Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-gr6zb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-23T20:59:14.879Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

ELSI Implications of Prioritizing Biological Therapies in Times of COVID-19

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2021

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Independent Articles: Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 2020

In their recent paper, Bladt et al.Reference Bladt, Vorup-Jensen, Sædder and Ebbesen1 focus on the delicate question of whether the four principles of biomedical ethics identified by Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. ChildressReference Beauchamp and Childress2 are reflected in the process of prioritization of financial resources in the Danish heath care system. They focus on biological treatment and multiple sclerosis, conducting a study based on eight semi-structured interviews.

Since ethical challenges are often intertwined with legal and social implications, we would like to use this opportunity to add some perspectives from the legal and regulatory sciences that we regard as particularly relevant in the ongoing SARS-Cov-2 pandemic. There is no doubt that COVID-19 will have a substantial impact on access to biologics and biosimilar uptake, as well as on the related ethical, legal, and social dimensions of prioritization decisions. This holds especially true for Denmark and European markets, where governments are expected to cover most of the pharmaceutical needs of their citizens and where the crisis has been leading to an important reduction of available resources.Reference Diaz3 Thus, we would like to make four key comments relating to (1) broader ethico-legal dimensions of prioritizations in Europe, (2) human rights law and (3) regulatory aspects of access, diversification, vulnerability and systemic trust, and (4) additional challenges posed by COVID-19.

Firstly, the issue of prioritization of scarce resources is not a new issue, but it becomes particularly critical in times of crisis. Several studies point towards different ways of rationing health resources.Reference Boyd and Potter4 For example, Persad, Wertheimer, and Emanuel published interesting work on the ethics and allocation of very scarce medical interventions, such as organs and vaccines, arguing that there are no “value-free medical criteria for allocation.”Reference Persad, Wertheimer and Emanuel5 In this context, biomedical ethics principles offer relevant guidelines to discuss such prioritization. Bladt et al’s. choice to use the four principles of biomedical ethics is justified by relying on a study that concluded Denmark was aligned with those principles.Reference Ebbesen and Pedersen6 It is true that the content of those principles have a universal scope, but Bladt et al. admit that their weights can differ. However, since their study focuses on Denmark, it could be interesting to place those principles in a European context by referring in particular to the “four ethical principles” common of European bioethics: autonomy, dignity, integrity and vulnerability.7 Beyond terminology, there are certainly overlaps between those principles. Yet, the principle of dignity, constantly referenced in Europe, is much less present in the American ethico-legal debate. Besides, Bladt et al ignore the principle of solidarity, although quite important in the Danish context. In this regard, we welcome that the authors’ empirical study allowed the persons interviewed to formulate other principles than those set out in their original framework. Indeed, it is important to note that one of the essential elements of the right to health according to international law is that it is both culturally appropriate and respectful of medical ethics.8

Second, Bladt et al. focus on principles of bioethics and moral obligations which is both understandable to limit the scope of the study and consistent with the authors’ research question. However, they do not account for law, although studies on prioritization of health resources would benefit from engaging with state obligations under human rights law. Denmark is bound by several international and European legal instruments on bioethics, health, or more broadly, the protection of vulnerable people.9 Denmark must respect, protect, and fulfill human rights in biomedicine, which makes it not only a relevant, but a mandatory source to assess its policies. While it will not solve all health dilemmas, the World Health Organization encourages a human rights-based approach to health. Human rights law requires states to ensure equitable access and non-discrimination in health care. Human rights treaties and courts also give states some discretion when it comes to manage scarce resources and establish criteria of allocation.10 This also applies to limit compassionate use of experimental drugs, an issue that was at the center of the seminal Charlie Gard case. In that case, the UK authorities denied to the parents of a baby with severe brain damage a right to maintain life support and to access to experimental treatment available in the US. In conformity with its prior jurisprudence, the European Court of Human Rights found the application inadmissible and upheld the UK judicial decision.11 The polarization of the debate surrounding those findings,Reference Truog12 demonstrates the divergence of conceptions on access to experimental treatments and prioritization of resources.

Finally, and notwithstanding the past impressive successes of the Danish regulatory framework for biologics and biosimilars’ uptake, we believe that the remaining lack of certainty in biosimilars might become an increasingly important issue that is aggravated by COVID-19. The push towards more use of follow-on products is likely to intensify as a means to drive cost reductions in strained health systems. This will also enhance public pressure on pharmaceutical pricing and fuel the related controversies over the current frameworks for intellectual property rights, trade secrets, pharmaceutical regulation and competition law. We therefore assume that COVID-19 will substantially influence the perceptions, approaches, and regulatory options with regard to physician-led switching and pharmacist-led substitution of biosimilars and originator biologics.

Third, an additional part of prioritization of resources is to look into diversifying the available treatments and increasing access to affordable medicines to decrease the need for such prioritization. One such means was the introduction of biosimilars to often costly originator biologics.Reference Tsiftsoglou, Ruiz and Schneider13 While market challenges for these products still exist,14 biosimilars need to be used to fulfill the aim of their regulatory introduction. The reluctance to use these products by treating physicians as described by Bladt et al. indicate that there is a regulatory issue at stake even in a country such as Denmark with high biosimilar uptake.15 Physician skepticism towards these follow-on products have been reported extensively and is present among about two-thirds of physicians according to a recent review.16 Thus, the high standard of biosimilars in the European Union seemingly remains untranslated into trust and certainty amongst physicians. A risk associated with physician skepticism is its influence on patients and their willingness to use these products. A study found that 21% of patients were more willing to switch to biosimilars if the information was positively framed17 and concerns among patients relate to uncertainty of differences in safety or efficacy compared to the originator.18 For increasing access to medicines via biosimilars, physicians must be able to counsel patients with their concerns as attempt to facilitate positive non-medical switches and limit negative patient expectations (also known as the nocebo effect).19 This is especially important in countries such as Denmark with almost mandatory switches due to tender procurement and prescription guidelines.20 However, overall, these considerations assume that the given patients can access biological medicines. In dire cases, and especially in a time of crisis such as COVID-19, some patients may be left more vulnerable and face increasing social consequences if medicines are not introduced to a market due to their prices, a possibility raised by participants in the study by Bladt et al. To stabilize biosimilar uptake, more effective initiatives are needed to facilitate physician trust in these products — which will be communicated to patients — and such initiatives are tasks likely to end up on desks in governments and medicines authorities.

Finally, and notwithstanding the past impressive successes of the Danish regulatory framework for biologics and biosimilars’ uptake,21 we believe that the remaining lack of certainty in biosimilars might become an increasingly important issue that is aggravated by COVID-19. The push towards more use of follow-on products is likely to intensify as a means to drive cost reductions in strained health systems.22 This will also enhance public pressure on pharmaceutical pricing and fuel the related controversies over the current frameworks for intellectual property rights, trade secrets, pharmaceutical regulation and competition law. We therefore assume that COVID-19 will substantially influence the perceptions, approaches, and regulatory options with regard to physician-led switching and pharmacist-led substitution of biosimilars and originator biologics.

Since there is much ado about something in the biosimilar space, we see a strong need for further interdisciplinary ethical, legal, and social research in this area.

Footnotes

Louise C. Druedahl is funded by a Ph.D. fellowship grant to the University of Copenhagen from LEO Pharma A/S. The funder had no role in the design or conduct of the study, collection, management, analysis, or interpretation of data; or the decision to submit the manuscript for publication. The research of Timo Minssen and Audrey Lebret is supported by the University of Copenhagen’s DATA+ pool (Strategy 2023 funds). Moreover, Timo Minssen is supported by the scientifically independent Collaborative Research Program for Biomedical Innovation Law, which is supported by the Novo Nordisk Foundation (grant NNF17SA0027784). The funders had no role in the preparation, review, or approval of the manuscript and decision to submit the manuscript for publication. The authors have no other conflicts of interest to disclose.

References

Bladt, T.M., Vorup-Jensen, T., Sædder, E. A., and Ebbesen, M.Empirical Investigation of Ethical Challenges Related to the Use of Biological Therapies,” Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 48, no. 3 (2020): 567568.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
These are respect for autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, nonmaleficence, respect for autonomy, and justice. See Beauchamp, T. L. and Childress, J. F., Principles of Biomedical Ethics 7th ed., (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), part II.Google Scholar
Diaz, J.I., “How Will COVID-19 Impact Biosimilar Trends In The Top 5 European Markets?” Biosimilar Development (May 5, 2020), available at <https://www.biosimilardevelopment.com/doc/how-will-covid-impact-biosimilar-trends-in-thetop-european-markets-0001> (last visited August 17, 2020).+(last+visited+August+17,+2020).>Google Scholar
Boyd, K.M. and Potter, B.T., “Priorities in the Allocation of Scarce Resources,” Journal of Medical Ethics 12, no. 4 (1986): 197200, doi:10.1136/jme.12.4.197; P.E. Liss, “Allocation of Scarce Resources in Health Care: Values and Concepts,” Texto & Contexto — Enfermagem 15 (2006): 125-134, doi: 10.1590/ S0104-07072006000500014; G. Curigliano, M.J. Cardoso, P. Poortmans, et al., “Recommendations for Triage, Prioritization and Treatment of Breast Cancer Patients During the COVID-19 Pandemic,” Breast 52, no. 8 (2020), doi:10.1016/j.breast.2020.04.00.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Persad, G., Wertheimer, A. and Emanuel, E. J., “Principles for Allocation of Scare Medical Interventions,” Lancet 373, no. 9661 (2009): 423431, at 423, doi: 10.1016/S0140-6736(09)60137-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ebbesen, M. and Pedersen, B.D., “Empirical Investigation of the Ethical Reasoning of Physicians and Molecular Biologists—the Importance of the Four Principles of Biomedical Ethics,” Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 2, no. 23 (2007): 116, doi: 10.1186/1747-5341-2-23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
See in particular J.D. Rendtorff and P. Kemp, Basic Ethical Principles in European Bioethics and Biolaw—Volume 1: Autonomy, Dignity, Integrity and Vulnerability, Report to the European Commission of the BIOMED-II Project, (Etik & Ret, 2000).Google Scholar
CESCR General Comment No. 14: “The Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of Health,” 11 August 2000 (in Document E/C.12/2000/4).Google Scholar
See the Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine, 4 April 1997, ratified by Denmark in 1999. See also the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), 16 December 1966, ratified by Denmark in 1972 (Art. 12 on the right to health etc). Among treaties related to vulnerable persons, see Convention on the Rights of the Child, 20 November 1989, ratified by Denmark in 1991 or Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, 13 December 2006, ratified by Denmark in 2009.Google Scholar
See CESCR General Comment No. 14: “The Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of Health,” 11 August 2000, Id. See also the case Pentiacova from the European Court of Human Rights, in which the Court found inadmissible the applications of several persons who claimed that the absence of reimbursement of hemodialysis breached their right to life and their right to private life. Pentiaova and others v. Moldada, App. N°14462/03 (2005).Google Scholar
Charles Gard and others v. UK, App n° 39793/17 (2017), at the core of this case, the interpretation of the “best interest of the child”. Prior decisions of the Court: see Hristozov and others v. Bulgaria, App. Nos. 47039/11 and 358/12 (2012) and Durisotto v. Italy, App. n° 62804/13 (2014). The applications were found inadmissible.Google Scholar
Truog, R.D., “The United Kingdom Sets Limits on Experimental Treatments: The Case of Charlie Gard,” JAMA 318, no. 11 (2017): 10011002, doi: 10.1001/jama.2017.10410.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tsiftsoglou, A.S., Ruiz, S., and Schneider, C.K.. “Development and Regulation of Biosimilars: Current Status and Future Challenges,” BioDrugs 27, no. 3 (2013): 203211, doi: 10.1007/s40259-013-0020-y.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
IQVIA. “The Impact of Biosimilar Competition in Europe,” (Oct, 2019), available at <https://ec.europa.eu/docsroom/documents/31642/attachments/1/translations/en/renditions/native> (last visited August 17, 2020).+(last+visited+August+17,+2020).>Google Scholar
IQVIA, D. Long, Vice President, Industry Relations, “Global /US Generics and Biosimilars: Trends, Issues and Outlook,” (February 5, 2019), available at <https://www.accessiblemeds.org/sites/default/files/2019-02/Doug-Long-Access2019.pdf> (last visited August 17, 2020)+(last+visited+August+17,+2020)>Google Scholar
K. Sarnola, M. Merikoski, J. Jyrkkä, and K. Hämeen-Anttila, “Physicians’ Perceptions of the Uptake of Biosimilars: A Systematic Review,” British Medical Journal Open 10 (2020): e034183, doi:10.1136/bmjopen-2019-034183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
C. Gastieger, A.S.K. Jones, M. Kleinstäuber, et al., “The Effects of Message Framing on Patients’ Perceptions and Willingness to Change to a Biosimilar in a Hypothetical Drug Switch,” Arthritis Care Research (2019), doi: 10.1002/acr.24012.CrossRefGoogle Scholar