Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-mzp66 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T03:31:12.163Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Legal personhood and the firm: avoiding anthropomorphism and equivocation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 July 2015

DAVID GINDIS*
Affiliation:
Hertfordshire Business School, University of Hertfordshire, Hatfield AL10 9AB, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

From the legal point of view, ‘person’ is not co-extensive with ‘human being’. Nor is it synonymous with ‘rational being’ or ‘responsible subject’. Much of the confusion surrounding the issue of the firm's legal personality is due to the tendency to address the matter with only these, all too often conflated, definitions of personhood in mind. On the contrary, when the term ‘person’ is defined in line with its original meaning as ‘mask’ worn in the legal drama, it is easy to see that it is only the capacity to attract legal relations that defines the legal person. This definition, that avoids the undesirable emotional associations and equivocations that often plague the debate, is important for a legally grounded view of the firm.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Millennium Economics Ltd 2015 

1. Introduction

In order to become a fully operational firm in a modern market economy, an entrepreneur or an association of resource owners need to go through a relatively straightforward registration (or incorporation) procedure. This constitutive procedure creates a separate legal person (or legal entity) with the capacity for property, contract and litigation, without which firms would not be able to properly function.Footnote 1 The assignment of separate legal personality is a key aspect of law's institutional support for the firm.

Legal entity status is a necessary part of the explanation of the firm's enhanced transactional capabilities as compared to bilateral exchange. In effect, the legal system creates an efficiency-enhancing nexus for contracts that literally carries the organizational framework of the firm. By vesting ownership rights to the assets used in production in the legal entity law secures its continuity by locking-in the founders’ committed capital, thereby allowing them to pledge assets, raise finance and do business in the firm's own name (Blair, Reference Blair2003; Deakin et al., forthcoming; Gindis, Reference Gindis2009; Hansmann, Reference Hansmann, Gibbons and Roberts2013; Hodgson, Reference Hodgson2002; Orts, Reference Orts2013; Robé, Reference Robé2011).

Strikingly, these institutional facts about the role of legal personality in the creation and operation of firms are all but absent in the theory of the firm literature. In part, this state of affairs is imputable to the general reluctance of economists to rely on legal concepts of the firm, and to sustained efforts to define the firm with little or no reference to law. Relatively little has changed since Masten (Reference Masten1988: 185) observed that ‘economists have either downplayed or rejected outright the role of the law in defining the firm’.Footnote 2

But the widespread lack of appreciation among theorists of the firm of the key economic advantages of legal entity status (Blair, Reference Blair and Grandori2004; Iacobucci and Triantis, Reference Iacobucci and Triantis2007; Kornhauser and MacLeod, Reference Kornhauser, MacLeod, Gibbons and Roberts2013; Schanze, Reference Schanze2006) can also be attributed to Jensen and Meckling (Reference Jensen and Meckling1976) ambiguous discussion in the only classic of the genre to mention legal personality. Their dismissal of this ‘legal fiction’ that inevitably fuels nonsensical anthropomorphic talk of the firm's objectives and responsibilities has arguably had a lasting and damaging influence.

This article shows that these fears are unfounded once the meaning and functions of legal personality are properly understood. It is important to recognize that from the legal point of view ‘person’ is not co-extensive with ‘human being’. Nor is it synonymous with ‘rational being’ or ‘responsible subject’. Much of the confusion surrounding the issue of the firm's legal personality is due to the tendency to address the matter with only these, frequently conflated, definitions of personhood in mind.

On the contrary, when the term ‘person’ is defined in line with its original meaning as ‘mask’ worn in the legal drama, it is easy to see that it is only the capacity to attract legal relations that defines the legal person. This definition severs the misleading link between the flesh-and-blood human being and the legal person, and opens the gates of the legal realm to firms and other candidates that would otherwise be excluded. Importantly, this definition avoids the undesirable emotional associations and equivocations that have all too often plagued the debate.

The rest of this paper is organized as follows. Section 2 presents Jensen and Meckling's treatment of legal personality and their associated discussion of misleading ‘personalization’. Section 3 compares the underlying conception of personhood with other definitions to the found in the history of legal theory and philosophy. Building on this discussion, three views of legal personality are discussed in Section 4 that shows that the least problematic of the three is derived from the original meaning of personhood. Section 5 draws some conclusions for a legally grounded view of the firm.

2. Misleading ‘personalization’

Jensen and Meckling's (Reference Jensen and Meckling1976: 311) definition of the firm as a ‘legal fiction which serves as a nexus for a set of contracting relationships among individuals’, where by ‘legal fiction’ is meant ‘the artificial construct under the law which allows certain organizations to be treated as individuals’ (Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1976: 310, n.12), is the only appearance of the concept of legal personality among the classics of the theory of the firm literature. Indeed, it is the only acknowledgement that law's assignment of legal personality is essential to the transaction-cost-minimizing nature of the firm.

Coasean theories of the firm are variations on the idea that the contractual centralization of transactions, where several input owners make bilateral contracts with a central agent, is an efficiency-enhancing institutional arrangement. Explicitly or implicitly, in most theories of the firm the central agent is assumed to be a flesh-and-blood human being (e.g., entrepreneur, employer, owner) or a group of such human beings (e.g., owners, management). For Jensen and Meckling, by contrast, the central agent is a legal entity with the legally endowed capacity to enter contractual relations with other parties.Footnote 3

However, this rare acknowledgement came with a warning. As they explained elsewhere, the fact that transaction costs are reduced when ‘individuals and organizations – employees, investors, suppliers, customers – contract with each other in the name of a fictional entity’ called ‘the firm’ (Meckling and Jensen, Reference Meckling and Jensen1983: 9) should not obscure the truth that, stripped to their essentials, firms and similar organizations are ‘pure conceptual artifacts, even when they are assigned the legal status of individuals’ (Meckling, Reference Meckling1976: 548).

