Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-v2bm5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T10:00:40.589Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Perspective: psychiatric diagnosis is too important for its own good

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 May 2013

A. Frances*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry, Duke University, Durham, NC, USA
*
*Address for correspondence: A. Frances, PO Box 3950, Department of Psychiatry, Duke University, Durham, NC, USA. (Email allenfrances@vzw.blackberry.net)
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Perspective
Copyright
Copyright © College of Psychiatrists of Ireland 2013 

I began my training in psychiatry in 1967, when Diagnostic and Statistical Manual (DSM)-I was still the diagnostic system in use in the United States. The next year, DSM-II appeared and no one really much noticed or cared. DSM-I and DSM-II were remarkably boring little books that neither seemed to have little relevance to our understanding of patients nor any influence on decisions how best to treat them. The two predominant models in psychiatry were psychodynamic and social psychiatry and neither relied very much on diagnosing a patient's presenting symptoms (Andreasen, Reference Andreasen2007).

Then, in the early 1970s, psychiatry was rocked by an existential crisis that threatened its newly won and much prized place among the medical specialties. Two damaging and highly publicized studies zeroed in on its Achilles heel of diagnosis to challenge psychiatry's usefulness, integrity, and common sense.

Rosenhan (Reference Rosenhan1973) formulated the devilishly clever experiment of sending eight healthy volunteers, or ‘pseudopatients’, to the admission offices of psychiatric hospitals, where they feigned having heard voices. All were admitted, whereupon each ‘ceased simulating any symptoms of abnormality… the pseudopatient behaved on the ward as he “normally” behaved’ (Rosenhan, Reference Rosenhan1973, pp. 251–252). Nonetheless, all eight were kept in hospital, for between 7 and 52 days. Many other patients caught on to the fact that the pseudopatients were feigning illness, but the psychiatrists did not. This dismal result, reported in Science, triggered a controversy that called into question whether psychiatrists had common sense and could be trusted with even the most obvious diagnostic decisions (Spitzer, Reference Spitzer1975; Wilson, Reference Wilson1993).

Simultaneously, the US–UK Diagnostic Project raised the same question and also returned with a decidedly negative answer (Kendell etal. Reference Kendell, Cooper, Gourlay, Copeland, Sharpe and Gurland1971). Psychiatrists from Great Britain and the United States were shown the same videotape interviews of patients, but drew opposite conclusions from them, with the British diagnosing mood disorder, whereas the Americans saw schizophrenia. The Brits were right, but the point taken was that psychiatry spoke an unintelligible Babel of languages with, as the authors politely put it, ‘important implications for transatlantic communication, and indeed for international communication in general’ (Kendell etal. Reference Kendell, Cooper, Gourlay, Copeland, Sharpe and Gurland1971).

Luckily, psychiatry was saved at the 11th hour when a new and more systematic method of making diagnoses was devised. The absence of objective biological tests required some other means of reducing the idiosyncrasy and subjectivity of descriptive psychiatry. The answer was to provide very explicit criteria sets for defining the different mental disorders. These were first laid out in 1972 in the Feighner criteria (Feighner etal. Reference Feighner, Robins, Guze, Woodruff, Winokur and Munoz1972), then in the Research Diagnostic Criteria (Spitzer etal. Reference Spitzer, Endicott and Robins1978), and finally were exported to general clinical practice in DSM-III (American Psychiatric Association, 1980).

DSM-III was successful beyond anyone's wildest dream (Mayes and Horwitz, Reference Mayes and Horwitz2005) – in fact, far too successful for its own good and for the good of psychiatry, our patients, and society. The successive editions of the DSM have played a very constructive role when used with caution and modesty, but cause problems when reified or used beyond their competence. Intended as a simple guide to clinical practice, DSM-III was soon described and worshipped as the Bible of psychiatry (Angell, Reference Angell2011) and given more weight in many arenas than it could safely carry. We will briefly summarize its uses and harms in each of these arenas.

Clinical

DSM-III played an essential role as lingua franca in improving clinical communication and providing the needed foundation for treatment planning and guideline development (Frances and Egger, Reference Frances and Egger1999). But there were negative unintended consequences. In many centers, the complexity and individuality of human nature was reduced to a rote checklist psychiatry that noted only what was common to patients and ignored what made them different; moreover, criteria created by fallible experts were treated as hard and fast rules that required no exercise of clinical judgment.

Research

DSM-III had the profound beneficial effect of dragging psychiatry out of the research wilderness and making it a research darling, in most universities the second largest research enterprise after internal medicine. Unfortunately, though, the fascinating advances in basic neuroscience have failed to explicate the psychopathology as laid out in DSM-III and its successors. The DSM disorders are too heterogeneous and complex to allow for easy research elucidation (Gillihan and Parens, Reference Gillihan and Parens2011). In the United States, the National Institute of Mental Health in its Research Domain Categories project is now picking simpler targets, not DSM syndromes (NIMH, 2011). Some have even argued that too close an adherence to DSM has retarded research advances (Hyman, Reference Hyman2010).

Epidemiology

DSM criteria sets have been the necessary foundation for all population-based studies, but have been badly misused in reporting and understanding their results. Lay interviewers, who are necessary as cost savers in large surveys, cannot judge the clinical significance of the symptoms they elicit. Reports on community rates of various psychiatric disorder have a consistent and systematic toward overstating prevalences that is rarely addressed in discussing the results (Kessler etal. Reference Kessler, McGonagle, Zhao, Nelson, Hughes, Eshleman, Wittchen and Kendler1994, Reference Kessler, Chiu, Demler, Merikangas and Walters2005). This leads to wild swings in reported rates that are misinterpreted as being real changes rather than methodological blips.

Education

I was taught a rounded biopsychosocial model that DSM-III helped to destroy. Its descriptive criteria approach lends itself well only to the ‘bio-’ model; the ‘psycho-’ model is too inferential to allow for reliability and the ‘socio-’ model, dealing only with the interpersonal arena, is not reducible to collating symptoms in the individual. Training in many centers has become almost completely reductionistic and biological, focusing only on eliciting symptoms and prescribing medication, with little attention to individual and family psychotherapy (Sowers, Reference Sowers2005).

Drug companies

Successive editions of the DSM have become unwitting tools in Pharma's aggressive and well-financed campaign to sell pills to people who do not need them. The misleading marketing messages of ‘disease awareness campaigns’ are that psychiatric diagnosis is easy, that mental disorders are common and unrecognized, and that they are because of a chemical imbalance and always require a pill solution (Spence, Reference Spence2012). Drug companies have no direct influence on DSM decisions, but they are skillful and ruthless in exploiting them. Selling pills promotes diagnostic inflation and diagnostic inflation promotes selling pills in a vicious cycle (Batstra and Thoutenhoofd, Reference Batstra and Thoutenhoofd2012; Frances, Reference Frances2013).

Insurance

In the United States, reimbursement usually depends on the patient's first having received a DSM diagnosis (Hyman, Reference Hyman2010). This is a serious mistake that harms the individual and winds up costing more in the long run. Unnecessary and inaccurate diagnosis results when clinicians are forced to make judgments on the basis of insufficient information gathered in what are often brief interviews on what may be the worst day of the patient's life. It would be highly desirable, clinically and eventually much cheaper to allow a period of extended evaluation before a diagnosis is required for reimbursement. Most people with problems in everyday living that are now misdiagnosed as mental disorder will return to their equilibrium with watchful waiting, time, normalization, advice, support, and brief psychotherapy. They will do better without a premature diagnosis that too often leads to long-term and costly medication.

Forensic

DSM criteria are widely used and accepted in courtroom proceedings because they offer needed clarity on diagnostic questions that otherwise would be impossible to answer reliably. However, despite the cautions provided in the DSM, the manuals are often misunderstood and misused in the courts; psychiatric concepts do not always map well to legal ones and the DSM writing style is insufficiently precise for legal purposes (Slovenko, Reference Slovenko2011). The most egregious examples occur after mass murders and assassinations when psychiatrists line up on both sides of the diagnostic question – is the killer mad or bad? – canceling each other out (Applebaum, Reference Applebaum2013).

School systems

The raging epidemic of autism is partly fueled by its role as a gatekeeper to enhanced school services (Liu etal. Reference Liu, King and Bearman2010). This is bad for optimal allocation of school services and bad for accurate diagnosis of autism. Whenever a benefit is closely attached to the presence of a psychiatric disorder, that disorder will be diagnosed loosely and the benefit will not be applied optimally (Zimmerman etal. Reference Zimmerman, Galione, Ruggero, Chelminski, Dalrymple and Young2010). Educational services should be allocated on the basis of educational evaluations, and not on an unreliable clinical diagnosis not developed with an educational purpose in mind.

