Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-grxwn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-07T04:12:27.507Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Racisms: from the Crusades to the twentieth century By Francisco Bethencourt. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2013. Pp. xiv + 444. Hardback £31.95, ISBN 978-0-691-15526-5; paperback £22.95, ISBN 978-0-691-16975-0.

Review products

Racisms: from the Crusades to the twentieth century By Francisco Bethencourt. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2013. Pp. xiv + 444. Hardback £31.95, ISBN 978-0-691-15526-5; paperback £22.95, ISBN 978-0-691-16975-0.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 February 2017

Benjamin Isaac*
Affiliation:
Tel Aviv University, Israel E-mail: isaacb@post.tau.ac.il
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

This is a learned and lavishly produced work, written for a broad audience, about the historical origins of one of humankind’s most harmful and persistent ills. It offers a condensed and generally lucid survey of the many waves of discrimination, segregation, and persecution in world history, with a special emphasis on the West. This emphasis is from the late medieval period to our own times; Bethencourt does not really accept that there was racism in Antiquity and early Islam, and so these are covered briefly. The work proceeds in a sober manner, with a fine eye for significant details, variations, and results. Bethencourt’s own field is the Iberian world – Spain and Portugal from the Middle Ages onward, and the Portuguese and Spanish empires – but his judgement on other regions and periods is sound and balanced, based on up-to-date research. The footnotes contain massive learning. This book, therefore, is recommended reading for anyone interested in the subject.

It is in discussing the reconquest of Iberia and the crusades that the author comes into his own. All major areas of ethnic and religious conflict and interaction are discussed in chronological order, with a great deal of attention paid to European activities in Africa, the Americas, and Asia in Parts II and III of the work. The development of racist theory and ideology are treated in Part IV. Part V, on ‘The impact of nationalism’, is devoted to the twentieth century.

That said, the work is an attempt to review the essence of racism at a conceptual level. Regrettably, I find the attempt unconvincing. This is not so much because I disagree with it, but because it lacks precision and coherence. Bethencourt defines racism as ‘prejudice concerning ethnic descent coupled with discriminatory action’ (p. 1). This phrase means that every form of group prejudice focusing on descent is racism, which is untenable. It would mean, for instance, that the Old Testament is full of racism. Prejudice concerning ethnic descent is at least as old as the art of writing. A further definition, or rather description, by Bethencourt follows (pp. 7–8), which is not helpful because it is insufficiently precise and tries to cover too much.

The complementary element of action is a matter of debate. Bethencourt claims that ‘The issue remains that prejudice related to ethnic descent does not sufficiently identify racism; such prejudice must be coupled with discriminatory action’ (p. 8). This is questionable at several levels. Not all prejudice related to ethnic descent is racist by nature. The postulate that racism exists only when there is discriminatory action is untenable. It would justify the absurd conclusion that intellectuals who have formulated clearly racist ideas, such as Hume, Kant, and Hegel, were not racists because their ideas were not accompanied by acts. As regards the pre-medieval periods, Bethencourt ignores the fact that we are faced in these with slave-holding societies. Slavery, obviously, is a practical reality. The question is then whether largescale slavery was justified by arguments that approach racism. I myself have argued that this was the case in both Greece and Rome. Bethencourt refers to my book contending that racism goes back to Antiquity (p. 3). It is only fair to list various other authors who have argued along similar or related lines.Footnote 1

The essential hypothesis of this work is that ‘racism is triggered by political projects and connected to specific economic conditions’ (p. 6). Also, as stated in its conclusion, ‘In all the significant cases I have studied, prejudices concerning ethnic descent coupled with discriminatory actions have been motivated by political projects’ (p. 365). This conclusion fails to distinguish between racist conflict and other forms of conflict between groups – religious, social, economic, and even plain political. This is not to deny, of course, that racist conflict has been exploited, reinforced, and sharpened by political forces. Racism has been a welcome tool for the wrong sort of politicians and political movements, as we all know, but its ultimate origins are not those of political pamphlets or actions. Nor can it be maintained that specific economic conditions are a prerequisite for racism. Racism represents a perverse way of looking at society that infects intellectual and social life at many levels, politics being only one of them. It is a social pathology that finds its expression, among other things, in publications, in written and other forms. It justifies aggression, but remains racism even if there is no actual aggression.

The historical development of racist politics is described in the work as follows: ‘nationalism brought with it the fusion of nation with race, with collective identity based on the idea of a shared language and descent’ (p. 369). While this may be true in some historical situations, as a general pronouncement it is untenable. It would mean that, according to Bethencourt, Herodotus and Thucydides, who wrote in the fifth century BCE, were racists – in spirit, if not in fact, for he recognizes only published opinion combined with action, not published opinion alone as a genuine form of racism. These two authors state that being Greek represents a combination of language, descent, culture, and religion. That in itself does not justify a conclusion that they were racists.

As is appropriate in a work such as this, religious conflict, discrimination, and persecution play a huge role. ‘Islam speared the idea of holy war’, Bethencourt says; ‘The idea of holy war as a personal and collective duty was alien to the Christian tradition’ (p. 19). He therefore argues that the Crusades as an idea were inspired by Islam. That seems farfetched. There is plenty of evidence of religious warfare in Judaism and Christianity preceding the Crusades. Generally speaking, one of the numerous lessons to be learned from this impressive work is how difficult it is to evaluate the fluid margins of racism and other forms of group prejudice in religious conflict.

I conclude, therefore, that Bethencourt defines racism in a sense that is both too narrow and too broad – or vague – and consequently both excludes and includes historical episodes on the basis of mistaken criteria. While this is an impressive and learned work that has much to offer, at a conceptual level I maintain that he fails to prove his views. In the rich bibliography there is hardly any reference to authoritative modern works on racism.Footnote 2 Since Bethencourt himself also has eccentric and provocative ideas and theories, the reader should have been made aware of the varied and diverse current literature that exists. It is only fair to end this review by emphasizing once again that my essential disagreement about what racism was and is does not affect my admiration for the remarkable scholarship to be found on every page of this fascinating work.

References

1 Delacampagne, C., L’Invention du racisme. Antiquité et Moyen Age, Paris: Fayard, 1983 Google Scholar; Buell, D. K., Why this new race: ethnic reasoning in early Christianity, New York: Columbia University Press, 2004 Google Scholar; Goldenberg, D., The curse of Ham: race and slavery in early Judaism, Christianity and Islam, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004 Google Scholar; Eliav-Feldon, M., Isaac, B., and Ziegler, J., The origins of racism in the West, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009 Google Scholar, notably the papers by Goldenberg, D., Buell, D. K., Bartlett, R., Biller, P., de Miramon, C., Nirenberg, D., Po-Chia Hsia, R., and Pagden, A.; recently McCoskey, D. E., Race: Antiquity and its legacy, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012 Google Scholar.

2 A small selection of significant works that are not mentioned: L. Poliakov, The Aryan myth: a history of racist and nationalist ideas in Europe, trans. E. Howard, New York: Barnes & Noble, 1996 (translation of the French from 1971); Poliakov, L., Le Racisme, Paris: Seghers, 1976 Google Scholar; Banton, M., The idea of race, London: Tavistock Publications, 1977 Google Scholar; Memmi, Albert, Le Racisme. Description, définition, traitement, Paris: Gallimard, 1982 Google Scholar; Cavalli-Sforza, L. L., Menozzi, Paolo, and Piazza, Alberto, The history and geography of human genes, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994 Google Scholar; Bulmer, Martin and Solomos, John, eds., Racism, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999 Google Scholar; Bernasconi, R. and Lott, T. L., eds., The idea of race, Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub. Co., 2000 Google Scholar; Delacampagne, C., Une histoire du racisme. Des origines à nos jours, Paris: Librairie Générale Française, 2000 Google Scholar (trans. into German by Ursula Vones-Liebenstein as Die Geschichte des Rassismus, Düsseldorf: Artemis und Winkler, 2005; Brace, C. Loring, ‘Race’ is a four-letter word: the genesis of the concept, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005 Google Scholar.