buenrostro (Reference Buenrostro2013) lists -aj as the passive suffix for derived transitives; I gloss -aj as div for ‘derived intransitive’, and propose here that it has a broader use than simply passive.Footnote [24]

Although further work is needed on the large number of stem-forming suffixes described by Hopkins (Reference Hopkins1967), examples like (57b) provide a first clue that -waj should be decomposed into the general ‘agentive intransitive’ suffix -w from Section 3, plus the suffix -aj. Indeed, we find an analogous alternation between a consonantal suffix and a -C-aj suffix in Chuj passives, summarized in (58).

What I label ‘agentless passives’ in Chuj are formed with the suffix -j.Footnote [25] This suffix attaches to transitive roots like man ‘buy’ and choj ‘grind’ in (59) to form an intransitive (unaccusative) stem. As with other intransitive stems in Chuj, the single argument is Set B and the intransitive status suffix -i appears stem-finally.

The agentless passive forms in (59) stand in contrast to passives formed with -chaj, shown in (60). As shown in (64), -chaj attaches to transitive roots – here yam ‘catch’ and mol ‘gather’ – to form an intransitive unaccusative stem. Again, the single argument is marked Set B and the stem is suffixed with -i.

I propose that the difference between agentless passives with -j in (59) and regular passives with -chaj in (60) lies in the presence of an implicit agent. The contrast is comparable to the difference between anticausatives and passives in English (see, e.g., Roeper Reference Roeper1987, Baker, Johnson & Roberts Reference Baker, Johnson and Roberts1989, Levin & Rappaport-Hovav Reference Levin and Rappaport-Hovav1995). In English, for example, the former may appear with agentive by-phrases and agent-oriented adverbs (61a), while the latter may not (61b).

Contrasts such as the one in (61) have been used to argue that passives contain an implicit agent, while anticausatives do not (see Bhatt & Pancheva Reference Bhatt, Pancheva, Everaert and van Riemsdijk2006 and Williams Reference Williams2015 for overviews). I offer a brief sketch of the analyses for the two constructions in Chuj, beginning with the -chaj passive in Section 4.1.1 and turning to the -j agentless passive in Section 4.1.2.

4.1.1 Passives with -chaj

I propose that Chuj -chaj passives have an implicit agent, and – as with -waj above – that the suffix -chaj should be decomposed into a v/Voice $^{0}$ head -ch and the derived intransitive suffix -aj, as illustrated in (62). The suffix -aj is a morphological reflex of the existential binding of the implicit external argument.

As expected under an account in which -chaj passives have an implicit agent, the notional agent can be realized in an oblique phrase: yuj heb’ ix in (62), on par with the English example in (61a). As in other Mayan languages, oblique phrases in Chuj are generally introduced by one of a set of what are called ‘relational nouns’. The relational noun shows Set A agreement with the DP it introduces. The form -uj (or -u’uj) can be translated roughly as ‘by’ or ‘because of.’

Also as predicted under an account in which -chaj passives contain an implicit agent, passives with -chaj allow agent-oriented adverbial material (63a), as well as control into purpose clauses, as in (63b).Footnote [26]

Schematically, I propose that the -chaj passives have the basic argument structure in (64) (we return to -aj below). The suffix -ch is a v/Voice $^{0}$ head which – like -w – merges directly with the root. Like -w, it categorizes the stem as a verb, assigns a thematic role to an external argument, and does not assign ergative case. Here, however, the external argument is necessarily implicit. I represent the implicit argument as  – a variable that must ultimately be existentially bound. The single overtly realized argument is the theme, which is licensed by finite Infl $^{0}$ . Oblique agents may optionally be adjoined higher in the structure and are then semantically associated with the implicit agent, as illustrated by the matching subscripts in (64).Footnote [27]

4.1.2 Agentless passives with -j

We now turn to the agentless passives. As illustrated by the forms in (65), agentless passive constructions can appear with an adjoined -uj-phrase, in apparent contrast to English anticausatives like the one in (61b). However, while the oblique in -chaj passives, like the one in (62) above, must be understood as the agent of the event, this is not the case with agentless passives.

Here, as discussed in Buenrostro (Reference Buenrostro2013), the oblique phrase is understood as a cause. This is clear in the case of the inanimate causer in (65a), and while not strictly impossible with an agentive interpretation, forms like the ones in (65b) are most naturally understood as situations in which the entity denoted by the DP in the oblique phrase in some way causes the event without direct volitional action. A natural context for the agentless passive in (65b), for example, would be one in which you drove me to the hospital, or paid my medical bills.

The forms in (66) further illustrate this contrast. In the -chaj passive in (66a), the man must be understood as the agent of the event of building. In (66b), the man is responsible for the construction of the house, but did not actually build it and need not have been present during its construction.

Further evidence comes from the fact that agent-oriented adverbs and purpose clauses are impossible with these forms, as shown by the examples in (67) (compare (63) above).

In agentless -j passives, there is no thematic agent, implicit or otherwise. As shown in (68), I propose that -j occupies a v/Voice $^{0}$ head that combines with the root. It verbalizes the stem, but does not assign a thematic role and does not merge an external argument. An -uj-phrase may adjoin higher in the structure, but it has no association with the thematic roles of the verb. It may have any semantically plausible causal relation to the event. I propose that this causality comes directly from the meaning of the relational noun itself, which we might gloss here as something like ‘because of’, ‘as a result of’, or ‘thanks to’.

Compare the contrast in English anticausatives in (69). While anticausatives are incompatible with agentive by-phrases, from may introduce causers or causing events (see discussion in Alexiadou et al. Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou, Schäfer and Frascarelli2006). I propose that Chuj’s relational noun -(u’)uj is broad enough in meaning to be compatible with agentive and non-agentive causation.

One question that arises is whether -j could be analyzed as introducing an implicit causer in its specifier (see, e.g., Alexiadou et al. Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou, Schäfer and Frascarelli2006). In Chuj, there is reason to think that this is not the case. As discussed in Buenrostro (Reference Buenrostro2013), inanimate causers are generally dispreferred as transitive subjects in Chuj. Compare the transitive in (70a) with the agentless passive in (70b).