Disability

When unemployment rises, the rates of depression and disability increase (Gili etal. Reference Gili, Roca, Basu, McKee and Stuckler2013). Requiring a psychiatric diagnosis for disability often entrenches both the diagnosis and the disability, typically for life. It would be better and cheaper to provide more financial support and job training for everyone who has been displaced, rather than closely coupling benefits to mental disorder.

Conclusion

Getting a psychiatric diagnosis is often a life-changing event – for better or for worse. It deserves the care exercised in picking a spouse or buying a house; the commitment to it may last as long and have a profound impact. It is impossible to be a complete clinician without a good command of a criteria-based diagnostic system (either DSM or ICD). But being a complete clinician requires a great deal more than the rote application of DSM.

DSM can play a very useful role in clinical work, research, epidemiology, education, insurance and medication decisions, and in the allocation of school services and disability benefits. But it has become too dominantly determinant in too many societal decisions that are outside its proper competence. If administrative and financial decisions are to be made wisely, we need to reduce their close coupling with diagnosis and this will also increase the accuracy of diagnosis.

There is one other obvious conclusion. Psychiatric diagnosis has become far too important a societal issue to be left in the hands of the American Psychiatric Association. The experts working on any one part of DSM always strive prematurely to expand their pet area of interest. This has contributed to the past diagnostic inflation that DSM-V now threatens to turn into hyperinflation (Frances, Reference Frances2012).

In preparing DSM-IV, we aimed to be very conservative and to tame expert exuberance by having an extremely high threshold for change (Frances etal. Reference Frances, First and Pincus1995). To succeed, suggestions had to be supported by rigorously conducted literature reviews, data reanalyses, and field trials and also had to achieve unanimous approval from the Task Force. We rejected 92 proposals and accepted only two – Asperger's and bipolar II disorder – both of which led to unpredicted fads.

In contrast, DSM-V made a premature attempt to create a paradigm shift in psychiatric diagnosis (Kupfer etal. Reference Kupfer, First and Regier2002). Striving to do too much, it has introduced new disorders (Batstra and Thoutenhoofd, Reference Batstra and Thoutenhoofd2012) and reduced criteria for existing ones (Zisook etal. Reference Zisook, Corruble, Duan, Iglewicz, Karam, Lanouette, Lebowitz, Pies, Reynolds, Seay, Katherine Shear, Simon and Young2012) in a way that will further complicate psychiatric diagnosis and reduce its credibility (Dayle Jones, Reference Dayle Jones2012). The best approach for Irish psychiatry is to ignore simply DSM-V.

New diagnoses can be more dangerous than new drugs and need a careful vetting beyond the capacities of any one discipline or association (Frances, Reference Frances2012). A new structure for monitoring and revising psychiatric diagnosis needs to be developed. And we need to contain the excessive influence of psychiatric diagnosis on decisions outside its proper competence.

Forty years ago, we surmounted a crisis of confidence in psychiatric diagnosis by creating the DSM system of criteria-based definitions. Now, we face a new crisis of confidence that will be surmounted only if we ensure that DSM diagnoses are tamed and kept within their proper sphere.

Conflicts of Interest

Dr Frances has written two books critical on DSM-V, Saving Normal and Essentials of Psychiatric Diagnosis.

References

American Psychiatric Association (1980). Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 3rd edn. APA: Washington, DC.Google Scholar
Andreasen, NC (2007). DSM and the death of phenomenology in America: an example of unintended consequences. Schizophrenia Bulletin 33, 108112.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Angell, M (2011). The Illusions of Psychiatry. New York Rev Books, July 14 (http://www.nybooks.com/articles/archives/2011/jul/14/illusions-of-psychiatry). Accessed 23 April 2013.Google Scholar
Applebaum, PS (2013). Law & psychiatry: imposed insanity defenses and political crimes. Psychiatric Services 64, 46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Batstra, L, Thoutenhoofd, ED (2012). The risk that DSM-5 will further inflate the diagnostic bubble. Current Psychiatry Reviews 8, 260263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dayle Jones, K (2012). The risk that DSM 5 will reduce the credibility of psychiatric diagnosis. Current Psychiatry Reviews 8, 277280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feighner, JP, Robins, E, Guze, SB, Woodruff, RA, Winokur, G, Munoz, R (1972). Diagnostic criteria for use in psychiatric research. Archives of General Psychiatry 26, 5763.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Frances, A. (2012). Diagnosing the DSM. New York Times, May 11.Google Scholar
Frances, A. (2013). Where have all the normals gone? Huffington Post, March 30 (http://www.huffingtonpost.com/allen-frances/jon-ronson-ted-talk_b_2978686.html). Accessed 24 April 2013.Google Scholar
Frances, A, First, M, Pincus, H (1995). DSM-IV Guidebook. American Psychiatric Press: Washington, DC, p. 418.Google Scholar
Frances, AJ, Egger, HL (1999). Whither psychiatric diagnosis? Australian and New Zealand Journal of Psychiatry 33, 161165.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gili, M, Roca, M, Basu, S, McKee, M, Stuckler, D (2013). The mental health risks of economic crisis in Spain: evidence from primary care centres, 2006 and 2010. European Journal of Public Health 23, 103108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gillihan, SJ, Parens, E (2011). Should we expect ‘neural signatures’ for DSM diagnoses? Journal of Clinical Psychiatry 72, 13831389.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hyman, SE (2010). The diagnosis of mental disorders: the problem of reification. Annual Review of Clinical Psychology 6, 155179.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kendell, RE, Cooper, JE, Gourlay, AJ, Copeland, JR, Sharpe, L, Gurland, BJ (1971). Diagnostic criteria of American and British psychiatrists. Archives of General Psychiatry 25, 123130.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kessler, RC, Chiu, WT, Demler, O, Merikangas, KR, Walters, EE (2005). Prevalence, severity, and comorbidity of 12-month DSM-IV disorders in the National Comorbidity Survey Replication. Archives of General Psychiatry 62, 617627.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kessler, RC, McGonagle, KA, Zhao, S, Nelson, CB, Hughes, M, Eshleman, S, Wittchen, HU, Kendler, KS (1994). Lifetime and 12-month prevalence of DSM-III-R psychiatric disorders in the United States. Results from the National Comorbidity Survey. Archives of General Psychiatry 51, 819.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kupfer, D, First, M, Regier, D (editors) (2002). A Research Agenda for DSM-V. American Psychiatric Publishing: Washington.Google Scholar
Liu, KY, King, M, Bearman, PS (2010). Social influence and the autism epidemic. American Journal of Sociology 115, 13871434.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mayes, R, Horwitz, AV (2005). DSM-III and the revolution in the classification of mental illness. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 41, 249267.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
National Institutes of Mental Health (NIMH) (2011). NIMH Research Domain Criteria (RdoC). Draft 3.1 (http://www.nimh.nih.gov/research-funding/rdoc/nimh-research-domain-criteria-rdoc.shtml). Accessed 24 April 2013.Google Scholar
Rosenhan, DL (1973). On being sane in insane places. Science 179, 250258.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Slovenko, R (2011). The DSM in litigation and legislation. Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry Law 39, 611.Google ScholarPubMed
Sowers, W (2005). Reducing reductionism: reclaiming psychiatry. Psychiatric Services 56, 637.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spence, D (2012). The psychiatric oligarchs who medicalise normality. British Medical Journal 344, e3135.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Spitzer, RL (1975). On pseudoscience in science, logic in remission, and psychiatric diagnosis: a critique of Rosenhan's “On being sane in insane places”. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 84, 442452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spitzer, RL, Endicott, J, Robins, E (1978). Research diagnostic criteria: rationale and reliability. Archives of General Psychiatry 35, 773782.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, M (1993). DSM-III and the transformation of American psychiatry: a history. American Journal of Psychiatry 150, 399410.Google ScholarPubMed
Zimmerman, M, Galione, JN, Ruggero, CJ, Chelminski, I, Dalrymple, K, Young, D (2010). Overdiagnosis of bipolar disorder and disability payments. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 198, 452454.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Zisook, S, Corruble, E, Duan, N, Iglewicz, A, Karam, EG, Lanouette, N, Lebowitz, B, Pies, R, Reynolds, C, Seay, K, Katherine Shear, M, Simon, N, Young, IT (2012). The bereavement exclusion and DSM-5. Depress Anxiety 29, 425443.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed