Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-l4dxg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T08:02:00.918Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Of Athletes, Bodies, and Rules: Making Sense of Caster Semenya

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 January 2022

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article aims to systematically deconstruct four distinct narratives derived from the case of Caster Semenya v. IAAF (Court of Arbitration for Sport).

Type
Independent Articles
Copyright
© 2021 The Author(s)

This article helps navigate through Mokgadi Caster Semenya et al. v. International Association of Athletics Federations (IAAF), a case decided by an arbitral panel of the Court of Arbitration for Sport (CAS) in 2019 1 and on appeal, by the Swiss Supreme Federal Tribunal (SFT) in 2020.2

In Semenya, Athletics South Africa (ASA) and the globally famous South African runner Caster Semenya contended that the IAAF’s Eligibility Regulations for the Female Classification (Athletes with Differences of Sex Development) (DSD Regulations) violated Semenya’s right to participate in sport without discrimination. Semenya and the ASA claimed that the DSD Regulations unnecessarily, disproportionally and unreasonably discriminated against people with Differences of Sex Development (DSD) by preventing them from competing in the female category unless they underwent testosterone-suppressing treatment.Reference Davis3

In particular, the DSD Regulations require women athletes with DSD and testosterone levels higher than 5nmol/L to lower them for a six-month period prior to a competition and continuously thereafter. 4 Building on the principle of non-discrimination contained in the Olympic Charter and in the IAAF’s Constitution, 5 the CAS found that the DSD Regulations did discriminate on the basis of genetic characteristics, sex and gender, but nonetheless considered them a “necessary, reasonable and proportionate means of attaining a legitimate objective.” 6 The SFT eventually upheld the award and denied Semenya’s claim that the CAS award had violated public policy. 7

This article complements the existing academic literature on the case, which consists of two strands of criticism, respectively approaching the award under human rights law and critical legal theories. According to the former view, the DSD Regulations entail multiple violations of the rights of athletes with DSD, which are sidelined by the CAS award.Reference Krech 8 The United Nations Human Rights Council has adopted this perspective in a resolution calling for the respect of female athletes’ “rights to bodily integrity and autonomy.” 9 The latter view reproaches the CAS for having mobilized science over legal concerns, ignoring the multiple ethical issues raised by the DSD Regulations. This analytical approach criticizes more generally the “technocratization” of law, which relies on the assumption that science reveals “absolute truths” about athletic performance and sex/gender boundaries.Reference Holzer 10

Against any absolute truth about sex and gender, we conceive both sex and gender as cultural constructs. As our examination of Semenya will demonstrate, not only gender but also sex vary across time and space. Sex traits are biological and concrete facts. The scientific gaze on bodies is always distant. Far from being the direct representation of what it observes, science translates what it sees through human and non-human intermediaries that “stand in for what actually is.”Reference Jasanoff 11 The way in which the human eye interprets and categorizes sex characteristics is, therefore, far from naturalReference Drescher 12 but rather imbued with cultural expectations. Hence, in this paper we refer to “sex/gender,” unless the analysis requires the separate use of one of the two terms or the term is contained in a quotation from another source.

In Semenya, Athletics South Africa (ASA) and the globally famous South African runner Caster Semenya contended that the IAAF’s Eligibility Regulations for the Female Classification (Athletes with Differences of Sex Development) (DSD Regulations) violated Semenya’s right to participate in sport without discrimination. Semenya and the ASA claimed that the DSD Regulations unnecessarily, disproportionally and unreasonably discriminated against people with Differences of Sex Development (DSD) by preventing them from competing in the female category unless they underwent testosterone-suppressing treatment.

In this article, we offer an original analysis of Semenya that looks at a set of narratives that the adjudicators used to make sense of the case, by deconstructing them as legally flawed and ethically questionable. We elaborate this argument in two parts. Part I presents the case’s factual and legal background. Part II offers an analysis in four sections, respectively dedicated to each of the abovementioned narratives. Particularly, we challenge that:

  • Deciding on eligibility is not deciding about sex/gender.

  • Testosterone is an accurate predictor of athletic performance.

  • The required testosterone-suppressing treatment is safe and harmless.

  • Semenya now protects women as a whole.

Despite the adjudicators’ attempt to offer an objective, neutral and apologetic narrative, the way they made sense of Semenya’s excellent performance is stereotyped, gendered and stigmatizing. We conclude that the narratives presented in Semenya are inherently flawed and contradict the principle of fairness in sport. In fact, by precluding athletes with DSD from competing in the same way as the other athletes, the outcome of the case contradicts the very essence of equal participation in sport.

I. A Longstanding Dispute On Gendered Bodies

A . Before Semenya

On August 19, 2009, eighteen-year-old South African runner Mokgadi Caster Semenya set a new world record in women’s 800-meters finals at the World Athletics Championship in Berlin, winning the gold medal with a time of 1:55.45. As she excelled eight seconds beyond her prior record, her performance was perceived as a “double transgression” for both her young age and common standards of preparation.Reference Liotard, Montanola and Olivesi 13 While the antidoping tests failed to mark any irregularity, Semenya’s peers objected that she should not compete with them as “she is not a woman, she is a man.”Reference Padawer and Bryant 14

To placate the storm, the IAAF announced further tests on Semenya under their 2006 Policy on Gender Verification (PGV), a one-page instruction set for “handling cases of gender ambiguity.” 15 A regime based on mere suspicions of gender non-conformity, the PGV targeted female athletes based on the assumption that they “should not be enjoying the benefits of natural testosterone levels normally seen in a male.” 16 Such testing had already been heavily criticized a few years earlier, when Indian athlete Santhi Soundarajan, a champion in the 800-meter race at the 2006 Asian Games in Doha, was stripped of her medal on the alleged grounds that she “did not possess the sexual characteristics of a woman.”Reference Schultz 17 Her career in sport being interrupted without formal explanations, she attempted suicide, with the IAAF’s silence feeding speculations by the media for months.Reference Harper 18 Caster Semenya was subject to the same treatment. She was described as having “male sex organs and no wombs or ovaries”Reference Hurst 19 and being “too strong and muscular to be a woman.”Reference Cooky and Dworkin 20 In response, South African media criticized the IAAF’s policy as “a lingering artifact of South Africa’s apartheid past and the racist history of Global North/Western culture’s scientific scrutiny of African Women’s bodies.” 21

Following these polemics, in 2011 the IAAF replaced the PGV with the Regulations Governing Eligibility of Females with Hyperandrogenism to Compete in Women’s Competition (Hyperandrogenism Regulations). 22 By refusing the label of “gender verification” and “gender policy,” 23 this new regime restricted its own scope to female athletes with suspected or diagnosed “hyperandrogenism.” This was defined as the excessive production of testosterone above the normal male range, which was conventionally fixed at 10 nanomoles per liter (nmol/L). 24 After qualifying hyperandrogenism as “a risk to health,” 25 these regulations envisaged a threefold investigation procedure to be carried out by a panel of independent medical experts. 26 As in the PGV, the assumption behind the Hyperandrogenism Regulations was that the condition generated an advantage in terms of muscle development that nullified the athletic difference between male and female athletes. 27 The new regime also revived the suspicion regime that existed under the PGV, although now suspicion was formally required to come “from any reliable source.” 28

In 2014, the Indian athlete Dutee Chand challenged the Hyperandrogenism Regulations for the first time before a CAS arbitral tribunal. 29 A sprinter and 100-meters national champion at the age of sixteen, Chand had been disqualified at the last minute from the Commonwealth Games upon suspicion of hyperandrogenism. After medical personnel performed two-round tests on her, the Athletics Federation of India (AFI) suspended her from any competition and recommended she follow the Hyperandrogenism Regulations if she planned to compete again.Reference Viret, Wisnosky, Duval and Rigozzi 30 Notwithstanding the absence of clear-cut answers regarding Chand’s medical conditions, the media speculated that Chand had “failed a gender test” and therefore was not a “normal” woman. 31

Before the CAS, Chand argued that the Hyperandrogenism Regulations disproportionately discriminated against female athletes with particular biological characteristics based on flawed scientific assumptions about the impact of testosterone on athletic performance. 32 The CAS eventually issued an interim award and suspended the Hyperandrogenism Regulations. In particular, the CAS accepted the IAAF’s argument that “the Regulations do not police the male/female divide but establish a female/female divide within the female category.” 33 Moreover, the CAS rejected Chand’s contention that testosterone was irrelevant in explaining the difference in athletic performance between men and women and confirmed it as a scientifically sound marker for eligibility.Reference Buzuvis 34 However, because the parameter against which hyperandrogenism was measured was not men’s testosterone level but that of non-hyperandrogenic females, the CAS required the IAAF to produce sufficient evidence about the degree of athletic advantage enjoyed by hyperandrogenic athletes. 35 As a result, in early 2018, the IAAF withdrew the Hyperandrogenism Regulations and enacted a completely new set of rules, the DSD Regulations, allegedly supported by the strongest scientific evidence and with a more limited scope, resulting in the arbitral proceedings being terminated. 36

B . Caster Semenya, the DSD Regulations and the CAS Award

Compared to the Hyperandrogenism Regulations, the DSD Regulations provide more details about the imperatives supporting their provisions. Their self-proclaimed objective is “[t]o ensure fair and meaningful competition in the sport of athletics” while at the same time maintaining the male/female categorization “[b]ecause of the significant advantages in size, strength and power enjoyed (on average) by men over women from puberty onwards, due in large part to men’s much higher levels of circulating testosterone, and the impact that such advantages can have on sporting performance.” 37 Nonetheless, the DSD Regulations recognize possible “atypical” developments in chromosomal, gonadal and anatomical sex characteristics — the so-called “differences of sex development:” (DSD) — which do not perfectly match the traditional male/female categorization. 38

The DSD Regulations require the affected individuals — athletes with “46,XY DSD” — to undergo testosterone-suppressing treatment if they wish to continue to compete. Specifically, 46,XY DSD results from a discordance between the genetic sex, the gonadal sex (testes or ovaries), the external genital sex (vulva or penis and scrotum) and/or the initial sex ducts existing at birth. Endocrinology identifies a spectrum of 46,XY DSD conditions which include, inter alia, the 5a-reductase type 2 deficiency (5-ARD). Shortly, 5a-reductase (5-AR) is an enzyme that helps testosterone metabolize into dihydrotestosterone (DHT), an androgen that in turn contributes to the proper formation of the typical male external genitalia (penis and scrotum). The 5-ARD results in a newborn child’s genitalia looking atypical or female-typical, while developing testosterone levels closer to the male range from puberty onwards. 39 The DSD Regulations target athletes with 5-ARD and other DSD, including “any other genetic disorder involving disordered gonadal steroidogenesis.” 40 Additionally, for ineligibility to apply, the athlete must have circulating testosterone levels in blood of 5 nmol/L or above and sufficient androgen sensitivity to a “material androgenizing effect.” 41 It is an eligibility condition for the athlete to maintain her blood testosterone level below that threshold “for a continuous period of at least six months (e.g., by use of hormonal contraceptives)” and thereafter “continuously […] for so long as she wishes to maintain eligibility.” 42