Furthermore, while the sequence -chaj is only ever found attached to transitive roots, -j appears in a handful of isolated forms attached to non-transitive roots. In (71), we find -j suffixed to the adjectival root al ‘heavy’, resulting in an inchoative interpretation. This is expected under an account in which -j is a v/Voice $^{0}$ head which verbalizes the stem but does not introduce any type of external argument (agent, causer, or otherwise).

The regular passive -ch, on the other hand, merges an implicit agent in its specifier position and is correctly expected to be only compatible with those roots denoting events that may be externally caused by an agent – specifically, √ TV roots.

Again I suggest that Chuj’s morphology may be instructive more broadly to the question of how to capture valence and voice alternations. The fact that we find two distinct overt morphemes for regular passives and agentless passives – -ch ajnd -j – lends credit to proposals in which Voice heads may be specified for whether and what type of external arguments are introduced, as proposed in Alexiadou et al. (Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou, Schäfer and Frascarelli2006) and Wood (Reference Wood2015), among others.

4.2 Implicit arguments and the suffix -aj

Having examined two types of passives, we return to the suffix -aj. In both antipassives and passives, the presence of -aj correlates with the availability of oblique DPs that are associated with particular thematic roles (see the table in (58) above). In the non-aj constructions, on the other hand, the argument slot is either already filled (by the bare NP object in the case of the incorporation antipassive), or is not projected at all (in the agentless passive with -j). Minimal pairs are provided in (72) and (73) below.

While the absolutive antipassive with -waj permits the theme to be realized as a PP (72b), incorporation antipassives like (72a) prohibit oblique themes altogether, requiring instead that the theme be a bare NP.

In the preceding section, we found that agentless passives like the one in (73a) permit an oblique, but this DP is not associated with the notional agent. Instead, it may have any semantically plausible causal relation to the event, as a result of the meaning of the relational noun that introduces it. In a regular passive like (73b), the oblique must be understood as the agent.

As foreshadowed above, I propose here that the suffix -aj in both absolutive antipassives and regular -chaj passives correlates with the presence of an implicit argument – an argument that contributes to the semantic interpretation, but is never overtly realized. Passives like (73b) and (74) have an implicit external argument, while antipassives like (72b) and (75) have an implicit internal argument. In both passives and antipassives, I propose that -aj is an overt reflex of Existential Closure (Diesing Reference Diesing1992).

In the forms in (78) and (79), I represent -aj as a morpheme located between the v/Voice $^{0}$ head which introduces the external argument, and the intransitive status suffix which demarcates the edge of the verb stem. This is in keeping with the proposal that the root undergoes head movement through the functional spine, landing in the projection that hosts the status suffix. This location for existential closure is also compatible with existing semantic work. For example, in Diesing’s (Reference Diesing1992) system, existential closure happens at the edge of VP – which, at the time of her work, was assumed to host all of the participant arguments. Translating this into modern terms, we might expect existential closure to take place just above the projection hosting the external argument, here v/VoiceP. More recently, Chung & Ladusaw (Reference Chung and Ladusaw2004) proposed that ‘[p]redicates must have their participant arguments (semantically) saturated at the event level’ (Chung & Ladusaw Reference Chung and Ladusaw2004: 11). The event argument delimits the event level, and is the highest argument of a predicate, combining after all participant arguments have been saturated. Again, we would expect existential binding to happen just above v/VoiceP – exactly in line with the order of morphemes on the Chuj stems.

I assume that the implicit argument combines with the root via regular Functional Application, but is a variable that must be existentially bound higher in the derivation. Optionally, a PP may be adjoined higher and associated with the implicit argument. Compare the transitive construction in (76a) with the absolutive antipassive in (76b).

In both constructions, the transitive root tek’ ‘kick’ composes with an internal argument via Functional Application: in (76a) it is the DP nok’ pelota, while in (76b) it is the unexpressed implicit argument, represented as

As the contexts and translations of the sentences in (76) suggest, there is a semantic difference between a transitive construction and an antipassive in which the notional patient is expressed as a PP: in the transitive, the patient has a higher degree of ‘affectedness’ than in the corresponding antipassive (Hopper & Thompson Reference Hopper and Thompson1980). This is in keeping with existing literature on antipassives (see, e.g., Spreng Reference Spreng, Johns, Massam and Ndayiragije2006, Basilico Reference Basilico, Cuervo and Roberge2012, Polinsky Reference Polinsky2017). I set the details of this construction – as well as semantic properties of the implicit internal argument, see Bhatt & Pancheva (Reference Bhatt, Pancheva, Everaert and van Riemsdijk2006) and Williams (Reference Williams2015) for discussion and overviews – aside as a topic for future work.Footnote [28]

5 Summary and Conclusions

5.1 Summary

This detailed tour through the Chuj verb stem provides evidence for the division of labor in (77), repeated from (2) above. Specifically, while functional projections are responsible for introducing the external argument, as well as for clausal licensing and agreement generally, it is the root itself that determines whether or not it will semantically compose with an internal argument.

I argued that Chuj’s rich verbal morphology offers a window into the syntax of its argument structure. In Chuj, as in other Mayan languages, roots may be clearly classed based on their stem-formation possibilities. Following a range of work in Mayan linguistics, and discussed in Section 2, it is clear that root class does not correspond directly to surface lexical category: a √ TV is not a transitive verb, an √ ITV is not an intransitive verb, and √ POS does not correspond to any surface lexical category (Haviland Reference Haviland1994, Henderson Reference Henderson2017).