On this view, one should always be careful about the legal treatment of firms as if they were individuals, and resist the tendency to think and talk about firms as if they were individuals. While ‘ascribing human characteristics to the [firm] is often a useful linguistic expedient’ that has ‘venerable roots in both law and economics’ (Meckling and Jensen, Reference Meckling and Jensen1983: 10), it is vital not to take what is at best a metaphorical ascription or a shorthand form of expression for something more. As Jensen and Meckling (Reference Meckling1976: 311, emphasis in original) famously put it:

The personalization of the firm implied by asking questions such as ‘what should be the objective function of the firm’, or ‘does the firm have a social responsibility’ is seriously misleading. The firm is not an individual.

The anthropomorphic practice of ‘personalization’ obscures the fact that firms cannot be said to ‘have objectives’ or ‘act’ in any particular way. Only individuals have purposes, act or can act. From this perspective, since pure conceptual artifacts are not the kinds of things that have what it takes to qualify as actors, claims to the contrary amount to seriously misleading category mistakes.Footnote 4 These considerations, according to Jensen and Meckling, have important implications for both economics and legal practice.

The implication for economic theory is that the textbook personalization of the firm as a profit-maximizing entity must give way to a more realistic view of the ‘behavior’ of the firm. Once attention is shifted away from the ‘black box’ of the textbook firm to the actions of individual participants, the behavior of the firm can be likened to that of the market, namely: ‘the outcome of a complex equilibrium process’ in which the ‘conflicting objectives of individuals … are brought into equilibrium within a framework of contractual relations’ (Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1976: 311).Footnote 5

More fundamentally, for Jensen and Meckling, given that firms do not qualify as actors law's assignment of contractual capabilities to the legal fiction serving as a nexus for these contractual relations should never be taken to imply that firms can be referents of rights and duties. This would be the gravest type of personalization. Just as all rights are ‘human rights, i.e., rights which are possessed by individuals’ (Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1976: 306, n.6), all duties always ultimately belong to individuals. By the same token, costs and benefits can only be borne by ‘“real” as distinct from artificial beings’ (Meckling and Jensen, Reference Meckling and Jensen1983: 10).Footnote 6

Overall, Jensen and Meckling's treatment of legal personality is puzzling. The commendable acknowledgement that law's assignment of separate legal personality is essential to the transaction-cost-minimizing nature of the firm is largely overshadowed by the vigorous charges against personalization. They are clearly uncomfortable with the idea that the non-human central agent must be a rights-and-duties bearing entity if it is to play its efficiency-enhancing role. This implication is trivialized and downplayed in their ambiguous discussion that suggests a strong and virtually inevitable link between fictitious legal personality and misleading personalization.Footnote 7

Jensen and Meckling's definition of the firm as a legal fiction was not picked up in the theory of the firm literature, perhaps because it was perceived to be the reason for their controversial claim ‘it makes little or no sense to try to distinguish those things which are ‘inside’ the firm … from those things that are ‘outside’ of it’ (Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1976: 311). Given the literature's focus on the boundaries of the firm, their definition became a convenient foil, and the concept of legal personality disappeared from the theoretical narrative as furtively as it had appeared.

However, the rejection of personalization, that Klein and Coffee (Reference Klein and Coffee1988: 107) called the ‘reification illusion’, was picked up and amplified in the new literature on the economic analysis of corporate law (Butler, Reference Butler1989; Easterbrook and Fischel, Reference Easterbrook and Fischel1991; Fischel, Reference Fischel1982; Hessen, Reference Hessen1979; Klein, Reference Klein1982; Posner and Scott, Reference Posner and Scott1980). The invitation to debunk ‘metaphysical entities in law’ (Posner, Reference Posner1990: 186), including the concept of corporate personality, was typical of the process that Kornhauser (Reference Kornhauser1989: 1449) described as a ‘revolution [that] swept the legal theory of the corporation’.Footnote 8

In this literature, as Bratton (Reference Bratton1989: 409) observed, Jensen and Meckling's definition of the firm as a legal fiction that serves as a nexus for a set of contracting relations was ‘accorded … the weight of scientific truth’, and ‘received … as an ontological discovery’ with significant conceptual and practical implications. For years, as a result, anyone interested in both the theory of the firm and the topic of legal personality would have found little else on the subject in the field of law and economics.

3. The meanings of personhood

A long tradition in modern economics holds that the real actor, and hence the appropriate unit of analysis, is the rational individual agent (Brunner and Meckling, Reference Brunner and Meckling1977; Buchanan and Tullock, Reference Buchanan and Tullock1962; Furubotn and Richter, Reference Furubotn and Richter1998; Hayek, Reference Hayek1955; Jensen and Meckling, Reference Jensen and Meckling1994; Pejovich, Reference Pejovich1990; Werin, Reference Werin2003). As real beings, individuals are legal persons by virtue of their ‘natural’ capacity to attract rights and duties. Any extension of this capacity to non-humans, including both groups of individuals and inanimate things, is an artificial distortion of reality that bears the ‘unnatural’ flavor of anthropomorphism.

The notion of personhood underlying this position can be usefully compared with other definitions to be found in the long history of the legal and philosophical debate. Since persons are basic categories of what Smith (Reference Smith2004: 8ff) called law's ‘ontological inventories’, decisions concerning who or what counts as a ‘person’ from the legal point of view have profound implications. Just as the chemist will refer to the periodic table and see the world as ultimately divisible into basic natural kinds, by analogy the legal mind will refer to ‘the persons that populate the legal world’ (Vining, Reference Vining1978: 143).

As a result, MacCormick (Reference MacCormick2007: 77) argued, it is difficult to gain ‘an understanding of law and how it works’ without some ‘reflection on the idea of a person’. The distinction between ‘persons’ and ‘things’, or ‘subjects’ and ‘objects’, is indeed fundamental to the construction of law's periodic table. Since the earliest written codes of law in recorded history these legal categories have been indispensable building blocks of every system of law and political economy (Davies and Naffine, Reference Davies and Naffine2001; Iwai, Reference Iwai1999; Radin, Reference Radin1982; Trahan, Reference Trahan2008).Footnote 9 Importantly for the Western legal tradition, they were central to Roman law.

The term ‘person’ derives from the Latin persona meaning ‘actor's mask’. This is why the Roman lawyer found it suitable to denote the subject of civil rights and duties (Derham, Reference Derham and Webb1958; Duff, Reference Duff1938; Fuller, Reference Fuller1967; Hollis, Reference Hollis, Carrithers, Collins and Lukes1985; Poole, Reference Poole1996; Stoljar, Reference Stoljar1973). A person, as Hallis (Reference Hallis1930: xix) explained, ‘was one who could be a party in a legal dispute, one who could, so to speak, act in a legal drama’. Accordingly, legal persons were the actors that courts gave legal standing to as dramatis personae. Closely related to the notion of persona was the concept of capacitas that referred to ‘a status conferred upon citizens for the purpose of enabling them to participate in the economic life of the polity’ (Deakin, Reference Deakin2006: 318).

Not all human beings, however, had legal standing or the capacity to engage in the economic life of the polity. In early Roman civil law, for instance, a slave was a res (Watson, Reference Watson1967), a thing that was owned rather than a persona, and therefore did not have the right to own property or initiate any legal actions. Although in later Roman law slaves acquired some limited rights, including the ability to have quasi-marital relationships (Johnston, Reference Johnston1999), it was clear that they were not persons in the then legally, socially and economically meaningful sense of possessing freedom, citizenship and family rights (Stein, Reference Stein1999).

This conception of personhood as legal identity based on social status is not confined to the distant past but is central to any discussion of legal personality (Pound, Reference Pound1959). Significantly, over the course of the 19th century, both the abolition of slavery (1833 in the British Empire and 1865 in the United States) and the abolition of coverture for married women (1880s in the United Kingdom and the United States) involved a process of acquisition of separate legal personality. Before their emancipation, these categories of human beings could not own property or be parties to contracts in their own right.Footnote 10

The original accent on the social face that each member of society wears in a legal or public forum, that List and Pettit (Reference List and Pettit2011: 171) call the ‘performative conception of personhood’, contrasts with the definition of the person as an ‘individual substance of a rational nature’ given in the 6th century by the theologian Boethius (cited in Marshall, Reference Marshall1950: 472).Footnote 11 In fact, as Groarke (Reference Groarke2010: 299) observed, ‘the most striking philosophical feature of the Boethian person is that the private and the public components of the person are separated from each other’.

A comparable position can be found in Locke's (Reference Locke and Nidditch1975 [1690]: 335–336) claim that ‘person stands for … a thinking, intelligent being’, and that ‘consciousness makes personal identity’ not only at any point in time but also over time.Footnote 12 Although Locke also argued that ‘person … is a forensic term appropriating actions and their merit’ that ‘belongs only to intelligent agents capable of a law’ (Locke, Reference Locke and Nidditch1975 [1690]: 346), he was less concerned with the legal practices of ascribing actions and their merit to specific individuals than with the conditions under which these practices would make sense at all (Poole, Reference Poole1996).

Distinguishing the ‘metaphysical notion’ of the person as a conscious, rational agent from the ‘moral notion’ of the person as an accountable agent possessing rights and responsibilities, Dennett (Reference Dennett and Rorty1976) proceeded to examine the conditions under which the two notions overlap. Clearly, he pointed out, there are ‘conditions that exempt human beings from personhood, or at least some very important elements of personhood’ (Dennett, Reference Dennett and Rorty1976: 175).

Infants, minors, the mentally disabled and those declared legally insane normally cannot be parties to contracts, make legally binding decisions by themselves or be held fully accountable for their actions (Cane, Reference Cane2002; Honoré, Reference Honoré1999). Of course, this is not to deny that even when their actions cannot be imputed to them for these valid reasons, all human beings are ‘persons’ not only in common parlance (Teichman, Reference Teichman1985) but also in the broad Kantian sense of ‘ends in themselves, i.e., as something that may not be used merely as means’ (Kant, Reference Kant and Wood2002 [1785]: 46).