Before these new provisions formally entered into force, Caster Semenya and Athletics South Africa (ASA) tried to have them invalidated by CAS on the grounds that they unnecessarily, disproportionally and unreasonably discriminated against people with DSD. 43 Semenya and ASA, as the claimants, argued that the DSD Regulations breached the athletes’ fundamental rights, exposing them not only to stigmatization but also to adverse physical and mental health risks as a consequence of the mandatory testosterone-suppressing treatment. 44 In response to these claims, the IAAF argued that the DSD Regulations were necessary for providing the so-called biological females with the same sporting opportunities as male athletes. The IAAF also explained that the DSD Regulations were reasonable in their scope and considerably narrower than the previous regimes. 45

The CAS agreed with the claimants that the DSD Regulations were discriminatory but found them necessary, proportionate and reasonable for the IAAF to pursue the objectives of ensuring fair competition and protecting the integrity of the female category. In particular, the CAS observed that, insofar as a binary system was maintained, sex segregation should necessarily be based not on legal status but on “human biology” — biological factors such as the level of endogenous testosterone. 46 In the CAS’ view, the DSD Regulations were necessary because athletes falling within their scope — androgen sensitive female athletes with 46,XY DSD — enjoy “a significant performance advantage over other female athletes” due to their greater levels of circulating testosterone. 47 Such an advantage had been determined by two academic papers which integrated the need for evidence underlined by the CAS in Chand.Reference Bermon and Garnier 48 Furthermore, the CAS found that the DSD Regulations were reasonable in light of their limited scope to specific events where the athletic advantage enjoyed by DSD athletes is particularly evident. 49 Finally, the CAS concluded that, with the DSD Regulations requiring athletes with diagnosed DSD to take oral contraceptives to reduce testosterone, the side effects of such a treatment, albeit generally unknown, would not be different in nature from those experienced by the many thousands of XX women who take such oral contraceptives. 50 Thus, these side effects did not render the Regulations disproportionate.

At the same time, however, the CAS expressed grave concerns relating to: (i) the paucity of evidence justifying the Regulations material scope; 51 and (ii) the possibility of the affected athletes not being able to maintain a natural testosterone level below 5 nmol/L, even after complying with the DSD Regulations, due to unintentional fluctuations in their endogenous testosterone levels. 52 Although the CAS recommended the IAAF to address both concerns swiftly, the IAAF ignored these recommendations. Semenya decided therefore to quit athletics and register in soccer competitions instead, a discipline unaffected by the DSD Regulations. 53

Semenya and ASA subsequently sought a review of the award by the Swiss Supreme Federal Tribunal (SFT), whose jurisdiction over CAS awards is limited to public policy (ordre public). 54 According to the SFT’s decade-long judicial practice, an award is contrary to public policy if it disregards “essential and widely recognized values which, according to the prevailing views in Switzerland, should underlie any and all systems of law.”Reference Favre-Bulle 55 The SFT found that the CAS award did not disregard such values. The SFT indeed upheld all the conclusions reached by the CAS regarding the necessity, proportionality and reasonableness of the DSD Regulations. 56

II. The Four Narratives

There are four narratives that emerge from Semenya: (1) deciding on eligibility is not deciding on sex/gender; (2) testosterone is a reliable predictor of athletic performance; (3) the required testosterone-suppressing treatment is safe and harmless; and (4) Semenya now protects female athletes as a whole. These narratives reflect the ways sport authorities and adjudicators make sense of the case. We, nevertheless, challenge them.

Methodologically, we deconstruct these narratives using both legal and ethical arguments. These narratives are described in the literature covering the subject in various ways.Reference Sahni and Sinha 57 Here we intend “narratives” to be understood as “ordered representation[s of] the way we think.” 58 Scholars of different disciplines have highlighted the enormous powers attained to narratives. Narratives are not just vehicles of communication or instruments that help describe the world, but behavior-shaping techniques that influence our lives.Reference Damodaran 59 Given the importance of law in shaping behaviors, the power of narratives becomes particularly important when it comes to legal matters and decisions. As one the foremost experts in legal narratology, Peter Brooks, puts it, a judicial decision may “activate conviction that its narrative is the true and the right one.”Reference Brooks 60

The narratology we derive from Semenya depicts an apparently logical sequence of objective, neutral and apologetic considerations. These justify a regime of conditions for athletes with DSD for the sake of highly priced values in sports including equality, fairness and the common good. Against this logic, we maintain that the outcome of the case sidelines equally important notions for sports such as gender and race (as in narratives 1 and 4) and expresses extremely narrow views of the surrounding scientific and ethical dynamics (as in narratives 2 and 3). As Australian sociologist and former middle-distance runner Madeleine Pape showed in her in-depth analysis of Chand, sidelining certain important dimensions of a case is a way for the CAS to deal with complexity.Reference Pape 61 Her analysis persuasively found that sidelining manifested itself in Chand when the CAS replaced one gendered dichotomy with another one. The CAS, indeed, substituted the male versus female dichotomy with “a new binary” female-with-DSD versus female-without-DSD, which “simulate the sex categories of male and female in all but name.” 62 The same phenomenon, we argue, occurs in Semenya, where the CAS is able to: transform complex questions about sex/gender into a simple eligibility matter (narrative 1); amplify the reliability of the deeply flawed research produced by the IAAF while downgrading the criticisms raised by the claimants as “insufficient” (narrative 2); affirm that a completely unethical medical treatment is nonetheless safe (narrative 3); and downplay the experience of the claimant for the sake of principles (narrative 4).

1. The case is about eligibility and not about sex/gender

The idea that one can decide on an athlete’s eligibility without deciding on their sex/gender is expressed very clearly by both the IAAF and the CAS. On the one hand, the DSD Regulations state that “[i]n no way are they intended as any kind of judgment on or questioning of the sex or the gender identity of any athlete.” 63 On the other hand, the CAS stipulates that “nothing in this Award is intended to question, determine, or pass judgment upon any aspect of any person’s sex or gender” 64 — a conclusion that is shared by the SFT. 65

According to Judith Butler, “we can invoke certain standards for admission to compete under a particular gender category without deciding whether or not the person unequivocally “is” that category.” 66 The problem with these statements, however, is that the question of eligibility and that of sex/gender in sports are so profoundly intertwined that it becomes difficult, if not impossible, to judge an athlete’s eligibility without making assumptions about her sex/gender. In fact, while defining the eligibility of certain athletes with DSD to compete within the female category, both the DSD Regulations and the CAS award implicitly determine who is a woman and who is not. They do not simply describe or recognize an athlete’s sex/gender. They define it to mean “a real woman does not have a DSD.”

The whole eligibility system is grounded on a form of collective surveillance over the athlete’s body which valorizes the simple suspicion of gender non-conformity. 67 While the IAAF Medical Manager is the only person who can initiate an investigation, the DSD Regulations are imprecise as to those who may raise “concern,” referred to, in Section 3.3 thereof, as:

sources, such as (for example, but without limitation) the athlete herself, the team doctor of the National Federation to which the athlete is affiliated, results from a routine preparticipation health examination, and/or information/data (including but not limited to blood testosterone levels) obtained from the collection and analysis of samples for anti-doping purposes. 68

Clearly, such a system leaves the door ajar to gender stereotypes and biases to drive the eligibility process. Borrowing from Rebecca Cook and Simone Cusack, a stereotype is “a generalized view or preconception of attributes or characteristics possessed by, or the roles that are or should be performed by, members of a particular group.”Reference Cook and Cusack 69 Stereotyping is everywhere. Gender stereotyping, in particular, dominates sport competitions as much as our everyday lives. Both explicit and implicit gender stereotyping is heavily implicated in sport behaviors.Reference Plaza, Boiché, Brunel and Ruchaud 70 In this respect, particular body morphologies and above-average levels of strength represent powerful triggers for implicit gender stereotyping, especially in the case of gender nonconforming bodies. A stereotype builds on the “salient representatives of a given category.”Reference Bohnet 71 Consequently, appearance replaces great athletic performances with non-stereotypical characteristics being targeted as signs of gender non-conformity. For instance, media speculations surrounding Caster Semenya’s victory in Berlin in 2009 reflected the idea that Semenya’s voice, way of dressing, muscles, short hair and attitude render her a man, 72 an argument that the IAAF did not hesitate to buy. 73

In the context of sport competitions, well beyond the measurement of hormonal levels, “appropriate” female bodies are those meeting the aesthetics and expressions of normative femininity, reporting the beholder — acting as the supposed “source” under the DSD Regulations’ investigation provisions — to culturally-coded ideas of femininity. These are the lenses through which higher testosterone levels are interpreted.Reference Bohoun and Rodriguez 74 Specific characteristics or modes of behaving may therefore be perceived as signs of high testosterone so that the tone of voice, the size of muscles, facial and other features which do not fit the typical feminine traits become the target of a widespread surveillance of female athletes by different actors and entities like national federations, doctors, doping officials and other official personnel. In this context, striking performances are not interpreted as deserving victories but as gender non-conformity accidents, with talent and stubbornness turning into ambiguous or anomalous components of the athlete’s femininity to be extirpated. Hence, rather than expanding the category of woman, the goal is to more narrowly define it in a way that leads to stigmatizing DSD outliers.Reference Fausto-Sterling 75

Ironically, both the IAAF and the CAS insist on the prevention of stigmatization to which they actually contribute. By upholding the legitimacy of the DSD Regulations, the CAS turns a blind eye to the inconsistency of the above mentioned Section 3.3, describing the process through which any person or entity may provide information to the IAAF Medical Manager for initiating the investigation, with the prescription, contained in the subsequent Section 3.4, to respect of the “dignity and privacy of every individual.” 76 The latter provision also sets forth the specific prohibition for any person or entity providing information to the Medical Manager to “stigmatize or otherwise injure an athlete.” 77 This reflects the more general prohibition of stigmatization and “improper discrimination on the grounds of sex or gender identity.” 78 Among the conducts that will not be “tolerated” is the “persecution or campaigns against athletes simply on the basis that their appearance does not conform to gender stereotypes.” 79

As a matter of fact, stigmatization almost automatically follows gender stereotyping. In particular, the DSD Regulations do not target all women with hyperandrogenism, but only women with a subset of DSD variations with higher natural testosterone levels and androgen sensitivity sufficient to have “a material androgenizing effect.” 80 This last expression incorporated in the DSD Regulations constitutes per se a gender stereotype. Higher testosterone levels, indeed, produce certain traits which are considered not feminine and make women androgenized. The “androgenizing effect” is the key albeit vague criterion to selecting the athletes who look “masculine” or do not look “feminine enough.” 81 This is the premise of the DSD Regulations, which encourage stigmatization of those who look not like the standard(ized) feminine athlete and do not fit gender stereotypes. This claim is further substantiated by the content of the predecessor of and model for the DSD Regulations, the Hyperandrogenism Regulations. These Regulations expressly stated that women with higher testosterone “often display masculine traits and have an uncommon athletic capacity in relation to their fellow female competitors.” 82 By upholding the DSD Regulations, the CAS reinforces the stigmatization of athletes with DSD, perpetuating the vulnerability of female athletes whose bodies do not conform to common gender stereotypes. The risk of the DSD Regulations’ scope being overinclusive is real. While targeting women with DSD with sensitivity to high level of testosterone, the DSD Regulations reinforce stereotypes as to how women more generally should behave and look like.

A second manifestation of the confusion between eligibility and gender determination comes from the CAS’ focus on the gender binary which is at the basis of sex segregation in sport. For the CAS,

[o]nce it is recognized that the reason for organizing competitive athletics into separate male and female categories rests on the need to protect one group of individuals against having to compete against individuals who possess certain insuperable performance advantages derived from biology rather than legal status, it follows that it may be legitimate to regulate the right to participate in the female category by reference to those biological factors rather than legal status alone. 83

This statement reflects a view according to which sex segregation in sport is commanded by the apparently meritorious goal of protecting women from the “insuperable performance advantage” enjoyed by men. However, sociologists have unveiled the hypocrisy laying behind this view. According to this view, women appear as the protected category while, in reality, the purpose of sex segregation is, and has always been, that of policing sex/gender boundaries to protect male physical superiority. 84 What eligibility rules actually do is to “provide an upper limit for women’s sporting performance”Reference Heggie 85 which does not operate for men.

In the Western world, women were admitted to sport competitions since the 1860s under the dominant medical discourse that justified their access to exercise and training as a way to reinforce the nation’s strength. Women’s resulting muscular benefits, it was believed, would be inherited by their (male) children.Reference Petersen 86 Systematic and deeply invasive physical examinations were put in place, which effectively restricted women’s access to competitions, with the clear purpose of verifying that sport “cannot in any way injure the woman.”Reference Eliott-Lynn 87 This theory predicates women’s inherent fragility and perfectly fits the eugenic narrative of capitalism relegating women to a reproductive function.Reference McCrone, Mangan and Park 88 As such, it has been shared for decades by the Olympic Games ideologues, who vigorously opposed the idea of female athletes as “inconvenient, uninteresting, un-aesthetic and not correct” — women’s role had to be relegated to crowning the winners.Reference Ferez, Gori and Mangan 89 When, at the end, women were “admitted” (admises) at the Olympic Games, 90 it was not for the sake of gender equality. Instead, so many female sport associations had blossomed locally that it was ultimately impossible to ignore them. 91

Once this had happened, a new narrative was construed to support the sequence of “crude and unpleasant,” 92 “inappropriate” 93 and ultimately “obsolete”Reference Simpson 94 set of sex/gender verification tests enacted by sport authorities from the 1930s to the 1990s. Ranging from “femininity certificates” to the infamous “naked parades,”Reference Erikainen, Demos and Segal 95 to the Barr Body (or Chromatin) test,Reference Boyd 96 these tests were formally justified with the intention of identifying “gender frauds” and “gender cheaters.”

However, the number of cases that academic research has progressively revealed to the public tells a completely different story. On the one hand, more often than not, suspicions of gender frauds have been highly politicized, especially during the Cold War, with Western media targeting Eastern athletes in an attempt to discover the highest number of gender cheaters.Reference De Meo, Singh, Chanda and Jedrzejewski 97 On the other hand, as has been showed by a recent study, the various changes in IAAF’s sex segregation regime were actually demanded not by cases of cheating but rather by “social anxieties over sex/gender binary breakdown” and the need to police women’s bodies.Reference Erikainen 98 The Olympics’ experience with sex testing reflects both these anxieties for sex/gender boundaries and the connected geopolitical influences.

In sum, the eligibility regime drawn by the DSD Regulations and validated by the CAS construes a “female” category that is: (a) necessarily physically weaker than the “male” category; (b) based on anatomical features and differences between male and female athletes; and (c) arbitrarily drawn upon a line between what is typically female and non-female. Therefore, the category of “female” is treated monolithically as if no differences existed within the group of women. This stance ignores that there is always a particular segment of the sport community which remains difficult to label.Reference Bach Yen Nguyen 99 Where a difference is present, the DSD Regulations impose athletes with DSD to assimilate to the male or the female category, in the latter case subject to testosterone-suppressing treatment. In this framework, the Regulations’ statement that “in no way are they intended as any kind of judgement on or questioning of the sex or the gender identity of any athlete” 100 is nothing more than a theoretical dictate built on shaky grounds.

2. Testosterone is a predictor of athletic performance

The second narrative scrutinized here is the CAS’ conclusion of testosterone being a biological predictor of athletic performance. In this regard, the CAS shares the IAAF’s view that “androgen sensitive athletes with 46,XY DSD enjoy a significant performance advantage over other athletes without such DSD, and that this advantage is attributable to their exposure to levels of circulating testosterone in the adult male range.” 101 The CAS also responds affirmatively to the question as to whether this advantage is “insuperable,” thereby resulting in the justifiability of DSD Regulations as necessary. 102 We hereby criticize this narrative as an exercise of “opportunistic epistemology,” that is, an approach that formulates conclusions before searching for evidence.Reference Karkazis and Jourdan-Young 103

Let us start with the integrity of the scientific process that supports the alleged causal relationship between testosterone and the athletic advantage enjoyed by athletes with DSD. In Chand, the CAS adopted a rigorous approach in the evaluation of the scientific evidence by explicitly warning the IAAF that the “degree or magnitude of the advantage” must be scientifically determined as “substantial,” while “it is not enough simply to establish that the characteristic has some performance enhancing effect.” 104 Against this approach, according to which “numbers matter[ed],” 105 the majority of Semenya’s panel went loose on the exact weight of the athletic advantage and limited its findings to considering that the latter “cannot be characterized as minimal or marginal.” 106

Given such stunning level of disenfranchisement from Chand — which the CAS omitted to justifyReference Bersagel 107 — one should have expected the scientific evidence brought before the CAS to be methodologically sound, that is resilient to criticism. Yet, despite the CAS’ enormous efforts to elaborate on the scientific evidence provided by the IAAF, an accurate time analysis of the proceedings reveals that the evidence used in support of the DSD Regulations in the first place, i.e., the 2017 paper by IAAF’s medical experts Stéphane Bermon and Pierre-Yves GarnierReference Bermon and Garnier 108 (“BG17”) was firstly amended to fit the IAAF’s purposes and subsequently complemented with more research – namely, Professor David J. Handelsman’s expert testimony and paper, coauthored with Bermon, 109 published after the publication of the DSD Regulations. This explains why, as has been observed, the BG17 was “relegated to the periphery, out of sight and scrutiny, because that’s where the IAAF were the weakest,” 110 and why the CAS reported at length on Handelsman’s data and findings. 111

Now, the BG17 examined 1,332 blood samples made available to the IAAF in 21 women’s events in Daegu and Moscow IAAF World Championships and found a competitive advantage from 1.8% to 4.5% in female athletes with high testosterone over female competitors with normal androgen levels, with different margins depending on the discipline. 112 A substantial number of authors highlighted flaws in the paper’s methodology and data analysis, concluding that “it is reasonably likely that the correlations presented in [BG17] (even the largest ones) occurred by chance.”Reference Franklin, Betancurt and Camporesi 113 These authors also found that only in 12 over 21 of the examined events athletes with high testosterone performed better on average and that, given the absence of publicly available raw data, the paper filed with the arbitral tribunal failed to meet the standard of proof required by the CAS. 114 Other authors contended that BG17 failed to address “the issue of causality” between the testosterone level and athletic performance. They criticized the idea that the asserted competitive advantage could be measured by testosterone alone without considering “other relevant variables.”Reference Sonksen, Bavington and Boehning 115 Finally, one author questioned whether it was ethical to use the blood samples the athletes consensually provided in the context of antidoping testing for further research on athletic performance.Reference Camporesi 116

Analogous criticisms have been raised with regard of an amended version of the BG17 produced before the CAS. 117 As to Professor Handelsman’s paper, the authors not only declared that their research provided “incomplete evidence,” but also remarked that, in order to fill the existing “lack of well-designed study” on the sex/gender differences in athletic performance, the more research that is needed may raise “ethical concerns over short and long-term adverse effects” of administering exogenous testosterone to “healthy” adults. 118 Moreover, when Professor Handelsman’s independence was questioned before the CAS, he admitted that his remuneration by the IAAF was contingent on the outcome of the case. 119

Concerns have also been raised regarding a possible conflict of interest since the research supporting the conclusions of the IAAF has been conducted by its own in-house researchers, which is tantamount to “cigarette companies [providing] the scientific basis for the regulation of smoking”. 120 While sports governance necessarily requires robust evidence, the evidence in this case simply does not fulfil the standard criteria for courtroom admissibility due to the use of flawed scientific data which has not even been subject to peer-review. 121

The centrality of quantitative evidence in proceedings before the CAS acquires a further meaning if seen from the angle of what that evidence is expected to prove. The reasons underlying the two-year temporary suspension of the Hyperandrogenism Regulations in 2015 in the Dutee Chand interim award provide the background for understanding the narrative of testosterone being a predictor of athletic performance in Semenya.Reference Camporesi 122 The narrative upheld in Semenya was conditioned by the combination of the burden of proof being on the IAAF and the CAS’ assumption of testosterone being an indicator of improved performance in the Dutee Chand interim award. The panel assumed that, had the IAAF proven the testosterone-driven athletic advantage, the Hyperandrogenism Regulations should have been reinstated. In that ruling, the CAS suspended the regulations to allow the IAAF to provide scientific proof about the correlation between increased testosterone levels in hyperandrogenic athletes and a competitive advantage in athletic performance. By giving the IAAF the opportunity to provide scientific evidence about improved performance, the CAS, therefore, confirmed the IAAF’s assumption regarding the causal link between high testosterone levels and athletic advantage. The panel explicitly stated that this link “may well be proved valid” 123 although sufficient evidence of the correlation between testosterone and performance was not provided, with the onus of proof remaining with the IAAF. 124

We see the CAS’ approach in assessing the scientific evidence advanced by the parties as reflecting a power imbalance between the IAAF and its athletes. While the IAAF is allowed to produce, amend, contradict and provide further support to its own data and findings, the claimants are left unarmed against such a powerful expenditure of money and resources on the opposite side. It seems that the same dystopic dynamics highlighted by Pape in the Chand award are replicated in Semenya. Here, claimants are cornered into the awkward position of having to prove “the negative claim that testosterone does not confer an advantage of any size.” 125 Furthermore, as Pape argued, under this approach “legitimate expertise could only be that which constructed testosterone — and the sexed/gendered athletic bodies it was taken to approximate — in binary terms.” 126 This is exactly what both the BG17 and Professor Handelsman’s paper do. In fact, their research on testosterone is always gendered. It is led not by the genuine intent of discovering unexplored dimensions of testosterone but by the goal of biologically confirming the male-female binary. In other words, the focus of the IAAF’s research altogether is to confirm sex/gender boundaries so that male above-average performances are never considered but only female ones are. All this completely neglects the fact stressed by UN Special Rapporteurs, that “[n]atural physical and biological traits as well as social and economic factors also influence the performance of men athletes.” 127 We argue that this is the essence of opportunistic epistemology. The CAS fell into the same conceptual trap when it asserted that testosterone, in its own view, remains “the primary drive of physical advantages and therefore of the sex difference in sports performance between males and females.” 128

Overall, the expertise evidence claimed by the CAS as decisive in deciding about the role of testosterone in athletic performance appears extremely flawed. Contrary to what the CAS stated, there exists no clear scientific consensus that high testosterone levels actually produce a performance advantage in athletics. The equation at the core of the IAAF’s argument, that “more testosterone equals more ability,” is inaccurate and therefore makes the argument untenable. Studies even demonstrate that positive and negative relationships between testosterone and performance exist in a wide range of sports. 129 Additionally, as this article goes to print, Bermon and Garnier issued a correction to the BG17, clarifying that the results they reached regarding the relationship between testosterone level and athletic performance are “exploratory, nothing else, that is, not confirmatory of evidence for a causal relationship”, praising for “an independent, prospectively designed, randomly controlled trial […] to establish confirmatory scientific evidence”.Reference Bermon and Garnier 130 This further strike at the core of IAAF’s significant competitive advantage claim which is at the basis of the DSD Regulations confirms the weakness of the narrative surrounding the athletic advantage, which remains very far from being supported by solid scientific evidence, no matter the conclusions reached by the CAS. At any rate, one thing is to say that there is a significant advantage deriving from specific physical condition,Reference Ostrander, Huson and Ostrander 131 like the CAS argued, another thing is to argue that such an advantage is unfair. A performance difference is not necessarily unfair, unless it leaves gender binary unquestioned.

3. The required testosterone-suppressing treatment is safe and harmless

That bodies are (easily) malleable is the assumption underlying the third narrative. The body malleability narrative is expressed very clearly at multiple levels. First, the DSD Regulations plainly require athletes with DSD who have testosterone levels higher than 5 nmol/L to lower them for a 6-month period prior to a competition and continuously thereafter. 132 Second, the CAS accepted that “the use of oral contraceptives to reduce testosterone levels can cause a range of unwanted side effects” 133 such as “weight gain, feverish symptoms and consistent abdominal pain,” 134 making focus during training impossible and performance low. Yet, the CAS asserted that these side effects “are not different in nature to those experienced by many thousands, if not millions, of other XX women, who take oral contraceptives.” 135 Finally, the SFT recognized that “the assumption of oral contraceptives causes significant side effects and does not lay on a completely free and clear consent, to the point of constituting a grave violation of the athlete’s right to physical integrity.” 136 Nevertheless, the SFT upheld the mandatory testosterone-suppressing treatment as it was proportional and ultimately justified by the need to pursue the objectives prefixed by the IAAF.

Two premises are implicitly stated here, which make the required medical treatment look minimal or insignificant. The first premise is that the artificial lowering of testosterone is a negligible medical treatment; the second is that the medical procedure attained to obtain this result is both safe and effective. In fact, whereas generally speaking testosterone levels may be lowered either surgically or pharmacologically,Reference Karkazis and Carpenter 137 the DSD Regulations expressly forbid the former possibility, so that “surgical anatomical changes are not required in any circumstances.” 138

Both premises, however, are false. To begin with, despite said prohibition, there is no certainty that an athlete could not be required to undergo surgical operations, making the medical treatment uncertain and possibly dangerous. If the prohibition of surgical treatment is, on the one hand, the law on the books, then on the other hand, the genealogy of the implementation of the DSD Regulations’ predecessor dismantles this statement. In accordance with the Hyperandrogenism Regulations, indeed, four female athletes with “excessive” testosterone underwent medical investigations. Following the discovery of a 46 XY karyotype, doctors recommended partial clitoridectomy, vaginoplasty and estrogen replacement therapy. 139 Gonadectomy (i.e., the removal of gonads) had been the condition that the IAAF imposed for the athletes to compete.Reference Bermon, Vilain, Fénichel and Ritzén 140 That the surgical solution remains a concrete possibility for athletes with DSD exceeding the required threshold for testosterone is made clear by the CAS itself, which after taking into consideration both the use of GnRH antagonists and gonadectomy in case the oral contraceptives failed to achieve the expected result, simply recommended, in this event, “a different analysis of proportionality.” 141 The CAS did not seem concerned with the fact that the use of GnRH in combination with oral contraceptive may not bring the expected results.Reference Copperman and Benadiva 142 In any case, it implied that, besides the different proportionality standard that would be applied, gonadectomy nonetheless remains a feasible option in medical practice.

This is confirmed by the genealogy of the implementation of the DSD Regulations’ predecessor. In accordance with the Hyperandrogenism Regulations, indeed, four female athletes have been reported as having excessive testosterone levels and being subjected to the Hyperandrogenism Regulations. 143 They were all aged between eighteen and twenty-one and came from rural areas of developing countries. The doctors who examined them found a 46,XY karyotype and recommended partial clitoridectomy followed by vaginoplasty and estrogen replacement therapy.Reference Fénichel, Paris, Philibert and Hiéronimus 144 The IAAF allowed these athletes to compete one year after gonadectomy, despite the fact that a paper authored by IAAF officials discouraged gonadectomy for eligibility purposes while recommending keeping eligibility and therapeutic options distinguished.Reference Bermon, Vilain, Fénichel and Ritzén 145 By making permanent anatomical modifications a concrete option, while at the same time denying them as a condition to compete, both sport authorities and adjudicators have been able to minimize the costs that these operations entail on the athlete’s body and psyche.

This narrative on body malleability is accompanied by what Susie Orbach in a different context called “a rhetoric of empowerment.” This is the idea that not abiding by the testosterone-suppressing provision would signal the athlete’s voluntary exclusion from the competition. According to this rhetoric, no athlete would be actually “forced” to do anything against their own will, with the medical treatment following the discovery of testosterone levels beyond the prescribed threshold being just a part of the athlete’s stubbornness and prowessness.

These challengeable postures on bodily modifications show that nature is a concept prone to misrecognition and misunderstanding depending on the interests and the power dynamics at stake. In the CAS decision, the sport competition moves the focus from one’s identity to their bodily parts as components of a performing machine. Relatedly, the CAS conflates sex with gender. “Ms. Semenya is a woman,” the CAS argues. “At birth, it was determined that she was female, so she was born a woman.” 146 This is the opposite of Simone de Beauvoir’s well-known conception of gender as a non-innate feature but a becoming: “one is not born a woman, but rather becomes one.”Reference De Beauvoir 147 The confusion produced by the CAS conveys the idea that gender is inextricably determined by sex — because “gender is sex,” and “sex is gender.” It is undeniable that sex characteristics are natural in their origins. Yet the way in which a certain society or societal circle, such as the Westernized international sport arena, interprets, understands and thereby categorizes sex traits is anything but natural. Perceptions and interpretations change across times, spaces and cultures.Reference Chau and Herring 148

This narrative on body malleability is accompanied by what Susie Orbach in a different context called “a rhetoric of empowerment.”Reference Orbach 149 This is the idea that not abiding by the testosterone-suppressing provision would signal the athlete’s voluntary exclusion from the competition. According to this rhetoric, no athlete would be actually “forced” to do anything against their own will, with the medical treatment following the discovery of testosterone levels beyond the prescribed threshold being just a part of the athlete’s stubbornness and prowessness.

In connection with that, the DSD Regulations specify that the medical investigation and the possible subsequent treatment depend on the athlete’s willingness and responsibility, as if no coercive assessment and treatment were ever imposed on the athlete. The DSD Regulations state, precisely, that “[n]o athlete will be forced to undergo any assessment and/or treatment under these Regulations [and i]t is the athlete’s responsibility, in close consultation with her medical team, to decide whether or not to proceed with any assessment and/or treatment.” 150 Despite this statement, in practice the DSD Regulations leave no real choice to the athlete who wants to compete in the female category. Either the athlete agrees to undergo invasive medical investigations involving intimate parts of her body and undertake medical procedures with potentially physically and psychologically harmful consequences, or she has to quit the competition. 151

It is undisputable that the mere acceptance of the medical intervention is not equivalent to informed consent: such a consent must be voluntary and sufficiently informed to make a free decision. In 2018, the UN Special Rapporteur on the right to health addressed a letter to the IAAF, stressing the key element of making the athlete’s consent vitiated. The consent that the athlete gives to the intrusive investigation is indeed far from free, as the athlete makes the decision under pressure vis-à-vis the alternative of being excluded from competition without a viable choice. 152 The same UN Special Rapporteur had already explained in 2009 that informed consent is invalid if, inter alia, it is subject to “undue influence,” which corresponds to situations where the person “perceives there may be an unpleasant consequence associated with refusal or consent.” 153 There is no reason to doubt that ending an elite sport career amounts to an unpleasant consequence, an “impossible set of choices,”Reference Karkazis and Carpenter 154 a subtle form of double bind. Either you conform, or you cannot perform. Damned if you do, doomed if you don’t.

The side effects of the hormonal treatment imposed on the athlete whose testosterone level is over 5 nmol/L are equally unfortunate. The treatment has a great impact on the athlete’s health, which goes beyond the IAAF’s minimizing suggestion about contraceptives. 155 Paradoxically, the CAS recognizes that the side effects of hormonal treatment would make compliance with the DSD Regulations practically impossible, alerting the IAAF that:

[i]f the DSD Regulations cannot be implemented fairly in practice, that could render them disproportionate at a later stage since a regulation which is impossible or excessively difficult to apply fairly cannot be characterized as a proportionate interference with the rights of those who are subjected to it. 156

The CAS (followed by the SFT) moved from a strict proportionality analysis to a lighter standard requiring the mere lack of an evident disproportion in the prescribed measure. 157 This approach may be explained in light of the CAS’ decision to defer to the IAAF’s legislative competence. The CAS held that evaluating the IAAF’s policy making process or rewriting its rules was not their problem. 158 Nonetheless, we see a contradiction between CAS upholding the DSD Regulations’ exclusionary regime, on the one hand, and its assessment of the actual harm that is caused to the athlete’s body, on the other hand. Such a harm may attain the practical impossibility to participate in sport. This practical impossibility cannot be left to future cases and future proportionality assessments, as unfair implementation of the DSD Regulations in practice is already a reality today. By attempting to fix the standard to be applied in future cases, the CAS acted, probably unintentionally, as a constitutional adjudicator. Yet it declined to play this role in all respects, leaving the IAAF’s legislation completely untouched without considering any less harmful alternative, or even the possibility of a time percentage handicap. 159 This consideration undermines the CAS’ necessity analysis. How can a measure be deemed necessary if the adjudicators refuse to examine possibly less harmful alternatives?

The CAS’ approach appears shy at best, reverential to IAAF policy orientations at worst. One would expect that the intensity of the CAS’ legal review of the IAAF’s decision-making power would have been greater in the light of the IAAF’s public function in creating rules and impacting athletes’ lives. This is even more problematic given that a decision of such importance, for the control over powerful decision-makers and for the implications on athletes’ physical integrity, was reached with a two out of three majority.

The CAS’ narrative of the athletes’ easily malleable bodies is that of machines whose performance can be not just accurately measured but also remotely controlled through pharmacological treatment. As machines that are required to function perfectly, their suffering becomes either irrelevant or part of the inherent dynamics of their own working. In such a world, calling for these machines to consent to the burdens that are assigned to them is simply unconceivable.

4. The case is about protecting the integrity of the female category

The argument that it is fair to exclude certain athletes from the female category in order to protect the integrity of the category itself is made by both the IAAF and the CAS. In particular, the DSD Regulations clearly establish that they “exist solely to ensure fair and meaningful competition within the female classification, for the benefit of the broad class of female athletes.” 160 The CAS accepts this argument subject only to the IAAF proving the existence of an athletic advantage to the benefit of the considered subgroup, 161 a proof it considered reached anyway. The STF also upheld this argument when dealing with Semenya’s petition for annulment. 162

We wonder whether the resulting separation between “the broad class of female athletes” and a minority of women sensitive to high testosterone levels reflects ethno-racial boundaries. To dig deep in this direction, we resort to an intersectional analysis and therefore look at how sex/gender interact with other markers such as ethnic origins and race.Reference Jefferson Lenskyj 163 The type of discrimination arising from this interaction is peculiar in that it does not correspond to the simple sum of the different discriminatory grounds, but to their coalescence. Understanding these intersections helps appreciate the different subordination discourses underlying discrimination.Reference Valdes, Fineman, Jackson and Romero 164

Several authors have remarked that a common trait of the female athletes targeted by the DSD Regulations and their antecedents — including Semenya — is that they all apparently come from the Global South. Reference Munro 165 This circumstance makes these athletes “structurally vulnerable for ‘failing’ gender eligibility regulations.”Reference Oly 166 The United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights asserted that “[t]he existing data do not show much about the intersection between gender and race discrimination in sport, global and local resource inequities and exclusionary community practices.” 167 However, the apparent overrepresentation of athletes from the Global South among those subjected to the IAAF’s scrutiny under the DSD Regulations and their predecessors should raise attention across the board. For instance, by considering that allowing athletes with DSD to compete in the female category would amount to a defeat for the entire female category, the IAAF and the CAS open the door to a majority-minority dynamic. In this context, the logics of power take the shape of the “tyranny of the majority”Reference Davis 168 and the oppression of the minority.

This category-defeating narrative conceals an exercise that sociologists Pierre Bourdieu and Loïc Wacquant would define as “cultural imperialism.” This is “the power to universalize particularisms linked to singular historical tradition by causing them to be misrecognized as such.”Reference Bourdieu and Wacquant 169 Instead of being celebrated as exceptional athletes, athletes from the Global South are cornered with their bodies being obsessively scanned in search of biological explanations of their strength and stunning performances. These explanations build on understandings of body and sexuality that conform to the Western culture. In this perspective, globalized Western conceptualizations of the shape of sex traits and health (so-called) normality prevail over local dimensions of access to health and sexuality. 170 It is therefore not surprising that “the majority of medical experts named in the 2011 and the current [IAAF] policy include mainly men and a few women in Western research and medical institutions who have long-standing relationships with the [IAAF, International Olympics Committee and] national sporting organizations.”Reference Bromdal, Olive and Walker 171

Furthermore, the story of Caster Semenya has a parallel in that of Sarah/Saartjie Baartman, derisively known as the “Hottentot Venus.”Reference Cornwall and Daggers172 Born in Candeboo Valley, South Africa, in 1789, Baartman was brought to Europe in 1810 under the false pretense of a regular employment contract. There she was exhibited half-naked for years, with her body systematically examined by anatomists, zoologists and physiologists. After her death in 1815, her excised genitalia and brain were preserved in formaldehyde and, along with her skeleton, exposed at the Jardin des Plantes and the Musée d’Orsay in Paris.Reference Crais and Scully 173 Obviously, the two centuries that separate Semenya from Baartman — whose remains were returned to South Africa only in 2002 174 — account for completely different historical and geopolitical contexts. Nonetheless, in both cases, the Global North’s eye dehumanizes the Black body, portrayed as the dangerous site of fear and fascination.Reference Ray 175 In both cases, the European gaze submits individuals to analogous exhibition and enfreakment.Reference Schultz 176 Sexualization, pathologization and medicalization are the perfect ingredients for dehumanization of Black bodies.

The main problem with the category-defeating narrative is that it frames the question of the exclusion of athletes with DSD as a simple male-versus-female opposition. A champion of this narrative is certainly Duke law professor Doriane Lambelet Coleman, who acted as a witness expert before the CAS and has written extensively about women in sport and the Semenya case.Reference Lambelet Coleman 177 Coleman’s main argument is that athletes with DSD are so strong that, if they are not excluded somehow, “most of the women who will lose out will be biological females of color.”Reference Lambelet Coleman 178 She also denies that the overrepresentation of athletes from the Global South has any relevance, claiming that “[b]ecause our sport is mostly populated at the elite levels by athletes of color, it is this group that will be most impacted however the women’s category is defined.’ 179 In her opinion, the case is actually more about women’s empowerment and economic opportunities than race.

Although greatly articulated, arguments of this kind tend to adhere to a narrative dominated by “[a] perception of a “tsunami” of men coming to destroy women’s sport.” 180 This narrative neglects both the cultural imperialism that characterizes sport competitions in general, and the suffering of individual athletes in particular. In fact, what remains unclear within the broad discussions surrounding the category-defeating argument is how the stigmatization of athletes with DSD and the imposition of a highly invasive medical treatment to their bodies could do any good to the majority of female competitors.

Consider the story of Uganda’s 800-meter champion Annet Negesa, gold medalist at the 2011 All-Africa Games. After being alerted by her medical team that she could no longer compete, she went to Nice for medical tests and once back in Kampala, underwent an allegedly “simple” surgery, which she knew nothing about.Reference Negesa 181 Having been identified in the media as an “intersex,” Negesa petitioned for — and obtained —the refugee status in Germany as she risked the death penalty in Uganda because of her condition.Reference Abdul 182 Consider also Equatorial Guinean footballer Genoveva Anonma, whom the Confederation of African Football has forced to do a naked parade in front of her team to show that she was a woman;Reference Ahmed 183 or Kenyan runner Maximilla Imali, who was sidelined at the IAAF World Championship after her blood tests revealed that she had hyperandrogenism; 184 or, finally, her peer Margaret Wambui,Reference Omlo 185 who dropped from competing internationally after the CAS ruled on Semenya. That the policing of gender categories brings detrimental harm is patent.

What remains unsolved is the question of how all these dramatic experiences of discrimination, stigmatization, humiliation and exclusion could actually help the majority of women foster their lives in sport. This question remains unsolved after Semenya because for the CAS, the expertise evidence produced by the IAAF on testosterone’s impact on athletic performance has a different weight than the experiential evidence shown by Semenya regarding the side effects of testosterone-suppressing treatment. While the former is praised at length in the award, the latter is trivialized as irrelevant and perhaps even disturbing. After all, how dare Semenya complain about contraceptive-subsequent migraine when there are millions of women out there facing the same? It is unsurprising, then, that in the CAS award, testosterone-driven putative advantage prevails over the evidence of concrete harm suffered by individuals. 186

In sum, the category-defeating narrative is based on a sort of zero-sum consideration. The more a minority of outcast athletes is framed and suppressed, the better the majority’s chances to access to the podium. This narrative raises unsolved social justice matters that are worthy of further reflections at all levels.

Conclusion

This article offers a narratological perspective of the Semenya case. We have problematized the narratives generated by the CAS award and the SFT judgment on Semenya’s discrimination claims. The adjudicators have attempted to present the case outcome as the necessary conclusion of a smooth logic driven by objective, neutral and apologetic considerations.

Yet, the CAS left a large margin of manoeuvre to the IAAF concerning the level of “reasonableness” of scientific evidence, without problematizing the effects of the IAAF acting as a policy maker. What is peculiar is the lack of accountability in relation to an entity exerting broad policy-making powers such as those described in this case. This lacuna of accountability is unique in the international landscape and therefore requires close scrutiny.

The way adjudicators made sense of Semenya’s excellent performance is as flawed as it is stereotyped, gendered and stigmatizing. Sport authorities and adjudicators would like us to believe that the conversation about the DSD Regulation is over. We don’t think this is the case. To the contrary, we believe that a genuine conversation should start at all levels — sport authorities, adjudicators, media, governments, societies — regarding, inter alia, the key actors and networks influencing decision-making processes, the alleged scientific basis supporting eligibility regulations and decisions, and the interplay in sport between adjudication, science, and human rights.

One crucial point, which deserves not just to be stressed, but to be made the object of further research, is why sex/gender-related dimensions of sport are given more attention than other bodily traits. The world is filled with athletes having bone, heart, blood, and muscles advantages, but sport authorities do not look at them as they look at sex/gender-related aspects. Why are some of these advantages celebrated as gifts while others as anomalies? If we believe in fairness, talent, respect, integrity and solidarity, we should pursue these conversations.

Note

The authors have no conflicts to disclose.

Acknowledgments

The authors are grateful to Daniela Alaattinoglu, Florencia Amorena, Michela Balocchi, Coralie Boissel, Mauro Bussani, Giada Di Stefano, Jack Drescher, Marta Infantino, Anna Lorenzetti, Stefano Osella, Graziella Romeo, and Martin Scheinin for their deep insights on earlier drafts of this paper. This paper greatly benefited from the invaluable support provided by Romit Kohli throughout the research and drafting process.

References

Caster Mokgadi Semenya and Athletics South Africa v. International Association of Athletics Federations, CAS 208/O/5794 & CAS 2018/O/5798, Arbitral Award (Apr. 30, 2019).Google Scholar
A. v. International Association of Athletics Federations (IAAF) & Athletics South Africa (ASA), case No. 4A_248/2019 and Athletics South Africa (ASA) v. A. & International Association of Athletic Federations (IAAF), case No. 4A_398/2019 (Federal Tribunal, Switzerland, Aug. 25, 2020).Google Scholar
IAAF Eligibility Regulations for the Female Classification (Athletes with Differences of Sex Development) (DSD Regulations) Sec. 2.2(a) and 2.3(c) (2018); the acronym DSD was born to refer to the highly contested “disorders of sex development;” the expression has turned into the less pathologizing “differences of sex development.” Cf. Consortium on the Management of Disorders of Sex Development, “Clinical Guidelines for the Management of Disorders of Sex Development in Childhood”, 2006 available at <http://www.dsdguidelines.org/files/clinical.pdf> (last visited, Dec. 15, 2020). Yet the international movement for intersex rights considers “DSD” pathologizing and prefers “intersex” or “variations of sex characteristics” (VSC): see M. Balocchi, “È meglio usare il termine intersessuale, intersessuato o inter- sex?”, in B. Paoli et al., eds., Guida Arcobaleno (Torino: Golem 2018): at 226-228. Davis, G., “DSD is a Perfectly Fine Term: Reasserting Medical Authority Through a Shift in Intersex Terminology,” Sociology of Diagnosis Advances in Medical Sociology 12 (2011): 155182. M. Balocchi, “Introduzione: Le ragioni di un”antologia multidisciplinare” in M. Balocchi, ed., Intersex: Antologia Multidisciplinare (Pisa: ETS – àltera PoliTeSse): 15-29, at 20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., Sec. 2.3(b) (2018).Google Scholar
Olympic Charter Art. 4 (2018) (“The practice of sport is a human right. Every individual must have the possibility of practicing sport, without discrimination of any kind and in the Olympic spirit, which requires mutual understanding with a spirit of friendship, solidarity and fair play.”); IAAF’s Constitution Art. 4.1(j) (2019) (recognizing “the right of every individual to participate in Athletics as a sport, without unlawful discrimination of any kind undertaken in the spirit of friendship, solidarity and fair play.”).Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, paras. 548, 626.Google Scholar
A., supra note 2, para. 9.8.3.2.Google Scholar
See Krech, M., “The Misplaced Burdens of ‘Gender Equality’ in Caster Semenya v IAAF: the Court of Arbitration for Sport Attempts Human Rights Adjudication,” International Sports Law Review 19, no. 3 (2019): 6676, at 68; M. Maisonneuve, “Note: Mokgadi Caster Semenya & Athletics South Africa v. IAAF (Award), CAS Case Nos. 2018/O/5794 & 5798, 30 April 2019, and Mokgadi Caster Semenya v. IAAF Federal Supreme Court of Switzerland, 1st Civil Law Chamber, 4A_248/2019, 29 July 2019,” Revue de l’Arbitrage, (2019): 941-965, at 957; J. Cooper, “Testosterone: ‘the Best Discriminating Factor’,” Philosophies 4, no. 3 (2019): 36-51. See also UN Special Rapporteur on the right of everyone to the enjoyment of the highest attainable standard of physical and mental health, UN Special Rapporteur on torture and other cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment, UN Chair-Rapporteur of the Working Group on the issue of discrimination against women in law and in practice, “Regulations regarding eligibility for the female classification (athletes with differences of sex development),” Sept. 18, 2018, UN OL OTH 62/2018, available at <https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Women/WG/Communications/OL-OTH-62-2018.pdf> (last visited October 28, 2021), at 5.Google Scholar
UNGA, “Elimination of Discrimination against Women and Girls in Sport,” A/HRC/40/L.10/Rev. (March 30 2019), para. 3.Google Scholar
Holzer, L., “What Does it Mean to be a Woman in Sports? An Analysis of the Jurisprudence of the Court of Arbitration for Sport,” Human Rights Law Review 20, no. 3 (2020): 387411, at 394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jasanoff, S., “Science, Common Sense & Judicial Power in U.S. Courts,” Daedalus 147, no. 4 (2018): at 16; on the superior cultural authority that biology has acquired to determine what life is and what life is for, see S. Jasanoff, Can Science Make Sense of Life? (Cambridge, UK; Medford, MA: Polity Press, 2019).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
On the belief in the goodness of nature and the connected attribution of a greater hierarchical value to what is “natural” than to what is “unnatural,” see Drescher, J., “From Bisexuality to Intersexuality,” Contemporary Psychoanalysis 43, no. 2 (2007): 204228, at 220-222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liotard, P., “From Apartheid to Segregation in Sport. The Transgressive Body of Caster Mokgadi Semenya,” in Montanola, S. and Olivesi, A., eds., Gender Testing in Sport: Ethics, Cases and Controversies (London and New York: Routledge, 2016): 1426, at 15.Google Scholar
Padawer, R., “Too Fast To Be Female,” in Bryant, H., ed., The Best American Sports Writing 2017 (Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing: New York, 2017): 109125, at 117.Google Scholar
IAAF, Policy on Gender Verification (PGV) Sec. A.5 (2006). IAAF’s Secretary-General Pierre Weiss explained that there were just “visual doubts” about Semenya not being a woman and threatened to strip her of the medal “[i]f at the end of the investigation we find out that her is not a woman”. F. Rose, “Caster Semenya and the Intersex Hypothesis. On Gender as the Visual Evidence of Sex,” in Montanola and Olivesi, supra note 13: 101-117, 106.Google Scholar
PGV, supra note 15.Google Scholar
Schultz, J., Qualifying Times: Points of Change in U.S. Women’s Sport (University of Illinois Press: Chicago, 2014): at 103104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harper, J., Sporting Gender: The History, Science, and Stories of Transgender and Intersex Athletes (Rowman and Littlefield: New York, 2019): at 100101.Google Scholar
Hurst, M., “Caster Semenya Has Male Organs and No Womb or Ovaries,” The Daily Telegraph, Sept. 11, 2009.Google Scholar
Cooky, C. and Dworkin, S. L., “’What Makes a Woman a Woman?’” Versus ‘Our First Lady of Sport’: A Comparative Analysis of the United States and the South African Media Coverage of Caster Semenya,’ Journal of Sport and Social Issues 37, no. 1 (2013): 3156, at 39-41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 45.Google Scholar
IAAF Regulations Governing Eligibility of Females with Hyperandrogenism to Compete in Women’s Competition (Hyperandrogenism Regulations) (2011) and Hyperandrogenism Regulations Explanatory Notes (Explanatory Notes) (2011). A parallel set of rules was enacted by the International Olympic Committee (IOC) on the same subject matter. IOC Regulations on Female Hyperandrogenism, Games of the XXX Olympiad in London (IOC Regulations) (2012).Google Scholar
Hyperandrogenism Regulations, supra note 22, Sec. 1.4 (2011).Google Scholar
Hyperandrogenism Regulations, supra note 22, Sec. 6.5 (2011); IOC Regulations, supra note 22, Art. 8.F (2012).Google Scholar
Hyperandrogenism Regulations, supra note 22, preamble (2011).Google Scholar
The three levels are: (1) an “initial clinical examination” with physical examinations and the compilation of specific clinical and anamnestic data under particularized guidelines; (2) a preliminary endocrine assessment of the athlete’s urine and blood samples for a series of androgenic hormones, among which testosterone; and (3) the athlete’s full examination and subsequent diagnosis.Google Scholar
Explanatory Notes, supra note 22, at 1 (2011).Google Scholar
Id., Artt. 2.1-2.2.5 (2011).Google Scholar
Chand and AFI v IAAF, CAS 2014/A/3759, Interim Arbitral Award (24 July 2015).Google Scholar
Viret, M. and Wisnosky, E., “CAS 2014/A/3759, Chand v. AFI & IAAF, Award of 24 July 2015,” in Duval, A. and Rigozzi, A., eds., Yearbook of International Sports Arbitration 2015 (Asser: The Hague, 2016): 235273, at 237-240.Google Scholar
Padawer, supra note 14, at 118.Google Scholar
Chand, supra note 29, paras. 112-115 and 119-125.Google Scholar
Id., para. 510.Google Scholar
Id., para. 511. See Buzuvis, E., “Hormone Check: Critique of Olympic Rules on Sex and Gender,” Wisconsin Journal of Law, Gender & Society 31, no. 1 (2019): 2956, at 40-41.Google Scholar
Id., para. 532.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3 (2018).Google Scholar
Explanatory Notes, supra note 22, at 1.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 1.1(a) and 1.1(a)(ii) (2018).Google Scholar
See A.B. Wisniewski, “Gender Development in 46,XY DSD: Influences of Chromosomes, Hormones, and Interactions with Parents and Healthcare Professionals,” Scientifica (2012): 1-15, at 2.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 2.2(a)(G) (2018).Google Scholar
Id., Sec. 2.2(a)(iii) (2018).Google Scholar
Ibid., Sec. 2.3(c) (2018).Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, paras. 51-56.Google Scholar
Id., paras. 63-65.Google Scholar
Id., paras. 300-304.Google Scholar
Id., para. 558.Google Scholar
Id., para. 574.Google Scholar
Bermon, S. and Garnier, P.-Y., “Serum Androgen Levels and Their Relation to Performance in Track and Field: Mass Spectrometry Results from 2127 Observations in Male and Female Elite Athletes,” British Journal of Sports Medicine 51 (2017): 13091314; D.J. Handelsman, A.L. Hirschberg and S. Bermon, “Circulating Testosterone as the Hormonal Basis of Sex Differences in Athletic Performance,” Endocrine Reviews 39, no. 17 (2018): 803-829.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Semenya, supra note 1, para. 583.Google Scholar
Id., para. 598.Google Scholar
Id., paras. 606-609.Google Scholar
Id., paras. 612-619.Google Scholar
Id., paras. 609-624.Google Scholar
A., supra note 2, para.5.2.1 (mentioning that this jurisdiction is grounded on Art. 190(2) of the Federal Law on Private International Law of Dec. 18, 1987).Google Scholar
Id., para. 9.1, quoting X S.p.A. v. Y S.r.l., ATF 132 III 389 (Swiss Fed. Trib., March 8, 2006), para. 2.2.3, reported in Favre-Bulle, X., “Case Notes on International Arbitration,” Swiss Review of International and European Law 29, no. 4 (2019): 659689, at 668-669.Google Scholar
A., supra note 2, para. 12.Google Scholar
See for example Sahni, S. and Sinha, C., “Systematic Literature Review on Narratives in Organizations: Research Issues and Avenues for Future Research,” Vision 20, no. 4 (2016): 368379, at 379; M.S. Feldman, K. Sköldberg, R.N. Brown and D. Horner, “Making Sense of Stories: A Rhetorical Approach to Narrative Analysis,” Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 14, no. 2 (2004): 147-170: at 148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
H. Hansen, Narrative Change (New York: Columbia University Press, 2020): at 2; see also, from a linguistic perspective, J.L. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (J.O. Urmson and M. Sbisà eds, Oxford: Clarendon 1975).Google Scholar
See Damodaran, A., Narrative and Numbers (New York: Columbia University Press, 2017): at 14; V. Lowndes and M. Roberts, Why Institutions Matter: The New Institutionalism in Political Science (London: MacMillan International, 2013): at 63-69; S. E. Merry, Human Rights and Gender Violence: Translating International Law into Local Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2006): at 89-98, 134-178.Google Scholar
Brooks, P., “Narrativity of the Law,” Law and Literature 14, no. 1 (2002): 110, at 8.Google Scholar
Pape, M., “Expertise and Non-Binary Bodies: Sex, Gender and the Case of Dutee Chand,” Body and Society 25, no. 4 (2019): 328, at 12-15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Id., at 14.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 1.1(e) (2018).Google Scholar
E.g., Semenya, supra note 2, para. 464.Google Scholar
A., supra note 2, para. 10.3.Google Scholar
J. Butler, “Wise Distinctions. Thoughts on Caster Semenya,” London Review of Books, Nov. 20, 2009.Google Scholar
A. Olivesi, “From the Implicit to Aporia. The Specificities of the Caster Semenya Case as a ‘Discursive Moment’,” in Montanola and Olivesi, supra note 13, at 89-100, at 91; on the politics of bodies as a form of power and, particularly, sex as a dispositive to administer, control and police bodies, see M. Foucault, Histoire de la Sexualité: La Volonté de Savoir (Paris: Gallimard 1976): at 26, 35.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 3.3 (2018).Google Scholar
Cook, R.J. and Cusack, S, Gender Stereotyping: Transnational Legal Perspectives (Philadelphia: Unversity of Pennsylvania Press 2010), at 9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plaza, M., Boiché, J., Brunel, L., and Ruchaud, F., “Sport = Male … But Not All Sports: Investigating the Gender Stereotypes of Sport Activities at the Explicit and Implicit Levels,” Sex Roles 76, no. 1 (2017): 202217, at 214; C. Rodriguez Fernandez, J. Ospina Betancur, and J. Piedra de la Cuadra, “Athletic Body Stereotypes in the Academic Training of Students in the Physical Activity Sport Sciences,” Journal of Human Sport and Exercise 11, no. 3-4 (2016): 74-88, at 83-85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bohnet, I., What Works: Gender Equality By Design (Harvard University Press: Cambridge, 2016): at 3344.Google Scholar
Liotard, supra note 13, at 17-18.Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, para. 462.Google Scholar
Bohoun, A. and Rodriguez, E., “Gender Verifications vs. Anti-Doping Policies. Sexes Controls,” in Montanola and Olivesi, supra note 13: 2745, at 33.Google Scholar
Anne Fausto-Sterling has investigated the results of employing classifications systems which expand male and female categories; she shows, for instance, how scientific methods can be used to classify certain people out of existence; this has been the case of, for example, the distinction between the so-called “pseudo” and “true hermaphrodites,” based on organs of sexual reproduction as determinant of one’s “true” sex: see Fausto-Sterling, A., Sexing the Body: Gender Politics and the Construction of Sexuality (New York: Basic Books, 2000): at 3839.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 3.4 (2018).Google Scholar
Id., Sec. 3.4(a)(ii) (2018).Google Scholar
Id., Sec. 3.4(b) (2018).Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 2 (2018).Google Scholar
Holzer, supra note 10, at 402.Google Scholar
Hyperandrogenism Regulations, supra note 22, preface.Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, para. 560.Google Scholar
Krech, supra note 8, at 69.Google Scholar
Heggie, V., “Testing Sex and Gender in Sports: Reinventing, Reimagining and Reconstructing Histories,” Endeavour 34, no. 4 (2010): 157163, at 158.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Petersen, J.E., “Regulating Abortion and Birth Control: Gender, Medicine, and Republican Politics in France, 1870–1920,” French Historical Studies 19, no. 3 (1996): 673698, at 696-698.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eliott-Lynn, S, Athletics for Women and Girls: How to be an Athlete and Why (Scott, 1925): at 111, quoted in J. Hargreaves, Sporting Females: Critical Issues in the History and Sociology of Women’s Sports (Routledge: New York, 1994): at 65. See also id., at 212-213.Google Scholar
McCrone, K E, “Play up! Play up! And Play the Game! Sport at the Late Victorian Girls’ Public School,” in Mangan, J.A. and Park, R.J., eds., From “Fair Sex” to Feminism. Sport and the Socialization of Women in the Industrial and Post-Industrial Eras (Routledge: New York, 2004): 98129, at 104; N. Carter, Medicine, Sport and the Body: A Historical Perspective (Bloomsbury Academy: New York, 2012).Google Scholar
Ferez, S., “From Women’s Exclusion to Gender Institution: A Brief History of the Sexual Categorization Process within Sport,” in Gori, G. and Mangan, J.A., eds., Sport and Emancipation of European Women: The Struggle for Self-Fulfilment (Routledge: New York, 2016): at 70, 71.Google Scholar
Statut de Comité International Olympique (IOC: Paris, 1924): at 13.Google Scholar
Haggie, supra note 85, at 160.Google Scholar
Chand, supra note 29, para. 35(g).Google Scholar
Chand, supra note 29, para. 35(g).Google Scholar
Simpson, J. Leigh et al., “Gender Verification in the Olympics,” Journal of American Medical Association 284, no. 12 (2000): 15681569, at 1569.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Erikainen, S., “Hybrids, Hermaphrodites, and Sex Metamorphoses: Gendered Anxieties and Sex Testing in Elite Sport, 1937–1968”, in Demos, V. and Segal, M. Texler, eds., Gender Panic, Gender Policy (Emerald Publishing: New York, 2017): at 155176, 166-167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, A., “Back to the Binary: How the Olympics Struggle with Separation of Male and Female,” DePaul Journal of Sports Law and Contemporary Problems 14, no. 1 (2018): 132, at 11; Buzuvis, supra note 34, at 32.Google Scholar
De Meo, L., “Sport, Sexual Dimorphism and Gender Binarism: Intersexuality in Sports Law,” in Singh, A., Chanda, S. and Jedrzejewski, S., Sports Law & Policy in Present Global Scenario (Black Aviat Publishing: Lucknow, 2020): at 3450, at 36-38; J. Hood-Williams, “Sexing the Athletes,” Sociology of Sport Journal 12, no. 3 (1995): 290-305, at 300.Google Scholar
Erikainen, S., Gender Verification and the Making of the Female Body in Sport: A History of the Present (Routledge: New York, 2019); see also J.L. Rupert, “Genitals to Genes: The History and Biology of Gender Verification in the Olympics,” Canadian Bulletin of Medical History 28, no. 2 (2011): 339-365, at 340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Bach Yen Nguyen, A., “Fairness at a Price: Protecting the Integrity of Athletic Competition at the Expense of Female Athletes,” Notre Dame Journal of International and Comparative Law 8, no. 1 (2018): 5475, at 61-63.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 1.1(e) (2018).Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, paras. 574-575.Google Scholar
Id., para. 579.Google Scholar
Karkazis, K. and Jourdan-Young, R.M., Testosterone: An Unauthorized Biography (Harvard University Press: Cambridge, 2019): at 193197.Google Scholar
Chand, supra note 29, para. 528.Google Scholar
Id., para. 527.Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 2, para. 574.Google Scholar
Although “CAS panels unambiguously reject the notion that they apply a doctrine of stare decisis” they “de facto adhere[d] to precedent.” Bersagel, A., “Is There a Stare Decisis Doctrine in the Court of Arbitration for Sport? An Analysis of Published Awards for Anti-Doping Disputes in Track and Field,” Pepperdine Dispute Resolution Law Journal 12, no. 2 (2012): 189213, at 204.Google Scholar
See Bermon, S. and Garnier, P.Y., “Serum Androgen Levels and their Relation to Performance in Track and Field: Mass Spectrometry Results from 2127 Observations in Male and Female Elite Athletes,” British Journal of Sports Medicine 51, no. 17 (2017): 13091314, at 1312.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Handelsman, supra note 48.Google Scholar
T. Ross, “The Semenya Decision: Full CAS Report Brief Thoughts,” June 19, 2019, available at <https://sportsscientists.com/2019/06/the-semenya-decision-full-cas-report-brief-thoughts/> (last visited October 28, 2021).+(last+visited+October+28,+2021).>Google Scholar
See Semenya, supra note 1, paras. 351-367.Google Scholar
Bermon and Garnier, supra note 108, at 1312.Google Scholar
Franklin, S., Betancurt, J. Ospina, and Camporesi, S., “What Statistical Data of Observational Performance Can Tell Us and What They Cannot: The Case of Dutee Chand v. AFI & IAAF,” British Journal of Sports Medicine 52 (2018): 420421. See also R. Pielke Jr., R. Tucker, and E. Boye, “Scientific Integrity and the IAAF Testosterone Regulations,” The International Sports Law Journal 19, no. 1 (2019): 18-26, and “Correction to: Scientific Integrity and the IAAF Testosterone Regulations,” The International Sports Law Journal 19, no. 1 (2019): 27-28 (conclusions unchanged).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franklin, Ospina, and Camporesi, supra note 113, at 421.Google Scholar
Sonksen, P.H., Bavington, L. Dawn, Boehning, T. et al., “Hyperandrogenism Controversy in Elite Women’s Sport: An Examination and Critique of Recent Evidence,” British Journal of Sport Medicine 52, no. 23 (2018): 14811482.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Camporesi, S., “When Does an Advantage Become Unfair? Empirical and Normative Concerns in Semenya’s Case,” Journal of Medical Ethics 45, no. 11 (2019): 700704, at 701.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pielke, Tucker, and Boye, supra note 113, at 25.Google Scholar
Handelsman, Hirschbeidrg, and Bermon, supra note 109, at 822-823.Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 2, para. 367.Google Scholar
Pielke, Tucker, and Boye, supra note 113, at 25.Google Scholar
. Id., at 20-26.Google Scholar
S. Camporesi, “Clear Skies Overhead for Dutee Chand, but Clouds Loom on the Horizon,” HuffPost Sports, July 30, 2015, available at <https://www.huffpost.com/entry/clear-skies-overhead-for-_b_7896924> (last visited October 28, 2021). See also Camporesi, S., “Ethics of Regulating Competition for Women with Hyperandrogenism,” Clinics in Sports Medicine 35, no. 2 (2016): 293301.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Chand, supra note 29, para. 543.Google Scholar
Id., para. 534.Google Scholar
Pape, supra note 61, at 15.Google Scholar
UN Special Rapporteurs, supra note 8, at 4.Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 2, paras. 491-493.Google Scholar
Karkazis and Jourdan-Young, supra note 103, at 185.Google Scholar
Bermon, S., Garnier, P.Y., “Correction: Serum Androgen Levels and Their Relation to Performance in Track and Field: Mass Spectrometry Results from 2127 Observations in Male and Female Elite Athletes,” British Journal of Sports Medicine 55, no. 17 (2021): doi: 10.1136/bjsports-2017-097792.Google Scholar
See Ostrander, E. A., Huson, H. J., and Ostrander, G. K., “Genetics of Athletic Performance,” Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 10 (2009): 407429. Y. Pitsiladis et al., “Genomics of Elite Sporting Performance: What Little We Know and Necessary Advances,” British Journal of Sports Medicine 47, no. 9 (2013): 550-555.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 2.3(b) (2018).Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 2, para. 595.Google Scholar
Id., para. 594.Google Scholar
Id., para. 598.Google Scholar
A., supra note 2, para. 10.2.Google Scholar
Karkazis, K. and Carpenter, M, “Impossible “Choices”: The Inherent Harms of Regulating Women’s Testosterone in Sport,” Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 15, no. 4 (2018): 579587, at 583.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 2.4 (2018).Google Scholar
J. Macur, “Fighting for the Body She Was Born With,” New York Times, October 6, 2014.Google Scholar
Bermon, S., Vilain, E., Fénichel, P., and Ritzén, M., “Women with Hyperandrogenism in Elite Sports: Scientific and Ethical Rationales for Regulating,” Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 99 (2014): 43284335, at 4329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Semenya, supra note 2, para 592.Google Scholar
Copperman, A.B. and Benadiva, C., “Optimal Use of the GnRH Antagonists: A Review of the Literature,” Reproductive Biology and Endocrinology 11, no. 20 (2013): 1120, at 20.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
See J. Macur, “Fighting for the Body She Was Born With,” New York Times, Oct. 6, 2014.Google Scholar
Fénichel, P., Paris, F., Philibert, P., and Hiéronimus, Sylvie, et al., “Molecular Diagnosis of 5 Alpha-Reductase Deficiency in 4 Elite Young Female Athletes through Hormonal Screening for Hyperandrogenism,” Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Metabolism 98, no. 6 (2013): E1055E1059, at E1057.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bermon, S., Vilain, E., Fénichel, P., and Ritzén, M., “Women with Hyperandrogenism in Elite Sports: Scientific and Ethical Rationales for Regulating,” Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 99 (2014): 43284335, at 4329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, para. 454.Google Scholar
De Beauvoir, S., The Second Sex (Jonathan Cape: London, 1956): at 273.Google Scholar
See, inter alia, S.J. Kessler, Lessons from the Intersexed (Rutgers University Press 1998): at 12; Chau, P.L. and Herring, J., “Defining, Assigning and Designing Sex,” International Journal of Law, Policy and the Family 16, no. 3 (2002): 6585; J.A. Greenberg, “Defining Male and Female: Intersexuality and the Collision between Law and Biology,” Arizona Law Review 41, no. 2 (1999): 265-328, at 265, 272; M. Davies, “Taking the Inside Out: Sex and Gender in the Legal Subject,” in N. Naffine and R. Owens, eds., Sexing the Subject of Law (Sweet and Maxwell: New York, 1997): at 25-46.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Orbach, S., Bodies (Profile Books: London, 2019): at 80.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 2.5 (2018).Google Scholar
UNGA, Report of the Special Rapporteur on the Right of Everyone to the Enjoyment of the Highest Attainable Standard of Physical and Mental Health, UN Doc A/HRC/32/33 (April 4 2016), para. 57.Google Scholar
UN Special Rapporteur on the right of everyone to the enjoyment of the highest attainable standard of physical and mental health, UN Special Rapporteur on torture and other cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment, UN Chair-Rapporteur of the Working Group on the issue of discrimination against women in law and in practice, “Regulations Regarding Eligibility for the Female Classification (athletes with differences of sex development),” Sept. 18, 2018, UN OL OTH 62/2018, available at <https://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Health/Letter_IAAF_Sept2018.pdf> (last visited October 28, 2021), at 5.+(last+visited+October+28,+2021),+at+5.>Google Scholar
Report of the Special Rapporteur on the Right of Everyone to the Enjoyment of the Highest Attainable Standard of Physical and Mental Health, UN Doc A/64/272 (August 10 2009), paras 13, 14.Google Scholar
Karkazis, K. and Carpenter, M., “Impossible ‘Choices:’ The Inherent Harms of Regulating Women’s Testosterone in Sport,” Bioethical Inquiry 15, no. 4 (2018): 579587, at 586.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 2.3(b) (2018).Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, para. 616.Google Scholar
Maisonneuve, supra note 8, at 957.Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, para. 551.Google Scholar
Cooper, supra note 8, para. 3.7.Google Scholar
DSD Regulations, supra note 3, Sec. 1.1(e) (2018).Google Scholar
Semenya, supra note 1, paras. 563-564.Google Scholar
A., supra note 2, para. 9.8.3.4.Google Scholar
See Jefferson Lenskyj, H., Gender Politics and the Olympic Industry (Palgrave Macmillan: New York, 2013): at 1819. On intersectional analysis in general see K. Crenshaw, “Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory and Antiracist Politics,” University of Chicago Legal Forum 1989, no. 1 (1989): 139-167, at 151-152; G. de Beco, “Protecting the Invisible: An Intersectional Approach to International Human Rights Law,” Human Rights Law Review 17, no. 4 (2017): 633-663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valdes, F., “Queering Sexual Orientation: A Call for Theory as Praxis,” in Fineman, M., Jackson, J.E., and Romero, A.P., eds., Feminist and Queer Legal Theory: Intimate Encounters, Uncomfortable Conversations (Ashgate: New York, 2009): 91111, at 94.Google Scholar
See Anand Grover’s expert witness in Semenya, supra note 1, para. 219. See also Munro, B., “Caster Semenya: Gods and Monsters,” Safundi: The Journal of South African and American Studies 11, no. 4 (2020): 383396; S. Mahomed and A. Dhai, “Global Injustice in Sport: The Caster Semenya Ordeal — Prejudice, Discrimination and Racial Bias,” South African Medical Journal 109, no. 8 (2019): 548-551, at 550; K. Karkazis and Jordan-Young, “The Powers of Testosterone: Obscuring Race and Regional Bias in the Regulation of Women Athletes,” Femminist Formation 30, no. 2 (2018): 1-39; A. Bohuon, “Gender Verifications in Sport: From an East/West Antagonism to a North/South Antagonism,” The International Journal of the History of Sport 32, no. 7 (2015): 965-979, at 966.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oly, M. Pape, “The Unlevel Global Playing Field of Gender Eligibility Regulation in Sport,” Human Rights Defender 29, no. 2 (2020): 4143, at 41.Google Scholar
UN Human Rights Council, “Intersection of Race and Gender Discrimination in Sport: Report of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights,” A/HRC/44/26 (June 15 2020), para. 10.Google Scholar
Davis, H. Fogg, Beyond Trans: Does Gender Matter? (New York University Press: New York, 2018): at 114.Google Scholar
Bourdieu, P. and Wacquant, L., “On the Cunning of Imperialist Reason,” Theory, Culture & Society 16, no. 1 (1999): 4158, at 41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bohuon, supra note 158, at 975.Google Scholar
Bromdal, A., Olive, R., and Walker, B., “Questioning Representations of Athletes with Elevated Testosterone Levels in Elite Women’s Sports: A Critical Policy Analysis,” International Journal of Sport Policy and Politics 12, no. 4 (2020): 699715.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See Cornwall, S., “’From a Remote Rural Village in Limpopo:’ Colonized Bodies, Hybrid Sex and Postcolonial Theology,” in Daggers, J., ed., Gendering Christian Ethics (New Castle: Cambridge, 2012): at 147167; D. Lewis, “Representing African Sexualities,” in S. Tamale, African Sexualities: A Reader (Pambazuka Press: Cape Town, 2011): 199-216, at 202-203. On the connection between the narratives surrounding Baartman and neoliberalism see S. Lloyd, “Sara Baartman and the “Inclusive Exclusions” of Neoliberalism,” Meridians: Feminism, Race, Transnationalism 11, no. 2 (2013): 212-237.Google Scholar
Crais, C. and Scully, P., Sara Baartman and the Hottentot Venus: A Ghost Story and Biography (Princeton University Press: Woodstock, 2011): at 116.Google Scholar
Ray, C., “Caster Semenya 21st Century “Hottentot Venus”,” New African (2009): 18-19.Google Scholar
Schultz, J., “New Standards, Same Refrain: The IAAF’s Regulations on Hyperandrogenism,” American Journal of Bioethics 12, no. 7 (2012): 3234, at 32-33.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Semenya, supra note 1, paras. 390-399. See also Lambelet Coleman, D., “Sex in Sport,Law and Contemporary Problems 80, no. 4 (2017): 63126.Google Scholar
Lambelet Coleman, D., “A Victory for Female Athletes Everywhere,” Quillette, May 3, 2019, available at <https://quillette.com/2019/05/03/a-victory-for-female-athletes-everywhere> (last visited October 28, 2021).+(last+visited+October+28,+2021).>Google Scholar
Tucker, supra note 110.Google Scholar
Negesa, A., “The Story in Her Own Words,” Human Rights Defender 29, no. 2 (2020): 3637, at 37.Google Scholar
Abdul, G., “This Intersex Runner Had Surgery to Compete. It Has Not Gone Well,” New York Times, Dec. 16, 2019.Google Scholar
Ahmed, S., “The Violation of Genoveva Anonma,” Africa is a Country, available at <https://africasacountry.com/2015/01/genoveva-anonma-gender-testing> (last visited October 28, 2021).+(last+visited+October+28,+2021).>Google Scholar
“IAAF World Relays: Two Kenyan Female Sprinters Dropped over Testosterone Levels,” Sportstar, May 10, 2019, available at <https://sportstar.thehindu.com/athletics/athletics-kenya-drops-maximilla-imali-and-evangeline-makena-over-testosterone-levels-iaaf-world-relays-championship/article27095998.ece> (last visited October 28, 2021).+(last+visited+October+28,+2021).>Google Scholar
Omlo, I., “Athletics: Kenyans Pull out of Worlds after Failing to Take Tests,” Reuters, Sept 19, 2019, available at <https://www.reuters.com/article/us-athletics-kenya/athletics-kenyans-pull-out-of-worlds-after-failing-to-take-tests-idUSKBN1W42KE> (last visited October 28, 2021).+(last+visited+October+28,+2021).>Google Scholar
Karkazis and Jourdan-Young, supra note 103, at 200.Google Scholar