I proposed instead that root classes in Chuj may be at least partially distinguished based on their semantic types, summarized in (3) above. Specifically, √ TV and √ ITV roots are of type ${<}e,<s,t>>$ and thus combine directly with an internal argument DP to yield an event predicate, while √ NOM and √ POS roots – the latter discussed in depth in Henderson (Reference Henderson2017) – do not. As noted above, this is in line with the proposal by Davis (Reference Davis, Mendikoetxea and Uribe-Etxebarria1997) that all predicates are based on roots that combine with a single internal argument.Footnote [29] Surface verbs are formed by combining a root with one of a number of v/Voice $^{0}$ heads (often of the form -C in Chuj); we saw in Section 3 that √ TV, √ POS, and √ NOM roots may all form agentive intransitive stems with the v/Voice $^{0}$ head -w.

Here, we focused particularly on transitive roots, which may be identified by their unique ability to form transitive surface stems with no overt derivational suffix (Section 2.2). Options for transitive roots, along with their argument structural properties, are summarized in (78). For each v/Voice $^{0}$ head, I list the nature of the internal and external arguments, where present, along with the functional head responsible for licensing $/$ agreement. Crucially, note that while we find variation in three out of four columns, what is common to all constructions is the presence of some type of internal argument. As in (77), this is an inalterable property of the root itself.

In a full transitive construction as in (78 $/$ 79a), the null v/Voice $^{0}$ head introduces the external argument and assigns it ergative case. Infl $^{0}$ licenses the internal argument, the transitive object (see Coon et al. Reference Coon, Mateo Pedro and Preminger2014 for discussion). In both regular and agentless passives in (78 $/$ 79b–c), the internal argument is the only overtly present argument, and is licensed by finite Infl $^{0}$ . These two passive heads differ insofar as the v/Voice $^{0}$ head -ch introduces an implicit agent, while -j does not. The implicit agent need not be licensed, but must be existentially bound by the suffix -aj, obligatorily present in (79b). Finally, we found two types of antipassive with -w, as in (79d–e). In both, the -w head introduces an external argument but does not assign it ergative case. The external argument must then be licensed by Infl $^{0}$ . Full DP internal arguments are therefore impossible; the internal argument must be either a bare NP (79e) or an implicit argument that does not need case (79d). In the latter ‘absolutive antipassive’ construction, the suffix -aj is required on the stem and a PP adjunct is possible.

Again, there is no option in which the transitive root selects no complement. Transitive roots like jax ‘grind’ always semantically compose with an internal argument, whether as a full DP argument via Functional Application, as in the transitive and passive constructions from (79a–c), an incorporated NP via Restrict, as in (79e), or an implicit argument, detectable by the suffix -aj from (79d).

We focused specifically on the v/Voice $^{0}$ head realized by the suffix -w. This particular head is instructive because when it attaches to a transitive root an apparent conflict arises: there are not enough licensing heads in the derivation to permit a DP internal argument (Infl $^{0}$ must license the external argument DP), but the transitive root nonetheless must semantically compose with something. The fact that -w stems formed from nominal and positional roots do not combine with an internal argument to create event predicates provides evidence that this is a property of the root itself. This is further corroborated by the appearance of the suffix -aj in absolutive antipassives – the only stem to apparently lack an internal argument. Based on a comparison with two types of passive constructions, I proposed that this morpheme is an overt reflex of the existential binding of an implicit object.

5.2 Implications and avenues for future work

This work fits in line with a larger body of literature that takes roots to be not completely specified for their argument structure or ‘thematic grids’. Rather, argument structure is at least partially determined during the syntactic derivation (see, e.g., Halle & Marantz Reference Halle and Marantz1993, Arad Reference Arad2003, Borer Reference Borer2005, Lois & Vapnarsky Reference Lois, Vapnarsky, Lois and Vapnarsky2006, Lois Reference Lois, Shklovsky, Mateo Pedro and Coon2011, Harley Reference Harley, D’Alessandro, Franco and Gallego2017, among many others). However, in line with works such as Alexiadou et al. (Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou, Schäfer and Frascarelli2006) and Levinson (Reference Levinson2007, Reference Levinson2014), roots in Chuj clearly have more information than just loose semantic content (contra Borer Reference Borer2005, Acquaviva Reference Acquaviva2009, and others; see discussion in Levinson Reference Levinson2014). Minimally, roots belong to classes, which may be at least partially distinguished based on semantic type.

In Chuj, we saw that roots that belong to the class of transitives obligatorily semantically compose with an internal argument – the internal argument cannot be removed or suppressed in later stages of the derivation, although the manner in which it is realized depends on higher functional heads. This is in keeping with proposals such as that in Koontz-Garboden (Reference Koontz-Garboden2009) on the impossibility of removing arguments in later stages of the derivation, and Alexiadou et al. (Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou, Schäfer and Frascarelli2006), Wood (Reference Wood2015), and others who argue that voice alternations (like passive ${\sim}$ anticausative) are not derived one from the other, but rather all are derived from the root. The focus in much of this previous work is on external arguments, but Chuj provides evidence that the same holds true for internal arguments. This also lends support to proposals in which roots directly compose with internal arguments, as in Harley (Reference Harley2014).

Here, the focus is on roots rather than surface stems – two categories that are easily distinguishable in a language like Chuj, but more difficult to distinguish in English and other languages without rich verbal morphology. Although the implementations are different, the proposals here about differences among root classes find similarities in discussion of lexical categories in works such as Baker (Reference Baker2003). For Baker and others, verbs are lexical items that combine directly with an argument (see also Davis (Reference Davis, Mendikoetxea and Uribe-Etxebarria1997)), while nouns are those lexical items that introduce a referential index. This general approach is compatible with the proposals regarding √ TV,  √ ITV, and √ NOM roots discussed above.

The large classes of √ POS roots found across Mayan – and, as Henderson (Reference Henderson2017) points out, the correspondingly small classes of true adjectives – make it clear that different languages may make different choices about how the conceptual space is carved up into root classes, and even what these root classes may be. Nonetheless, it is an interesting topic for future work to consider what Mayan languages might tell us about root classes and categories in other languages. Levinson (Reference Levinson2014), for example, distinguishes at least three classes of verb roots in English: Root Creation Verbs (‘braid’, ‘pile’), Explicit Creation Verbs (‘build’, ‘bake’), and Change of State Verbs (‘open’, ‘freeze’). Although a more systematic study is needed, the first type never seem to belong to the √ TV class in Chuj (or Kaqchikel; Henderson, personal communication); instead, forms with equivalent meanings surface as derived transitive stems (Section 2.2), derived from nominal or positional roots. Among other differences between the latter two categories, Levinson shows that theme arguments are required of Change of State verbs, but optional for Explicit Creation Verbs. If we can take Chuj’s morphology to be instructive more generally, perhaps the theme in Explicit Creation Verbs is present implicitly – and if English had an -aj suffix, we would find it exactly here.

Footnotes

I am extremely grateful to Magdalena Torres for her patience and generosity in sharing her language; without her this work would have been impossible. Yuj wal dyos! Special thanks to Robert Henderson, Alan Bale, Itamar Kastner, David Basilico, and three anonymous reviewers for extended discussion and valuable feedback on this paper. Thanks also to Lizzie Carolan, Lauren Clemens, Henry Davis, Paulina Elias, Claire Halpert, Heidi Harley, Nick Hopkins, Pedro Mateo Pedro, Omer Preminger, Justin Royer, and to audiences at McGill, Minnesota, and CILLA VII. This work was supported in part by an SSHRC Connection Grant (Co-PI Pedro Mateo Pedro). Errors in data or interpretation are of course my own.

2 Accusative case assignment is not discussed in this paper, but see Coon et al. (Reference Coon, Mateo Pedro and Preminger2014) on the Agent Focus suffix in related Q’anjob’al, a cognate of which is present in Chuj. Coon et al. argue that this suffix is a Voice $^{0}$ head which introduces the external argument and assigns accusative case to the internal argument.

3 Abbreviations used in glosses are as follows: a – ‘Set A’ (ergative, possessive); abs – absolutive; ag – agentive intransitive; agr – agreement; ap – antipassive; appl – applicative; b – ‘Set B’ (absolutive); clf – noun classifier; dem – demonstrative; dir – directional; div – derived intransitive verb; dtv – derived transitive verb; inch – inchoative; ipfv – imperfective; irr – irrealis; iv – intransitive verb; l – linker; nml – nominal; pass – passive; pfv – perfective; p – plural; plur – pluractional; prep – preposition; prosp – prospective; rn – relational noun; s – singular; sp – Spanish origin; stat – stative suffix; suf – unidentified suffix; tv – transitive verb.

Chuj is written in the official orthography established by the Academia de Lenguas Mayas de Guatemala (see Domingo Pascual Reference Domingo Pascual2007). Glosses and orthography from other published works on Chuj have been modified in some cases for consistency; translation from Spanish is my own. Unless otherwise attributed, Chuj data presented here are the result of elicitation work in Montreal and Guatemala with speakers of the San Mateo Ixtatán variant of Chuj. Data from other sources have been confirmed through elicitation.

4 Mayan languages generally have a small class of adjectival roots (England Reference England, Dixon and Aikhenvald2004, Martínez Cruz Reference Martínez Cruz2007). Hopkins (Reference Hopkins1967) groups adjectival roots as a subclass of nominal roots, and I set these aside here.

5 Chuj shows split ergativity in the progressive aspect. The progressive involves embedding and utilizes special dependent stem forms not directly relevant to the discussion here. See Buenrostro (Reference Buenrostro2004) and Coon & Carolan (Reference Coon and Carolan2017) on the Chuj progressive.

6 The perfective is frequently null, and at least for some speakers, the choice between ix and Ø may be related to hodiernal versus more distant past distinctions within the perfective; see Carolan (Reference Carolan, Pomerleau and Gendron-Pontbriand2015).

7 The suffix -aj in (15a–b) appears on many derived intransitive stems, and is discussed further in Section 4. I assume that the suffix -n in (15a) is a reduced form of the stative-predicate-forming suffix -an, though further work is needed on this and a number of other derivational and stem-forming suffixes in Chuj; see Hopkins (Reference Hopkins1967) for a comprehensive list.

8 I take it for granted that these are unergatives for now, returning to this question in Section 3.3.

9 Note that the -i status suffix is maintained on the intransitive stem in (19a), even though the stem is not phrase final (compare the underived intransitive stem in (18b), in which -i does not surface). Following Mateo Pedro (Reference Mateo Pedro2011) for related Q’anjob’al, I propose that this difference is related to a phonological fact, and does not indicate a deep difference between -w stems and other intransitive stems. Specifically, the intransitive status suffix -i is not dropped if its omission would result in a complex final coda. Complex final codas are generally impossible in the San Mateo Ixtatán variant of Chuj examined here (*CC#). The status suffix is thus always retained on -w forms since the root itself always (as far as I am aware) ends in a consonant (…Cw-i).

Perhaps because the -i never drops from -w stems, some authors have treated the sequence -w-i as a single morpheme: -wi (e.g. Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013). Nonetheless, stems with -w may also appear in other stem forms without -i, for example with the irrealis suffix -ok, as in (19b). Further evidence comes from the San Sebastián Coatán variant of Chuj, described by Maxwell (Reference Maxwell1976). Here, final consonant clusters are possible, and, as expected, -i does drop in these contexts.

10 Some critiques of inherent ergative case assignment are concerned with ergative languages – like Chuj – in which some external arguments (i.e. transitive subjects) receive ergative marking, while others (i.e. unergative subjects) do not; see Baker & Bobaljik (Reference Baker and Bobaljik2017) for discussion. Note that if the proposal here is correct, we see overt morphological evidence for at least two distinct external argument-introducing v/Voice $^{0}$ heads: Ø assigns inherent ergative, while -w does not. See also footnote 15.

11 A reviewer asks whether the placement of the Set A prefix is a problem for the proposal that the stem is formed in a Mirror-Principle-compliant manner. Set A prefixes are the only true prefixes in the language, and I assume following Coon (Reference Coon2017) and Clemens & Coon (Reference Clemens and Coonto appear) that they are also different from the other verb-stem-forming suffixes in being not heads (i.e. not acquired through successive head movement of the root to the edge of the verb stem), but rather the spell-out of $\unicode[STIX]{x1D719}$ -features acquired through ‘inherent agreement’ with the external argument. While it must be specified that they are prefixes, their placement does not contradict the claim that the stem reflects the syntactic derivation. See Coon (Reference Coon2017: 104) for a more detailed derivation.

12 Independent evidence from non-finite embedded clauses corroborates the proposal that absolutive arguments are licensed by finite Infl $^{0}$ in Chuj; see also Coon & Carolan (Reference Coon and Carolan2017). Like its close relative Q’anjob’al, discussed in detail in Coon et al. (Reference Coon, Mateo Pedro and Preminger2014), Chuj is thus an absolutive = nominative language in the sense of Legate (Reference Legate2008) and work cited therein.

13 Smith-Stark (Reference Smith-Stark and England1978) reconstructs *-(V)w as one of the Proto-Mayan antipassive morphemes.

14 Maxwell (Reference Maxwell1976) describes dialectal variation in the types of modifiers allowed, and whether they may appear pre- or post-nominally, not pursued here. These data are from the San Mateo Ixtatán dialect.

15 Clausal licensing properties independently restrict the -w head from appearing in transitive constructions, but it is an open question as to why the transitive v/Voice $^{0}$ head does not appear when there is a bare NP complement. One possibility is that some type of economy condition on case assignment restricts the transitive Ø head from appearing in a construction in which ergative case is not needed. Alternatively, we could posit a requirement that Infl $^{0}$ must assign case; see, e.g., the Obligatory Case Parameter of Bobaljik (Reference Bobaljik and Phillips1993) and Laka (Reference Laka, Bobaljik and Phillips1993).

16 A reviewer asks about -w’s interaction with causatives. Although many Mayan languages have a productive morphological causative construction, none are described for Chuj in Buenrostro’s (Reference Buenrostro2013) dissertation on voice alternations, and I have also not located one.

17 I set aside the question of how VSO and VOS orders in regular transitive clauses are derived. See Clemens & Coon (Reference Clemens and Coonto appear) for discussion of possible derivations.

18 This is a slight simplification since there are certain nominals that never appear with a classifier in Chuj. These include nouns that denote abstract entities and concepts, as well as nouns denoting elements made of recently introduced materials, such as plastic; see Hopkins (Reference Hopkins2012b) and Royer (Reference Royerto appear) for discussion. I assume that for nominals that do appear with classifiers, the classifier is required to shift the noun from type ${<}$ e,t ${>}$ to type ${<}$ e ${>}$ . For nouns that never appear with a classifier, I assume that this shifting is still possible, but has no overt phonological correlate.

19 Restrict and Existential Closure are defined as follows.

See Chung & Ladusaw (Reference Chung and Ladusaw2004) for discussion of $\exists$ x taking scope within $\unicode[STIX]{x1D706}$ e in (44c).

20 Some languages have more than one option for saturating the remaining argument slot after Restrict. This is shown for Chamorro by the sentences in (i), discussed in Chung & Ladusaw (Reference Chung and Ladusaw2004).

In both sentences in (i), the bare NP ga’ ‘pet’ composes with the predicate ‘have’ via the operation Restrict. In the construction in (ia), the remaining argument slot is saturated by Existential Closure, just as in Chuj in (43). Chamorro, however, allows an additional option, not permitted in Chuj: in (ib), the remaining argument slot is saturated by an adjunct DP added later in the derivation. See Chung & Ladusaw (Reference Chung and Ladusaw2004) for further discussion and cross-linguistic variation.

21 There is at least one form that appears to be a problem for the generalization that -w stems are unergative $/$ agentive. The positional root tel ‘lying down’ forms an intransitive -w stem which can mean ‘to lie down’, but for the speakers consulted, it most naturally means ‘to fall’, as shown in (i). It may be used in clearly non-volitional contexts.

A possibility for this form is that telw has been reanalyzed as an √ ITV root. We might thus posit two lexical roots, a positional root tel ‘lying down’ and an intransitive (unaccusative) root telw. Assuming ‘fall’ to be a relatively frequent form, this is perhaps not far-fetched, although ideally we would like corroborating evidence in the form of independent unaccusativity diagnostics.

22 The proposal that all intransitive roots are unaccusative is compatible with the fact that the class of √ ITV roots found in other Mayan languages is notably small. In his detailed look at Tsotsil roots, for example, Haviland finds that there are ‘no more than 50’ intransitive roots in Tsotsil (Haviland Reference Haviland1994: 699) out of an inventory of 855 roots that are ‘basically verbal’. This number is compatible with the class of √ ITV roots in Chuj.

23 In (55a), the subject is ix s-nun winh ‘his mother’; the Set A prefix on nun co-indexes the postnominal possessor, represented by the classifier winh.

With the exception of examples from other sources, I follow Dayley (Reference Dayley1981) in translating the absolutive antipassive into the slightly unnatural English ‘do X-ing (to Y)’.

24 Derived transitive stems form absolutive antipassives with the suffix -an (Buenrostro Reference Buenrostro2013). I set aside as a topic for future work whether this suffix has a similar function to that proposed for -aj here.

25 Buenrostro (Reference Buenrostro2013) calls these ‘impersonal passives’, and lists the suffix as -ji. Just like -w-i stems, I propose that the sequence -ji is decomposable into the stem-forming suffix -j and the intransitive status suffix -i. The status suffix is protected from dropping because its omission would result in a final consonant cluster; see footnote 9.

26 The phrase sk’annhej sk’o’ol winh, translated as ‘on purpose’, literally involves a possessed form of k’o’ol ‘stomach’, which is used as the metaphorical center for many emotions and internal states in Chuj and other Mayan languages; see, e.g., Hopkins (Reference Hopkins2012a). Nicholas Hopkins (personal communication) suggests that it involves a form of the verb ‘to ask’ (k’ana’) and may be best translated as something like ‘he consulted his gut’. In this case, because the possessor of k’o’ol is male (indicated by winh), the implied agent must also be male. I leave a detailed gloss decomposition for future work.

27 A reviewer asks how the oblique agent in the passive here (and the oblique antipassive patient below) should be integrated into the semantics. Some previous work (see, e.g., Bruening (Reference Bruening2013) and references therein) takes passive constructions to involve existential quantification only in the absence of a by-phrase. An alternative, along the lines of what is sketched here, would be to propose that existential quantification occurs in all passives and that in the presence of an oblique by-phrase, the by-phrase further specifies the argument. Formally, this can be achieved through an operator in the spirit of von Stechow (Reference von Stechow and Suchsland1992), or in terms of Dynamic Semantics (Groenendijk & Stokhof Reference Groenendijk and Stokhof1991). Thanks to Alan Bale for discussion of this question.

28 Recall from Section 3.2 above that Existential Closure was also needed in the case of incorporation antipassives, but crucially no -aj appears in these constructions. In the incorporation antipassive construction (see (44) above), the internal argument does not saturate the argument slot of the root, and EC occurs immediately in order for the derivation to proceed. Above, I followed Chung & Ladusaw (Reference Chung and Ladusaw2004) in breaking the semantic composition into two steps – Restrict and EC – but note that both must take place before any other elements are merged.

The absolutive antipassive construction behaves differently. Here, the internal argument does compose by regular Functional Application, saturating the argument slot of the transitive root. However, this argument is a bound variable, which must be existentially bound by a certain stage in the derivation, which I take to be just above v/VoiceP. Thus, we have a principled reason why -aj appears in absolutive antipassives but not in incorporation antipassives: in the incorporation antipassive construction, there is no unbound variable by the time the derivation reaches v/VoiceP, since it is bound immediately in the merge of the root with the NP complement.

29 Davis (Reference Davis, Mendikoetxea and Uribe-Etxebarria1997) presents a detailed look at verb stem formation in St’át’imcets (Lillooet; Salish) and argues that all roots are unaccusative; transitive and unergative predicates are always derived by morphosyntactic operations. Data from Chuj corroborate this proposal, once we take into account the availability of (and cross-linguistic variation in) zero v/Voice $^{0}$ heads. In St’át’imcets, transitive predicates appear with overt derivational morphology. I proposed above that Chuj has a Ø suffix which derives transitive stems from √ TV roots (Section 2.2). In Chuj, the agentive intransitive v/Voice $^{0}$ head is -w (all unergatives are overtly derived, Section 3.3), whereas Davis argues that a comparable head in St’át’imcets may be null.

References

Acquaviva, Paolo. 2009. Roots and lexicality in Distributed Morphology. York Papers in Linguistics 2.10, 121.Google Scholar
Aissen, Judith. 1992. Topic and focus in Mayan. Language 68.1, 4380.Google Scholar
Aissen, Judith, England, Nora C. & Maldonado, Roberto Zavala (eds.). 2017. The Mayan languages (Routledge Language Famliy Series), New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Alexiadou, Artemis, Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Schäfer, Florian. 2006. The properties of anticausatives crosslinguistically. In Frascarelli, Mara (ed.), Phases of interpretation, 187212. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, doi:10.1515/9783110197723.4.187.Google Scholar
Alexiadou, Artemis, Borer, Hagit & Schäfer, Florian (eds.). 2014. The syntax of roots and the roots of syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Arad, Maya. 2003. Locality constraints on the interpretation of roots: The case of Hebrew denominal verbs. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 21.4, 737778; doi:10.1023/A:1025533719905.Google Scholar
Armstrong, Grant. 2015. Non-verbal predicate constructions in Yucatec Maya. Ms., University of Wisconsin, Madison.Google Scholar
Baker, Mark C. 1988. Incorporation: A theory of grammatical function changing. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Mark C. 2003. Lexical categories: Verbs, nouns and adjectives. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Mark C. & Bobaljik, Jonathan David. 2017. On inherent and dependent theories of ergative case. In Coon et al. (eds.), 111134.Google Scholar
Baker, Mark, Johnson, Kyle & Roberts, Ian. 1989. Passive arguments raised. Linguistic Inquiry 20.2, 219251.Google Scholar
Baquiax, Barreno Modesto, Mateo, Rigoberto Juárez, Mejía, Fernando Rodríguez & Pérez, María Magdalena. 2005. Yaq’b’anil stxolilal ti’ Q’anjob’al: Gramática descriptiva Q’anjob’al. Guatemala: Academia de Lenguas Mayas de Guatemala.Google Scholar
Basilico, David. 2012. The antipassive and its relation to scalar structure. In Cuervo, María Cristina & Roberge, Yves (eds.), The end of argument structure?, 75104. UK: Emerald Group.Google Scholar
Bennett, Ryan, Coon, Jessica & Henderson, Robert. 2016. Introduction to Mayan linguistics. Language & Linguistics Compass 10.10, 453454.Google Scholar
Bhatt, Rajesh & Pancheva, Roumyana. 2006. Implicit arguments. In Everaert, Martin & van Riemsdijk, Henk (eds.), The Blackwell companion to syntax. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bobaljik, Jonathan David. 1993. On Ergativity and Ergative Unergatives. In Phillips, Colin (ed.), Papers on case and agreement II, vol. 19 (MIT Working Papers in Linguistics), 4588. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.Google Scholar
Borer, Hagit. 2005. Structuring sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bruening, Benjamin. 2013. By phrases in passives and nominals. Syntax 16.1, 141.Google Scholar
Buenrostro, Cristina. 2004. El sufijo -an en el Chuj de San Mateo Ixtatán. Anales de Antropología 38, 255267.Google Scholar
Buenrostro, Cristina. 2013. La voz en Chuj de San Mateo Ixtatán. Ph.D. dissertation, El Colegio de México, Mexico.Google Scholar
Carolan, Elizabeth. 2015. An exploration of tense in Chuj. In Pomerleau, Marc & Gendron-Pontbriand, Eve-Marie (eds.), Revue de l’édition 2014 de VocUM. Montreal, QC: Université de Montréal.Google Scholar
Chung, Sandra & Ladusaw, William A.. 2004. Restriction and saturation. Cambidge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clemens, Lauren Eby. 2014. Prosodic noun incorporation and verb-initial syntax. Ph.D. dissertation, Harvard University, Cambidge, MA.Google Scholar
Clemens, Lauren Eby & Coon, Jessica. To appear. Deriving verb initial order in Mayan. Language.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica. 2010. Complementation in Chol (Mayan): A theory of split ergativity. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT Doctoral, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica. 2012. Split ergativity and transitivity in Chol. Lingua 122, 241256.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica. 2013. Aspects of split ergativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica. 2016. Mayan morphosyntax. Language & Linguistics Compass 10.10, 515550.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica. 2017. Little-v agreement and templatic morphology in Ch’ol. Syntax 20.2, 101137.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica & Carolan, Elizabeth. 2017. Nominalization and the structure of progressives in Chuj Mayan. Glossa 2.1, 135.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica, Massam, Diane & Travis, Lisa (eds.). 2017. The Oxford handbook of ergativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica, Mateo Pedro, Pedro & Preminger, Omer. 2014. The role of case in A-bar extraction asymmetries: Evidence from Mayan. Linguistic Variation 14.2, 179242.Google Scholar
Coon, Jessica & Preminger, Omer. 2009. Positional roots and case absorption. In Avelino, Heriberto, Coon, Jessica & Norcliffe, Elisabeth (eds.), New Perspectives in Mayan Linguistics: Proceedings of SSILA 2008 (The Society for the Study of Indigenous Languages of the Americas), 3558. Cambridge, MA: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.Google Scholar
Craig, Colette Grinevald. 1979. The antipassive and Jacaltec. In Martin, Laura (ed.), Papers in Mayan linguistics, vol. 1, 139164. Lucas Brothers.Google Scholar
Craig, Colette Grinevald. 1986. Jacaltec noun classifiers. Lingua 70, 241284.Google Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1967. The logical form of action sentences. In Rescher, Nicholas (ed.), The logic of decision and action, 8195. Pittsburgh, PA: Pittsburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Davis, Henry. 1997. Deep unaccusativity and zero syntax in St’át’imcets. In Mendikoetxea, A. & Uribe-Etxebarria, M. (eds.), Theoretical issues at the morphology–syntax interface (Supplements of the International Journal of Basque Linguistics and Philology), 5596. Bilbao: ASJU.Google Scholar
Day, Christopher. 1973. The Jacaltec langauge, vol. 12 (Language Science Monographs), Indiana University.Google Scholar
Dayley, Jon. 1981. Voice and ergativity in Mayan languages. Journal of Mayan Linguistics 2, 382.Google Scholar
Diesing, Molly. 1992. Indefinites. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Domingo Pascual, Pascual Martín. 2007. Stzolalil stz’ib’chaj ti’ Chuj/Gramática normativa Chuj. Guatemala: Academia de Lenguas Mayas de Guatemala.Google Scholar
England, Nora. 1983. A grammar of Mam, a Mayan language. Austin: University of Texas Press.Google Scholar
England, Nora. 1991. Changes in basic word order in Mayan languages. International Journal of American Linguistics 57, 446486.Google Scholar
England, Nora C. 2004. Adjectives in Mam. In Dixon, R. M. W. & Aikhenvald, Alexandra Y. (eds.), Adjective classes: A cross-linguistic typology, 125146. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
England, Nora C. & Zavala, Roberto. 2013. Mayan languages. In Aronoff, Mark (ed.), Oxford bibliographies in linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, Nicholas & Levinson, Stephen C.. 2009. The myth of language universals: Language diversity and its importance for cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32, 429492.Google Scholar
Farkas, Donka F. & de Swart, Henriëtte. 2003. The semantics of incorporation: From argument structure to discourse transparency. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
García Pablo, Gaspar & Pascual Martín Domingo Pascual. 2007. Gramática descriptiva Chuj. Guatemala: Academia de Lenguas Mayas de Guatemala.Google Scholar