4. From human beings and responsible subjects to points of imputation

This discussion reveals that there are three notions of personhood that need to be carefully considered in any examination of legal personality.Footnote 13 First, there is the ordinary language view that ‘person’ and ‘human being’ are interchangeable or co-extensive (Teichman, Reference Teichman1985). This belief is consistent with the broad Kantian sense, and is axiomatic in discussions of ‘human rights’ in which the fact that human beings are the ‘natural’ subjects of rights from birth onwards by the mere fact of being born human, irrespective of considerations regarding their mental or physical state, is normally taken for granted (Ohlin, Reference Ohlin2005).Footnote 14

For proponents of this approach, whose periodic table contains all human beings (and possibly the unborn), the quality of personhood is not attributed by law to human beings (Beitz, Reference Beitz2009). On the contrary, as natural law theorists have long argued, positive law is subordinated to the law founded in human nature (Del Vecchio, Reference Del Vecchio1920). Human beings, from this perspective, always have ontological, explanatory and moral priority (Finnis, Reference Finnis and Horder2000).

As if to illustrate the long-standing dispute between natural law and legal positivism, most if not all jurisdictions clearly distinguish between the human being and the ‘responsible subject’ (Naffine, Reference Naffine2004: 628). The actions of a person thus defined are guided by reason, and this implies, by virtue of what Frankfurt (Reference Frankfurt1969: 829) called ‘the principle of alternate possibilities’, both moral and legal responsibility. The responsible subject is the ‘ideal legal actor’ (Naffine, Reference Naffine2009: 67) or the ‘default legal person’ (Blumenthal, Reference Blumenthal2007: 1138).

In fact, many actual legal rules concerning property, contract, standing, accountability, and so on, rely on this second view of the person, even though this more restrictive definition allows only a subset of human beings – those of a certain age and in sufficient possession of their faculties – to be fully admitted into the legal realm.Footnote 15 When personhood is equated with the responsible subject law's periodic table shrinks.

Much of the confusion surrounding the issue of the firm's legal personality is due to the tendency to address the matter with only these two, all too often conflated, definitions of personhood in mind. When the term ‘person’ is defined as either ‘human being’ or ‘responsible subject’, it is clear that the personality attributed by law to anything else is at best a fiction. This is essentially Jensen and Meckling's position. However, this inclination to frame the debate exclusively in terms of ‘human-size persons’ (Rovane, Reference Rovane1998: 136) has obscured the fact that there is a third and more useful possibility.

When the term ‘person’ is defined in line with its original meaning as ‘mask’ worn in the legal drama, it is easy to see that ‘it is [only] the legally endowed capacity to attract legal relations, and hence bear rights and duties, which defines the person’ (Naffine, Reference Naffine2003: 366). From this perspective, legal persons are law's essential ‘points of reference’ (Kocourek, Reference Kocourek1927: 57) or ‘points of imputation’ (Kelsen, Reference Kelsen and Wedberg1945: 99) for rights and duties that arise in legal relations.

A distinctive characteristic of this definition is that it severs the links between the flesh-and-blood human being and the legal person. With the additional separation between the legal person and the ideal responsible subject, the concept of legal personality becomes ‘wholly formal’ (Tur, Reference Tur, Peacocke and Gillett1987: 121). As a result, legal persons may be ‘of as many kinds as the law pleases’ (Salmond, Reference Salmond1902: 344). This conception of the legal person expands law's periodic table by opening the gates of the legal realm to candidates that would otherwise be excluded.

Alongside firms of various types, this includes foundations, municipalities, states, regional organizations, and international organizations (Aufricht, Reference Aufricht1943; Frug, Reference Frug1980; Paasivirta, Reference Paasivirta1997; Tiunov, Reference Tiunov1993; Wolff, Reference Wolff1938), as well as less obvious things such as idols, temples and ships (Collier, Reference Collier1992; Duff, Reference Duff1927; McDougal et al., Reference McDougal, Burke and Vlasic1960). Further extensions to trees, animals, species, artificial intelligences, computers and electronic agents have been proposed (Allen and Waddison, Reference Allen and Waddison1996; Solum, Reference Solum1992; Stone, Reference Stone1972; Teubner, Reference Teubner2006; Varner, Reference Varner1987; Wise, Reference Wise2001).

On this view, that helps ‘describe with simplicity and accuracy all the relevant phenomena of the legal system’ (Nékám, Reference Nékám1938: 70), there is no essential difference between the legal personality attributed under certain conditions to human beings and the legal personality attributed under different conditions to groups of human beings or organizations such as firms.Footnote 16 As Deakin (Reference Deakin, Clarke and Branson2012: 115–116) explained, ‘it is no more a ‘fiction’ to assign legal personality to organizational structures than it is to grant it to natural persons’. In both cases, the capacity to attract rights and duties is not ‘natural’ if this term is taken to mean ‘pre-legal’. The assignment of the capacity to hold rights and duties is one of the constitutive roles of law.Footnote 17

Like the legal realm itself, legal personality is always ‘artificial’, but this does not mean that it is ‘fictitious’ (Dewey, Reference Dewey1926; Fuller, Reference Fuller1967; Machen, Reference Machen1911). Accordingly, as Koessler (Reference Koessler1949: 449) put it, speculations about the reality or unreality of legal personality assigned by law to the firm ‘have no more sense than speculations about the reality or unreality of the conception of property or of other established institutions of a legal nature’.

Adopting this view does not imply that the attribution of legal personality to any inanimate thing, living creature or association of human beings is wholly unproblematic, as is clear from the unresolved dispute concerning animal rights (Kurki, unpublished; Sunstein and Nussbaum, Reference Sunstein and Nussbaum2004) or the currently intense American debate regarding the constitutional rights of business corporations (Adelstein, Reference Adelstein2014; Ripken, Reference Ripken2011). But by creating the conditions in which a discussion of these issues is possible without the equivocations that often plague the debate, many misunderstandings can surely be avoided. It is important to understand, as Dewey (Reference Dewey1926: 656) explained, that

what ‘person’ signifies in popular speech, or in psychology, or in philosophy or morals, [is] as irrelevant, to employ an exaggerated simile, as it would be to argue that because a wine is called ‘dry’, it has the properties of dry solids; or that, because it does not have those properties, wine cannot possibly be ‘dry’. Obviously, ‘dry’ as applied to a particular wine has the kind of meaning, and only the kind of meaning, which it has when applied to the class of beverages in general. Why should not the same sort of thing hold of the use of ‘person’ in law?

The fear of falling prey to the reification illusion or committing a fatal category mistake disappears when the term ‘person’ is purged from its meanings derived from ordinary language or psychology or morals. Under these conditions, a discussion of the functional role and economic value of law's assignment of legal personality becomes possible.

5. Concluding comments

When the law treats the firm as a ‘person’, nothing more than the fact that the firm has (not is) a point of imputation for rights and duties that arise in legal relations should be implied. The point of imputation is the legal entity in which ownership rights over assets used in production are vested, in whose name contracts are made, and thanks to which the firm has standing in court. The constitutive legal procedure that creates this efficiency-enhancing central contractual agent, entirely distinct from all of the human beings involved, is truly what Spulber (Reference Spulber2009: 152) described as a ‘foundational shift’.

The assignment of legal entity status transforms what is fundamentally a specialized economic undertaking into something that can act as a unit in the legal scheme, and it is this unified capacity for property, contract and litigation that carries the organizational framework of the firm (Deakin, unpublished; Schanze, Reference Schanze2006) In modern market economies, this holds for all observed types of firm (entrepreneurial or managerial, capitalist or cooperative, non-human asset-intensive or human asset-intensive). Debates about what drives the distribution of types do not alter this institutional fact.

For all types of firms, the value of operating as a legal entity lies in the separation that it introduces between the assets locked-in to guarantee the firm's contractual commitments, and the human beings involved (Blair, Reference Blair and Grandori2012; Deakin et al., forthcoming; Hansmann and Kraakman, Reference Hansmann and Kraakman2000; Rock, Reference Rock2006).Footnote 18 As compared to bilateral exchange, the firm's enhanced transactional capabilities stem from the fact that its commitments can indefinitely survive changes in its membership. Armed with this credible commitment the firm's founders can pledge assets, raise finance and do business in the firm's own name, such that some even thrive.

It is important to recognize that without the device of legal personality firms would be unable to own assets, contract with one another, merge, and act in other market-like ways. Most of the firm's activities would accordingly be difficult to sustain, if possible at all. The inclusion of legal personality in the theory of the firm narrative is therefore unavoidable (Gindis and Hodgson, unpublished), and further developments of the legally grounded view of the firm, that Orts (Reference Orts2013) calls the ‘institutional theory of the firm’, are warranted.

Contrary to the widespread view among economists that legal concepts of the firm are not only trivial but also likely to misdirect attention away from the economic forces at work, this article has shown than the advancement of our understanding of firms and markets requires significantly greater engagement with fundamental legal concepts. It is precisely the lack of such an engagement that explains the lasting influence of Jensen and Meckling's ambiguous discussion of personalization. The clarification of the legal concept of personhood proposed in this article is necessary if the tendency to downplay or ignore the role of law in constituting the firm is to be reversed.

Footnotes

1 The expressions ‘legal person’ and ‘legal entity’ are used synonymously in this paper, as are the expressions ‘legal personality’ and ‘legal entity status’. The expressions ‘registration’ and ‘incorporation’ are used synonymously to designate the constitutive procedure by which the firm founders duly apply for and obtain the official recognition of the firm's existence by the legal system.

2 With the notable exception of Williamson's (Reference Williamson1991) legally grounded discussion of discrete structural alternatives.

3 Jensen and Meckling (Reference Meckling1976: 311, n.14) noted in this respect ‘the important role [played by] the legal system and the law in … the organization of economic activity’.

4 A category mistake can involve presenting a thing as being of a certain kind when in actual fact it belongs to another kind, or attributing a property to something that the thing it is attributed to logically cannot have.

5 They acknowledged, however, that treating the firm ‘as if it were a wealth-maximizing individual’ remained useful for competitive price theory and the overall explanation of the functioning of the market system (Meckling and Jensen, Reference Meckling and Jensen1983: 10).

6 Likewise, wrote Meckling and Jensen (Reference Meckling and Jensen1983: 10), contrary to proponents of corporate social responsibility firms ‘can no more be responsible than can a lump of coal’.

7 See Ireland (unpublished) on the ‘schizophrenia’ involved in simultaneously relying on but dismissing separate legal personality.

8 The expression ‘corporate personality’ normally refers to the legal personality of corporate bodies such as associations, clubs, charities, business firms, trade unions, cooperatives or municipalities, and is often (misleadingly) called ‘artificial personality’ to mark the difference with the ‘natural personality’ of human beings.

9 As Blackstone (Reference Blackstone1766: 16, emphasis in original) wrote, the fact that ‘the objects of dominion or property are things, as contradistinguished from persons’, cannot be disputed, and the classical aphorism attributed to Gaius, that law pertains to persons, things, and actions, remains central today.

10 The legal personality of foreigners also had to be progressively defined in each jurisdiction (Mark, Reference Mark, Smelser and Baltes2001).

11 This definition was endorsed by Aquinas in the 13th century, giving it ‘almost authoritative standing’ (List and Pettit, Reference List and Pettit2011: 171), precisely at the time of Innocent IV's famous definition of the corporation as a persona ficta. Innocent, in other words, was denying that the corporation could be a Boethian person.

12 Like the Boethian person, Locke's person is an autonomous and private being, confined within a ‘first-person world’ (Davis, Reference Davis2003: 6).

13 See Naffine's (Reference Naffine2003) useful discussion of these three types.

14 The principle that ‘everyone has the right to recognition everywhere as a person before the law’, enshrined in Article 6 of the United Nations’ Universal Declaration of Human Rights, is intended to ensure that every human being is treated as a subject rather than an object of law in every jurisdiction.

15 Human beings are not born with complete legal personality but gain it by degrees as they grow up ‘by acquiring rights, powers, and duties, which gather cumulatively’ (Tur, Reference Tur, Peacocke and Gillett1987: 123).

16 Who or what is regarded as a legal person, and the number and quality of the rights and duties thus recognized, will depend on the changing social and political evaluation of the given community.

17 See Gindis (Reference Gindis2009), Lawson (2015) and Deakin et al. (forthcoming) for a more detailed discussion of law's constitutive role.

18 The degree of separation will depend on the type of legal entity.

References

Adelstein, R. P. (2014), ‘Firms as Persons’, Cahiers d’économie politique, 65: 163184.Google Scholar
Allen, T. and Waddison, R. (1996), ‘Can Computers Make Contracts?Harvard Journal of Law and Technology, 6 (1): 2552.Google Scholar
Aufricht, H. (1943), ‘Personality in International Law’, American Political Science Review, 37 (2): 217243.Google Scholar
Beitz, C. R. (2009), The Idea of Human Rights, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Blackstone, W. (1766), Commentaries on the Laws of England, Vol. 2, Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Blair, M. M. (2003), ‘Locking-In Capital: What Corporate Law Achieved for Business Organizers in the Nineteenth Century’, UCLA Law Review, 51 (2): 387455.Google Scholar
Blair, M. M. (2004), ‘The Neglected Benefits of the Corporate Form: Entity Status and the Separation of Asset Ownership from Control’, in Grandori, A. (ed.), Corporate Governance and Firm Organization: Microfoundations and Structural Forms, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Blair, M. M. (2012), ‘The Four Functions of Corporate Personhood’, in Grandori, A. (ed.), Handbook of Economic Organization, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.Google Scholar
Blumenthal, S. L. (2007), ‘The Default Legal Person’, UCLA Law Review, 54 (5): 11351265.Google Scholar
Bratton, W. W. (1989), ‘The “Nexus-of-Contracts” Corporation: A Critical Appraisal’, Cornell Law Review, 74 (2): 407465.Google Scholar
Brunner, K. and Meckling, W. H. (1977), ‘The Perception of Man and the Conception of Government’, Journal of Money, Credit and Banking, 9 (1): 7085.Google Scholar
Buchanan, J. M. and Tullock, G. (1962), The Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Butler, H. N. (1989), ‘The Contractual Theory of the Corporation’, George Mason University Law Review, 11 (4): 99123.Google Scholar
Cane, P. (2002), Responsibility in Law and Morality, Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Collier, J. G. (1992), ‘Of Temples and Phalluses and Suchlike Things’, Cambridge Law Journal, 51 (1): 3941.Google Scholar
Davies, M. and Naffine, N. (2001), Are Persons Property? Legal Debates about Property and Personality, Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Davis, J. B. (2003), The Theory of the Individual in Economics: Identity and Value, London and New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Deakin, S. (2006), ‘ Capacitas: Contract Law and the Institutional Foundations of a Market Economy’, European Review of Contract Law, 2 (3): 317341.Google Scholar
Deakin, S. (2012), ‘The Juridical Nature of the Firm’, in Clarke, T. and Branson, D. (eds.), The SAGE Handbook of Corporate Governance, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Google Scholar
Deakin, S. (unpublished), ‘The Evolution of the Company: From Shareholders’ Property to the Corporation as Commons, unpublished.Google Scholar
Deakin, S., Gindis, D., Hodgson, G. M., Huang, K. and Pistor, K. (forthcoming), ‘Legal Institutionalism: Capitalism and the Constitutive Role of Law’, Journal of Comparative Economics, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Del Vecchio, G. (1920), ‘Rights and Human Personality in the History of Thought’, International Journal of Ethics, 30 (2): 121141.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1976), ‘Conditions of Personhood’, in Rorty, A. O. (ed.), The Identities of Persons, Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Derham, D. P. (1958), ‘Theories of Legal Personality’, in Webb, L. C. (ed.), Legal Personality and Political Pluralism, Carlton: Melbourne University Press.Google Scholar
Dewey, J. (1926), ‘The Historic Background of Corporate Legal Personality’, Yale Law Journal, 35 (6): 655673.Google Scholar
Duff, P. W. (1927), ‘The Personality of an Idol’, Cambridge Law Journal, 3 (1): 4248.Google Scholar
Duff, P. W. (1938), Personality in Roman Private Law, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Easterbrook, F. H. and Fischel, D. R. (1991), The Economic Structure of Corporate Law, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Finnis, J. (2000), ‘The Priority of Persons’, in Horder, J. (ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fischel, D. R. (1982), ‘The Corporate Governance Movement’, Vanderbilt Law Review, 35 (6): 12591292.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. G. (1969), ‘Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility’, Journal of Philosophy, 66 (4): 829839.Google Scholar
Frug, G. E. (1980), ‘The City as a Legal Concept’, Harvard Law Review, 93 (6): 10571154.Google Scholar
Fuller, L. L. (1967), Legal Fictions, Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Furubotn, E. G. and Richter, R. (1998), Institutions and Economic Theory: The Contribution of the New Institutional Economics, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Gindis, D. (2009), ‘From Fictions and Aggregates to Real Entities in the Theory of the Firm’, Journal of Institutional Economics, 5 (1): 25–46.Google Scholar
Gindis, D. and Hodgson, G. M. (unpublished), ‘Missing Persons in the Theory of the Firm: Why Legal Personality Matters’, unpublished.Google Scholar
Groarke, P. (2010), ‘The Legal Concept of the Person: A Relational Account’, Heythrop Journal, 51 (2): 298313.Google Scholar
Hallis, F. (1930), Corporate Personality: A Study in Jurisprudence, London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hansmann, H. (2013), ‘Ownership and Organizational Form’, in Gibbons, R. and Roberts, J. (eds.), Handbook of Organizational Economics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hansmann, H. and Kraakman, R. R. (2000), ‘The Essential Role of Organizational Law’, Yale Law Journal, 110 (3): 387440.Google Scholar
Hayek, F. A. (1955), The Counter-Revolution of Science: Studies on the Abuse of Reason, Glencoe, IL: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hessen, R. (1979), ‘A New Concept of Corporations: A Contractual and Private Property Model’, Hastings Law Journal, 30 (5): 13271350.Google Scholar
Hodgson, G. M. (2002), ‘The Legal Nature of the Firm and the Myth of the Firm-Market Hybrid’, International Journal of the Economics of Business, 9 (1): 3660.Google Scholar
Hollis, M. (1985), ‘Of Masks and Men’, in Carrithers, M., Collins, S. and Lukes, S. (eds.), The Category of the Person: Anthropology, Philosophy, History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Honoré, A. M. (1999), Responsibility and Fault, Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Iacobucci, E. M. and Triantis, G. G. (2007), ‘Economic and Legal Boundaries of the Firm’, Virginia Law Review, 93 (3): 515570.Google Scholar
Ireland, P. (unpublished), ‘Corporate Schizophrenia: The Corporation as a Separate Legal Person and an Object of Property’, unpublished.Google Scholar
Iwai, K. (1999), ‘Persons, Things and Corporations: The Corporate Personality Controversy and Comparative Corporate Governance’, American Journal of Corporation Law, 47 (4): 583632.Google Scholar
Jensen, M. C. and Meckling, W. H. (1976), ‘Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Capital Structure’, Journal of Financial Economics, 3 (4): 305360.Google Scholar
Jensen, M. C. and Meckling, W. H. (1994), ‘The Nature of Man’, Journal of Applied Corporate Finance, 7 (2): 419.Google Scholar
Johnston, D. (1999), Roman Law in Context, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2002 [1785]), Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, edited and translated by Wood, A. W., Hew Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Kelsen, H. (1945), General Theory of Law and State, translated by Wedberg, A., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Klein, W. A. (1982), ‘The Modern Business Organization: Bargaining under Constraints’, Yale Law Journal, 91 (8): 15211564.Google Scholar
Klein, W. A. and Coffee, J. C. (1988), Business Organization and Finance: Legal and Economic Principles, 3rd ed., New York: Foundation Press.Google Scholar
Kocourek, A. (1927), Jural Relations, Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill Co. Google Scholar
Koessler, M. (1949), ‘The Person in Imagination or Persona Ficta of the Corporation’, Louisiana Law Review, 9 (3): 435449.Google Scholar
Kornhauser, L. A. (1989), ‘The Nexus of Contracts Approach to Corporations: A Comment on Easterbrook and Fischel’, Columbia Law Review, 89 (7): 14491460.Google Scholar
Kornhauser, L. A. and MacLeod, B. (2013), ‘Contracts between Legal Persons’, in Gibbons, R. and Roberts, J. (eds.), Handbook of Organizational Economics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kurki, V. J. (unpublished), ‘Why Things Can Hold Rights: Reconceptualizing the Legal Person’, unpublished.Google Scholar
Lawson, T. (2015), ‘The Nature of the Firm and Peculiarities of the Corporation’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 39 (1): 132.Google Scholar
List, C. and Pettit, P. (2011), Group Agency: The Possibility, Design and Status of Corporate Actors, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Locke, J. (1975 [1690]), An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, edited with an introduction by Nidditch, P. H., Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
MacCormick, N. D. (2007), Institutions of Law: An Essay in Legal Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Machen, A. W. (1911), ‘Corporate Personality’, Harvard Law Review, 24 (4): 253267.Google Scholar
Mark, G. A. (2001), ‘Legal Personality’, in Smelser, N. J. and Baltes, P. B. (eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 13, Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Marshall, M. H. (1950), ‘Boethius’ Definition of Persona and Mediaeval Understanding of the Roman Theater’, Speculum, 25 (4): 471482.Google Scholar
Masten, S. E. (1988), ‘A Legal Basis for the Firm’, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 4 (1): 181198.Google Scholar
McDougal, M. S., Burke, W. T. and Vlasic, I. A. (1960), ‘The Maintenance of Public Order at Sea and the Nationality of Ships’, American Journal of International Law, 54 (1): 25116.Google Scholar
Meckling, W. H. (1976), ‘Values and the Choice of the Model of the Individual in the Social Sciences’, Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Volkswirtschaft und Statistik, 112 (4): 545–560. Google Scholar
Meckling, W. H. and Jensen, M. C. (1983), ‘Reflections on the Corporation as a Social Invention’, Midland Corporate Finance Journal, 1 (3): 615.Google Scholar
Naffine, N. (2003), ‘Who are Law's Persons? From Cheshire Cats to Responsible Subjects’, Modern Law Review, 66 (3): 346367.Google Scholar
Naffine, N. (2004), ‘Our Legal Lives as Men, Women and Persons’, Legal Studies, 24 (4): 621642.Google Scholar
Naffine, N. (2009), Law's Meaning of Life: Philosophy, Religion, Darwin and the Legal Person, Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
Nékám, A. (1938), The Personality Conception of the Legal Entity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Ohlin, J. D. (2005), ‘Is the Concept of the Person Necessary for Human Rights?Columbia Law Review, 105 (1): 209249.Google Scholar
Orts, E. W. (2013), Business Persons: A Legal Theory of the Firm, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Paasivirta, E. (1997), ‘The European Union: From an Aggregate of States to a Legal Person’, Hofstra Law and Policy Symposium, 2: 3759.Google Scholar
Pejovich, S. (1990), The Economics of Property Rights: Towards a Theory of Comparative Systems, Boston: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Poole, R. (1996), ‘On Being a Person’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74 (1): 3856.Google Scholar
Posner, R. A. (1990), The Problems of Jurisprudence, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Posner, R. A. and Scott, K. E. (eds.) (1980), Economics of Corporation Law and Securities Regulation, Boston, MA: Little, Brown & Co. Google Scholar
Pound, R. (1959), Jurisprudence, Vol. 4, St. Paul, MN: West Publishing.Google Scholar
Radin, M. J. (1982), ‘Property and Personhood’, Stanford Law Review, 34 (5): 9571015.Google Scholar
Ripken, S. K. (2011), ‘Corporate First Amendment Rights After Citizens United: An Analysis of the Popular Movement to End the Constitutional Personhood of Corporations’, University of Pennsylvania Journal of Business Law, 14 (1): 209259.Google Scholar
Robé, J.-P. (2011), ‘The Legal Structure of the Firm’, Accounting, Economics and Law, 1 (1): Article 5.Google Scholar
Rock, E. B. (2006), ‘The Corporate Form as a Solution to a Discursive Dilemma’, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 162 (1): 5771.Google Scholar
Rovane, C. (1998), The Bounds of Agency: An Essay in Revisionary Metaphysics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Salmond, J. W. (1902), Jurisprudence, London: Stevens & Haynes.Google Scholar
Schanze, E. (2006), ‘The Advantage of the Corporate Form: Premise-Based Decision-Making in Teams and its Relations to Specialization, Professionalization and Delegated Responsibility’, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 162 (1): 7275.Google Scholar
Smith, S. D. (2004), Law's Quandary, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Solum, L. B. (1992), ‘Legal Personhood for Artificial Intelligences’, North Carolina Law Review, 70 (4): 12311287.Google Scholar
Spulber, D. F. (2009), The Theory of the Firm: Microeconomics with Endogenous Entrepreneurs, Firms, Markets and Organizations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stein, P. G. (1999), Roman Law in European History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stoljar, S. J. (1973), Groups and Entities: An Inquiry into Corporate Theory, Canberra: Australian University Press.Google Scholar
Stone, C. D. (1972), ‘Should Trees Have Standing? – Toward Legal Rights for Natural Objects’, Southern California Law Review, 45 (2): 450501.Google Scholar
Sunstein, C. R. and Nussbaum, M. C. (eds.) (2004), Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Teichman, J. (1985), ‘The Definition of Person’, Philosophy, 60 (232): 175185.Google Scholar
Teubner, G. (2006), ‘Rights of Non-Humans? Electronic Agents and Animals as New Actors in Politics and Law’, Journal of Law and Society, 32 (4): 497521.Google Scholar
Tiunov, O. I. (1993), ‘The International Legal Personality of States: Problems and Solutions’, Saint Louis University Law Journal, 37 (2): 323336.Google Scholar
Trahan, J. R. (2008), ‘The Distinction between Persons and Things: An Historical Perspective’, Journal of Civil Law Studies, 1: 920.Google Scholar
Tur, R. (1987), ‘The “Person” in Law’, in Peacocke, A. R. and Gillett, G. (eds.), Persons and Personality: A Contemporary Enquiry, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Varner, G. E. (1987), ‘Do Species Have Standing?Environmental Ethics, 9 (1): 5772.Google Scholar
Vining, J. (1978), Legal Identity: The Coming of Age of Public Law, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, A. (1967), The Law of Persons in the Later Roman Republic, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Werin, L. (2003), Economic Behavior and Legal Institutions: An Introductory Text, Singapore: World Scientific Publishing.Google Scholar
Williamson, O. E. (1991), ‘Comparative Economic Organization: The Analysis of Discrete Structural Forms’, Administrative Science Quarterly, 36 (2): 269296.Google Scholar
Wise, S. M. (2001), ‘Dismantling the Barriers to Legal Rights for Nonhuman Animals’, Animal Law, 7: 918.Google Scholar
Wolff, M. (1938), ‘On the Nature of Legal Persons’, Law Quarterly Review, 54 (4): 494521.Google Scholar