Groenendijk, Jeroen & Stokhof, Martin. 1991. Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy 14.1, 39100.Google Scholar
Gutiérrez Sánchez, Pedro. 2004. Las clases de verbos intransitivos y el alineamiento agentivo en el Chol de Tila, Chiapas. MA thesis, CIESAS, México.Google Scholar
Hale, Kenneth & Keyser, Samuel Jay. 1993. On argument structure and the lexical expression of syntactic relations. In Hale & Keyser (eds.), 53109.Google Scholar
Hale, Ken & Keyser, Samuel Jay. 1997. On the complex nature of simple predicates. In Alsina, Alex, Bresnan, Joan & Sells, Peter (eds.), Complex predicates, 2966. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Halle, Morris & Marantz, Alec. 1993. Distributed Morphology and the Pieces of Inflection. In Hale & Keyser (eds.), 111176.Google Scholar
Harley, Heidi. 2014. On the identity of roots. Theoretical Linguistics 40.3, 225276.Google Scholar
Harley, Heidi. 2017. The ‘bundling’ hypothesis and the disparate functions of little v. In D’Alessandro, Roberta, Franco, Irene & Gallego, Ángel (eds.), The verbal domain, 328. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haviland, John B. 1994. ‘Te xa setel xulem’ [The buzzards were circling] – Categories of verbal roots in (Zinacantec) Tzotzil. Linguistics 32.4–5, 691741.Google Scholar
Henderson, Robert. 2012. Morphological alternations at the intonational phrase edge: The case of K’ichee’. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 30.3, 741787.Google Scholar
Henderson, Robert. 2016. Mayan semantics. Language & Linguistic Compass 10.10, 551588.Google Scholar
Henderson, Robert. 2017. The roots of measurement. Ms., University of Arizona.Google Scholar
Hopkins, Nicholas. 1967. The Chuj language. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL.Google Scholar
Hopkins, Nicholas. 2012a. A dictionary of the Chuj Mayan Language. Tallahassee, FL: Jaguar Tours.Google Scholar
Hopkins, Nicholas. 2012b. Noun classifiers of the Chuchumatán Mayan languages: A case of diffusion from Otomanguean. International Journal of American Linguistics 78.3, 411427.Google Scholar
Hopper, Paul J. & Thompson, Sandra A.. 1980. Transitivity in grammar and discourse. Language 56.2, 251299.Google Scholar
Koontz-Garboden, Andrew. 2009. Anticausativization. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 27, 77138.Google Scholar
Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Rooryck, Johan & Zaring, Laurie (eds.), Phrase Structure and the Lexicon, 109137. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Laka, Itziar. 1993. Unergatives that assign ergative, unaccusatives that assign accusative. In Bobaljik, Jonathan David & Phillips, Colin (eds.), Papers on Case and Agreement I, vol. 18 (MIT Working Papers in Linguistics), 149172. Cambridge, MA: MITWPL.Google Scholar
Legate, Julie Anne. 2008. Morphological and Abstract Case. Linguistic Inquiry 39.1, 55101.Google Scholar
Levin, Beth & Rappaport-Hovav, Malka. 1995. Unaccusativity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Levinson, Lisa. 2007. The roots of verbs. Ph.D. dissertation, New York University, New York, NY.Google Scholar
Levinson, Lisa. 2014. The ontology of roots and verbs. In Alexiadou et al. (eds.), 208229.Google Scholar
Lois, Ximena. 2011. Roots and patterns in Yucatecan languages. In Shklovsky, Kirill, Mateo Pedro, Pedro & Coon, Jessica (eds.), Proceedings of FAMLi: Formal Approaches to Mayan Linguistics. Cambidge, MA: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.Google Scholar
Lois, Ximena & Vapnarsky, Valentina. 2006. Root indeterminacy and polyvalence in Yukatekan Mayan languages. In Lois, Ximena & Vapnarsky, Valentina (eds.), Lexical categories and root classes in Amerindian languages, 69115. Bern: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
Mahajan, Anoop. 1989. Agreement and agreement projections. In Laka, Itziar & Mahajan, Anoop (eds.), MIT Working Papers in Linguistics 10: Functional heads and clause structure, 217252. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.Google Scholar
Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don’t try morphological analysis in the privacy of your own lexicon. In Dimitriadis, Alexis, Siegen, Laura, Surek-Clark, Clarissa & Williams, Alexander (eds.), Proceedings of the 21st Penn Linguistics Colloquium (PLC 21), vol. 4.2 (University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics), 201225. Philadelphia, PA: Penn Linguistics Club.Google Scholar
Martínez Cruz, Victoriano. 2007. Los adjetivos y conceptos de propiedad en Chol. MA thesis, CIESAS, México.Google Scholar
Massam, Diane. 2001. Pseudo noun incorporation in Niuean. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 19.1, 153197.Google Scholar
Mateo Pedro, Pedro. 2011. The acquisition of unaccusativity in Q’anjob’al Maya. Ms., Harvard University.Google Scholar
Maxwell, Judith M. 1976. Chuj intransitives: Or when can an intransitive verb take an object? Journal of Mayan Linguistics 1, 128140.Google Scholar
Mithun, Marianne. 1984. The evolution of noun incorporation. Language 60, 847894.Google Scholar
Nash, Lea. 1996. The internal ergative subject hypothesis. In Kusumoto, Kiyomi (ed.), Proceedings of the 26th Northeast Linguistics Society (NELS 26), 195210. Amherst, MA: GLSA.Google Scholar
Perlmutter, David M. 1978. Impersonal passives and the Unaccusative Hypothesis. Proceedings of the 4th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society (BLS 4), 157189. Berkeley, CA: University of California at Berkeley.Google Scholar
Piedrasanta, Ruth. 2009. Los Chuj, unidad y rupturas en su espacio. Guatemala City, Guatemala: Amrar Editores.Google Scholar
Polinsky, Maria. 2017. Antipassives. In Coon et al. (eds.), 308331.Google Scholar
Pylkkänen, Liina. 2002. Introducing Arguments. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT Doctoral, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Roeper, Thomas. 1987. Implicit arguments and the head–complement relation. Linguistic Inquiry 18.2, 267310.Google Scholar
Royer, Justin. 2016. Classifiers, pronouns, and referentiality in Chuj (Mayan). BA Honours Thesis, Concordia University.Google Scholar
Royer, Justin. To appear. Noun and numeral classifiers in Chuj (Mayan). Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society. Berkeley Linguistics Society.Google Scholar
Smith-Stark, Thom. 1978. The Mayan antipassive: Some facts and fictions. In England, Nora (ed.), Papers in Mayan linguistics, 169187. The Curators of the University of Missouri.Google Scholar
Spreng, Bettina. 2006. Antipassive morphology and case assignment in Inuktitut. In Johns, Alana, Massam, Diane & Ndayiragije, Juvenal (eds.), Ergativity: Emerging issues studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 247270. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Vázquez Álvarez, Juan J.2011. A grammar of Chol, a Mayan language. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Texas Austin, Austin, TX.Google Scholar
von Stechow, Arnim. 1992. Kompositionsprinzipien und grammatische Struktur. In Suchsland, Peter (ed.), Biologische und soziale Grundlagen der Sprache, 175248. Tübingen: Niemeyer.Google Scholar
Williams, Alexander. 2015. Arguments in syntax and semantics. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wood, Jim. 2015. Icelandic morphosyntax and argument structure (Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory), Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
Woolford, Ellen. 1997. Four-way case systems: Ergative, nominative, objective and accusative. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 15.1, 181227.Google Scholar
Zavala, Roberto. 2000. Multiple classifier sytems in Akatek (Mayan). In Senft, Gunter (ed.), Systems of nominal classification, 114146. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar