Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-l4dxg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-07T08:46:43.832Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Enforcement and capacity building in international cooperation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2010

Johannes Urpelainen*
Affiliation:
Department of Political Science, Columbia University, 420 West 118th Street, 712 IAB, New York, NY 10027, USA
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

I examine enforcement and capacity building in international cooperation. In a game-theoretic model, a wealthy donor gives foreign aid in exchange for policy implementation by a poor recipient. The recipient has limited capacity to comply with international agreements, so the donor is not sure if cooperation failure is caused by willful disobedience or unintended error. I show that if perceived cooperation failure prompts reciprocal suspension of cooperation, the donor and recipient have a common preference for capacity building. But when the donor can request compensation for perceived cooperation failure, it only chooses to build capacity if cooperation is otherwise impossible. Consequently, the choice of enforcement mechanism shapes capacity building. This result lays a foundation for a genuine synthesis between the enforcement and managerialist schools of compliance. It generates falsifiable hypotheses and explains why reciprocal enforcement, which unfortunately inflicts collateral damage on the victim, is often considered legitimate.

Type
Original Papers
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2010

According to the enforcement school, a key problem in international cooperation is that states have incentives to violate international agreements (Keohane, Reference Keohane1984; Downs et al., Reference Downs, Rocke and Barsoon1996; Downs, Reference Downs1997, Reference Downs2000; Gilligan, Reference Gilligan2004; Carrubba, Reference Carrubba2005). Mutually profitable international cooperation requires the defectors and free riders be punished through sanctions or suspension of cooperation. But not all international cooperation theorists find enforcement so important. For managerialists, the complexity and ambiguity of international cooperation problems dominate enforcement concerns (Mitchell, Reference Mitchell1994; Chayes and Chayes, Reference Chayes and Chayes1995; Young, Reference Young1999; Tallberg, Reference Tallberg2002). In addition to transparency and rule interpretation, they emphasize capacity building as the key to successful international cooperation.

This study examines the relationship between enforcement and capacity building in international cooperation. In a game-theoretic model, a wealthy donor offers foreign aid to a poor recipient in exchange for policies that eradicate international externalities, such as environmental deterioration. I incorporate enforcement concerns by assuming that policy implementation is costly to recipient. Recipient has limited capacity to comply with international agreements, so compliance failure sometimes occurs despite genuine willingness to comply. A key problem is, therefore, that compliance failure could result either from inadequate capacity or willful disobedience, so the donor does not know if punishment is warranted. For example, Indonesia has consistently failed to reduce illegal logging despite promises made to donors of foreign aid, but it is unclear whether this failure should be mostly attributed to lacking political will or a genuine failure to address the rampant corruption that undermines environmental policies in the country.Footnote 1 This problem is so serious that deforestation makes Indonesia the third largest net emitter of greenhouse gas emissions, right after the United States and China.Footnote 2

I compare two canonical enforcement mechanisms. Under reversion, mutual suspension of international cooperation follows perceived compliance failure (Axelrod, Reference Axelrod1984; Axelrod and Keohane, Reference Axelrod and Keohane1985; Keohane, Reference Keohane1986; Conybeare, Reference Conybeare1987; Downs and Rocke, Reference Downs and Rocke1995; McGillivray and Smith, Reference McGillivray and Smith2000; Langlois and Langlois, Reference Langlois and Langlois2001). If the recipient appears to defect, both sides lose mutually profitable international cooperation for a period of time. Under compensation, a defector must compensate the other state to restart international cooperation (Barrett, Reference Barrett1999; Rosendorff and Milner, Reference Rosendorff and Milner2001; Carrubba, Reference Carrubba2005; Rosendorff, Reference Rosendorff2005; Svolik, Reference Svolik2006). If the recipient appears to defect, it must continue to cooperate whereas foreign aid is temporarily frozen. I focus on these stylized enforcement mechanisms because they capture an important feature of any international enforcement mechanism: does the enforcer prefer to implement the punishment or not? They are also variants of reciprocity, which according to Keohane (Reference Keohane1984: 214) ‘seems to be the most effective strategy for maintaining cooperation among egoists’.

The central theoretical result is that the choice of enforcement mechanism shapes donor incentives to fund capacity building. Under reversion, mutually profitable international cooperation is suspended every time the recipient appears not to comply. Thus, the donor has an incentive to build capacity so as to reduce the rate of spurious compliance failure. Under compensation, foreign aid is frozen if the recipient appears not to comply. Now the donor has an incentive not to build capacity because it can thus hold the recipient accountable for perceived compliance failure more frequently. Reversion unambiguously aligns preferences for capacity building, while compensation reduces the donor incentive to fund capacity building unless international cooperation is otherwise impossible. Strikingly, this result holds even if capacity building is costless.

The result is important for several reasons. Firstly, it contributes to the research program on international compliance (Chayes and Chayes, Reference Chayes and Chayes1995; Downs et al., Reference Downs, Rocke and Barsoon1996; Tallberg, Reference Tallberg2002). Although previous scholarship has posited enforcement and capacity building as competing accounts of compliance, this result shows that they interact in complex ways. Indeed, the result could explain why powerful states accept reversionary enforcement mechanisms despite potentially costly consequences. These mechanisms allow a credible commitment to capacity building, so the value of international cooperation to weak states increases, so that powerful states can build a legitimate and mutually profitable international order and avoid the high cost of coercion (Ikenberry, Reference Ikenberry2000; Stone, Reference Stone2008). Secondly, it improves our understanding of international institutional design, especially as it depends on the relationship between distributional conflict and enforcement concerns (Abbott and Snidal, Reference Abbott and Snidal1998; Fearon, Reference Fearon1998; Koremenos et al., Reference Koremenos, Lipson and Snidal2001). If the choice of an enforcement mechanism influences willingness to build capacity, then these decisions are interdependent.

Thirdly, it can help us to understand the politics of legitimacy in international relations (Hurd, Reference Hurd1999; Clark, Reference Clark2003; Reus-Smit, Reference Reus-Smit2003). At first sight, reversionary enforcement appears normatively troubling because it hurts the innocent victims of perceived wrongdoings. However, it could ultimately align state preferences over capacity building and thus contribute to deeper cooperation in the long run. Finally, the result has notable implications for the study of foreign aid (Alesina and Dollar, Reference Alesina and Dollar2000; Burnside and Dollar, Reference Burnside and Dollar2000; Easterly, Reference Easterly2002; Bueno de Mesquita and Smith, Reference Bueno de Mesquita and Smith2009). Many scholars have emphasized that giving fungible resources to a government invites corruption and rent seeking. By contrast, capacity building could be particularly conducive to long term development. Thus, reversionary enforcement could reduce the benefits of giving foreign aid by shifting the focus from capacity building to cash transfers.

I first discuss the relationship between enforcement and capacity building in light of the extant literature. I then introduce the model and conduct the analysis. In the concluding section, I discuss the central theoretical and empirical implications of the results.

Enforcement and capacity building

An important debate in international cooperation theory is that between the enforcement and managerial schools of compliance.Footnote 3 The enforcement school builds on ideas articulated by Downs et al. (Reference Downs, Rocke and Barsoon1996) who argue that states have incentives to violate international agreements even if they have previously ratified them. In the absence of a centralized enforcement mechanism, such as an omnipotent and benevolent world government, states monitor and sanction behavior by threatening defectors and free riders with punishment (Keohane, Reference Keohane1984; Axelrod and Keohane, Reference Axelrod and Keohane1985; Downs and Rocke, Reference Downs and Rocke1995; Carrubba, Reference Carrubba2005). To facilitate these tasks, states design international institutions accordingly by establishing dispute resolution mechanisms, monitoring bodies, creating collective enforcement power through issue linkage, and so on (Snidal, Reference Snidal1996; Koremenos et al., Reference Koremenos, Lipson and Snidal2001).

For managerialists, enforcement is a secondary problem in international cooperation. International cooperation problems are complex and ambiguous, but states usually sign and ratify international agreements under a genuine intention to comply with them. Thus, Chayes and Chayes (Reference Chayes and Chayes1995: 22) write, ‘[i]f we are correct that the principal source of noncompliance is not willful disobedience but the lack of capability or clarity or priority, then coercive enforcement is as misguided as it is costly’. In addition to rule interpretation and transparency, Chayes and Chayes (Reference Chayes and Chayes1995) emphasize the importance of adequate capacity to implement policies. Tallberg (Reference Tallberg2002: 614) summarizes this concern as follows:

Whereas some political and economic capacity problems are beyond the reach of international efforts, deficits in technical knowledge, bureaucratic capability, and financial resources maybe partially or entirely offset through capacity building. Often, capacity building is one of the main programmatic activities of international regimes; in other cases, technical and financial assistance is a targeted measure to alleviate a particular problem.

Capacity building is particularly important in the context of North-South international cooperation. Developing countries have limited capacity to implement complex policies necessary to improve trade policy, prevent environmental deterioration, eradicate or contain contagious diseases, reduce corruption, and so on (Barrett, Reference Barrett1994a, Reference Barrett2007; Keohane and Levy, Reference Keohane and Levy1996; Michalopoulos, Reference Michalopoulos1999; Finger and Schuler, Reference Finger and Schuler2000; VanDeveer and Dabelko, Reference VanDeveer and Dabelko2001; Guzman and Simmons, Reference Guzman and Simmons2005; Shaffer, Reference Shaffer2005; Suwa-Eisenmann and Verdier, Reference Suwa-Eisenmann and Verdier2007). And they do not have the financial and organization resources to increase that capacity. Thus, capacity building funded by wealthy donors appears central to successful and mutually profitable international cooperation.

Although, the enforcement and managerialist schools are often seen as competing accounts, it is interesting to note that enforcement concerns and lack of capacity could be mutually complementary.Footnote 4 Downs (Reference Downs1997: 330) recognizes this arguing that ‘[t]he claim that the political economy model is suspect because most treaty violations are caused by factors such as the ambiguity of treaties and capacity limitations rather than the product of premeditated exploitation is problematic because the former does not necessarily preclude the latter’. Indeed, enforcement can be complicated by lack of capacity. To see why, recall that if a state with limited capacity fails to comply, others do not know if the reason is an intended defection or an unintended managerial failure. Thus, inadequate capacity provides a smokescreen for opportunism. In the case of illegal logging in Indonesia that I have introduced, failure to prevent it could either stem from lack of political will or a genuine failure to improve the quality of environmental regulation because of bureaucratic ineffectiveness. Should the international community respond by reducing foreign aid as a punishment, or by increasing foreign aid for capacity building?

Although this dilemma is now in common knowledge among international cooperation theorists, the extant literature has little to say about the effect of alternative enforcement mechanisms on a wealthy donor’s incentives to contribute to capacity building. Intuitively, it seems plausible that the connection between enforcement and capacity building encourages donations because capacity building produces a double dividend. Not only does it solve managerial implementation problems, but it also improves the monitoring (Mitchell, Reference Mitchell1994). If the United States helps Ecuador develop implementation capabilities in rainforest conservation, Ecuador can improve forestry practices – and blaming inadequate capacity for implementation failure is simply not credible. Both effects seem desirable to a wealthy donor.

In the analysis, I compare two alternative enforcement mechanisms. Under reversion, future cooperation is contingent on past compliance with an international agreement but compensation for damage is not necessary (Axelrod, Reference Axelrod1984; Axelrod and Keohane, Reference Axelrod and Keohane1985; Keohane, Reference Keohane1986; Conybeare, Reference Conybeare1987; Downs and Rocke, Reference Downs and Rocke1995; McGillivray and Smith, Reference McGillivray and Smith2000; Langlois and Langlois, Reference Langlois and Langlois2001). For example, if the recipient defects, both foreign aid and policy implementation are temporarily suspended. Under compensation, a defector must compensate the other state (Barrett, Reference Barrett1999; Rosendorff and Milner, Reference Rosendorff and Milner2001; Carrubba, Reference Carrubba2005; Rosendorff, Reference Rosendorff2005; Svolik, Reference Svolik2006). This can be done so that the defector cooperates while the other state free rides for some time. For example, if the recipient defects, policy implementation continues for sometime while foreign aid is temporarily frozen.

Both enforcement mechanisms are based on the idea of reciprocity (Axelrod, Reference Axelrod1984). As Downs (Reference Downs2000: 323) writes, ‘[d]espite its name, the strategy of reciprocity is not designed to uphold some principle of equity-based justice’. Reversionary enforcement is based on reciprocity, but it does not allow compensation to the victims of non-compliance. In contrast, Keohane (Reference Keohane1986: 6) argues that reciprocity has a normative dimension because it is based on the principle of ‘mutual gain’. The compensation mechanism captures an important element of this normative dimension, because a victim of non-compliance will be compensated.

These enforcement mechanisms are highly stylized. In reality, states can choose from a broad inventory of enforcement mechanisms, ranging from simple reciprocity to issue linkage and institutionalized sanctioning mechanisms or binding dispute resolution (Keohane, Reference Keohane1986; Barrett, Reference Barrett1994b; Lohmann, Reference Lohmann1997; Koremenos, Reference Koremenos2007). The enforcement mechanisms that I study abstract away from the details and focus attention on the willingness of the enforcer to implement a punishment. Any enforcement mechanism that states could use also influences the payoff to the enforcer, so my main analytical results apply to a wide variety of possible enforcement mechanisms.

Intuitively, compensation seems superior for three reasons. Firstly, it does not inflict unnecessary damage on a victim of non-compliance (Chayes and Chayes, Reference Chayes and Chayes1995; Rosendorff, Reference Rosendorff2005). Secondly, compensation is not ‘renegotiable’ because a victim of non-compliance actually prefers compensation to business as usual (Farrell and Maskin, Reference Farrell and Maskin1989; Barrett, Reference Barrett1994b). In contrast, both states prefer not to implement the punishment under reversion. Finally, I show below that in an exchange relationship, compensation is easier to enforce than reversion. My key contribution is to show that states nevertheless often have good reasons to choose reversion over compensation, because the donor thus has stronger incentives to fund capacity building.

The Model

In the model, a wealthy donor and a poor recipient form an exchange relationship under which the donor funds policies that eradicate an international negative externality produced by the poor recipient. For example, the European Community and the United States have funded rainforest conservation in Brazil (Kolk, Reference Kolk1998). To improve the value of the exchange relationship, the donor can implement a capacity building program. For example, the United States could train Brazilian officials to enhance measures against illegal logging.

The exchange relationship is modeled as an infinitely repeated game with a common discount factor δ. At every time t∈{0,…,∞}, the donor chooses between contribution (c) and no contribution (d) and the recipient chooses between cooperation (C) and defection (D). The payoffs to the two states are given in Figure 1. The idea is that policy implementation is costly to the recipient, but this cost is lower than the benefit to the donor. Thus, policy implementation for foreign aid is mutually profitable.

Figure 1 Payoffs from international cooperation. The first (second) payoff is for the donor (recipient).

To model the dilemma of enforcement under limited capacity, I use a technique called imperfect public monitoring (Mailath and Samuelson, Reference Mailath and Samuelson2006). After every period, both states know if the donor contributed or not.Footnote 5 But recipient behavior is imperfectly observable, so it could accidentally send a misleading ‘signal’:

  1. (1) If the recipient cooperates, both states see a ‘defection’ signal with probability p and a ‘cooperation’ signal with probability 1−p.

  2. (2) If the recipient defects, both states see a ‘defection’ signal with probability q and a ‘cooperation’ signal with probability 1−q.

To ensure that cooperation increases the probability of a favorable ‘cooperation’ signal, let p < q. Intuitively, these signals correspond to the impression that the donor gets about the recipient’s intentions. The ‘cooperation’ signal carries information that leads the donor to believe the recipient made a genuine effort whereas the ‘defection’ signal suggests otherwise. For example, the donor could consult local non-governmental organizations or audit implemented projects (Maxwell and Riddell, Reference Maxwell and Riddell1998; Dai, Reference Dai2002).

To keep the analysis simple, I consider a single capacity building project that the donor can implement before the repeated game at a small cost ε→0. This project improves the accuracy of monitoring, so that the donor learns how the recipient really behaved more often. Formally, probability p decreases while probability q increases with capacity building. The results hold even if capacity building reduces the cost of cooperation to the recipient, but I omit the unnecessary complication.

The purpose of an international agreement is to ensure that the donor contributes and the recipient cooperates. A simplifying assumption is that if the donor ever fails to comply with an international agreement, international cooperation is permanently suspended. Although unrealistic, this convenient assumption is innocuous because donor behavior is transparent. As long as the donor has incentives to comply, international cooperation never breaks down. I assume this condition holds because the discount factor δ is high enough so that there is a large ‘shadow of the future’ (Axelrod and Keohane, Reference Axelrod and Keohane1985). I can now simply ignore donor incentives and only focus on the difficulties with disciplining the recipient.

I consider two alternative international agreements. The only difference between them is the enforcement mechanism. First, reversion is based on the idea that if the recipient appears to defect, both foreign aid and cooperation are suspended for one period. Given that the donor has no incentive to deviate, the equilibrium strategies are as follows:

  1. (1) During ‘compliance’, play (c, C). During ‘punishment’, play (d, D).

  2. (2) Begin with ‘compliance’ at time zero. Play ‘punishment’ at time t + 1 if ‘compliance’ should have been played but the signal was ‘defection’ at time t. Play ‘compliance’ at time t + 1 otherwise.

Second, compensation is based on the idea that if the recipient appears to defect, it must compensate the donor by cooperating for one period while foreign aid is frozen. Given that the donor has no incentive to deviate, the equilibrium strategies are as follows:

  1. (1) During ‘compliance’, play (c, C). During ‘punishment’, play (d, C).

  2. (2) Begin with ‘compliance’ at time zero. Play ‘punishment’ at time t + 1 if the signal was ‘defection’ at time t.

Under reversion, ‘punishment’ play need not be enforced because the states are playing mutual best responses. Under compensation, ‘punishment’ play must be enforced because the recipient prefers not to cooperate so as to compensate the donor.

Analysis

In equilibrium, the recipient never defects on purpose, but ‘defection’ signals must nevertheless result in punishment because otherwise the recipient has no incentives to comply at all. Under reversion, it is clear that neither state ever deviates during ‘punishment’ because they are playing mutual best responses.

If the donor is supposed to contribute and the recipient is supposed to cooperate, the recipient has an incentive to comply if and only if

(1)

where V is the average payoff from the game to the recipient. The only effect of replacing a ‘cooperation’ signal with a ‘defection’ signal is one unavoidable period of reversion, as if mutually profitable cooperation was postponed by exactly one period. Under imperfect monitoring, we have 0 < V < x−1, so the cost of the punishment is less than the value of successful cooperation.

For ease of interpretation, this expression can also be written as

(2)

The left side is the immediate reward for avoiding the cost of cooperation. The right side is the expected cost of reversion in the following period. Note in particular that loss of cooperation is never certain for the recipient, so the loss is weighted by the increase in probability qp < 1. The discount factor δ is present because punishment follows a period later.

Under compensation, the recipient must have an incentive to comply at any time, be it during ‘compliance’ or ‘punishment’. It is easy to verify that there is nevertheless only one constraint,

(3)

as the punishment consists of exactly one period of compensation. This expression can be written as

(4)

The left side is again the immediate reward for defection and the right side is the cost of possibly losing foreign aid. With x > x−1 > V, international cooperation is unambiguously easier to enforce under compensation than under reversion.

Is compliance possible? If the discount factor δ and the effect of defection on the probability of a ‘defection’ signal qp are high enough, there exists a donation x such that international cooperation is mutually profitable and neither state has an incentive to defect on purpose. In this case, international cooperation is enforceable. Otherwise it is not enforceable. If international cooperation is enforceable, states play according to the international agreement. If international cooperation is not enforceable, the donor never donates and the recipient always defects.

Results

Capacity building increases the value of q and decreases the value of p. Under reversion, this also increases the average payoff to the recipient V, so capacity building unambiguously improves enforceability. I assume that international cooperation is enforceable with capacity building, and possibly but not necessarily without capacity building, as the analysis is trivial if international cooperation is not enforceable even upon capacity building. Capacity building is funded by the donor, so only donor incentives are to be considered.

Consider first reversion. Every period preceded by a ‘defection’ signal produces a zero payoff to the donor, while the payoff after a ‘cooperation’ signal is always 3−x > 0. Capacity building increases the probability 1−p of a ‘cooperation’ signal, so it is profitable to the donor:

Proposition 1 (preference alignment). Under reversion, the donor builds capacity.

As long as capacity building is not too costly, it is unambiguously profitable to the donor. The only effect of capacity building is to reduce the frequency of erroneous ‘defection’ signals that occur every now and then even though the recipient cooperates. Such ‘defection’ signals must trigger punishment that is unfortunately costly to both states under reciprocal enforcement. The silver lining for the recipient is that under reciprocal enforcement, the donor has strong incentives to build capacity.

This simple principle of preference alignment is very general for reversionary mechanisms. It does not depend on the assumption that capacity building increases the average payoff to the recipient, or the assumption that the length of the punishment period is one period. Under reciprocal enforcement, either both states or neither state profit, so the preference alignment is rather strong. Reversion implies that the donor suffers from the recipient’s inadequate capacity to implement cooperative policies, so capacity building is something that both sides prefer.

Consider now compensation. Every period preceded by a ‘defection’ signal produces a payoff 3 while every period preceded by a ‘cooperation’ signal produces a payoff 3−x. Clearly, 3 > 3−x. Capacity building increases the probability 1−p of a ‘cooperation’ signal, so the frequency of the higher payoff decreases. Thus, capacity building is not profitable if international cooperation is enforceable without it:

Proposition 2 (preference non-alignment). Under compensation, the donor builds capacity if and only if international cooperation is not enforceable otherwise.

If enforceability is guaranteed, donor–recipient preferences are diametrically opposed under compensation. Every time the recipient cooperates but the erroneous ‘defection’ signal results, the donor is given unwarranted compensation. As a result, the donor benefits from lack of capacity. But if international cooperation cannot be enforced without capacity building, the donor is willing to build capacity so as to achieve any international cooperation. Thus, the donor never really prefers to invest in capacity building, but it might have to do so for enforceability.

This result is almost diabolical because a seemingly benevolent enforcement mechanism removes the donor incentive to invest in capacity building even if this is costless. The two states have designed an international agreement that prescribes compensation, and the lure of this compensation prevents capacity building. It is essential to note that the result is qualified if capacity building increases the value of international cooperation to the donor (as opposed to the recipient). If this increase outweighs the reduced frequency of compensation, partial preference alignment is possible. But even here, full preference alignment is never possible because preferences over the quality of monitoring continue to be diametrically opposed.

The following example suggests that policymakers appreciate this logic. When the Global Environment Facility was first established in preparation for the 1992 Earth Summit, a largely unsuccessful pilot phase led donors and recipients to agree on rather egalitarian principles for the allocation of foreign aid for environmental protection (Streck, Reference Streck2001; Clémençon, Reference Clémençon2006). At the third replenishment of the institution in 2002, President Bush announced that the United States was no longer willing to give foreign aid to developing countries that do not meet stringent performance criteria related to good governance (Hicks et al., Reference Hicks, Parks, Roberts and Tierney2008: 54). This announcement provoked a furious response by the Group of 77 who argued that such conditionality would change the nature of the Global Environment Facility to the extent that it was completely unacceptable (al-Nasser, Reference al-Nasser2004). Although the United States ultimately prevailed, it is notable that other donor countries also resisted the idea (Hicks et al., Reference Hicks, Parks, Roberts and Tierney2008, 54).

The result on enforcement and capacity building can help us to understand these dynamics. It is not immediately clear why the developing countries should unanimously resist performance criteria, especially if the total amount of aid remains unchanged. It is equally surprising that other donor countries were unwilling to consider such performance criteria, given widespread public concerns regarding the efficacy of foreign aid. But if donors can legitimately reduce foreign aid upon perceived compliance failure, their incentives to support capacity building in the long term are diminished. Performance criteria force developing countries to correct implementation failures and implement reforms before additional foreign aid is available, so they strongly resemble the compensation mechanism that I have analyzed. The resulting negative effect on capacity building could explain why the other donors agreed with the developing countries that this was not a good idea, even if they were actually committed to global environmental protection.

Concluding Remarks

I have examined the relationship between enforcement and capacity building in international cooperation. The key result concerns the possibility of preference alignment for capacity building. If states cooperate in the shadow of an international agreement based on a reversionary enforcement mechanism, the donor has a strong incentive to build capacity for the recipient because it thus reduces the risk of cooperation failure. But if enforcement is based on compensation for perceived failure to cooperate, the donor could deliberately refuse to build capacity so as to obtain compensation more frequently. Although the game-theoretic model that I have analyzed is simple, this alignment theorem holds in a wide range of circumstances.

International cooperation theorists have not previously recognized this relationship. Other rationalist explanations for limiting enforcement to reversion include the negotiation costs that dispute resolution mechanisms carry (Keohane, Reference Keohane1984; Koremenos et al., Reference Koremenos, Lipson and Snidal2001; Koremenos, Reference Koremenos2005; Carrubba, Reference Carrubba2009) and the possibility that enforcing compensation is sometimes too difficult (Downs and Rocke, Reference Downs and Rocke1995; Barrett, Reference Barrett1999). The argument advanced here is particularly notable, however, because it operates even if strong sanctions are enforceable and do not carry high negotiation costs. Additionally, it can explain reversion even if compensation is easier to enforce than reversion. But the argument also does not contradict the existing explanations in any way, and indeed the results that favor reversion are stronger if the compensation mechanism is costly or difficult to enforce.

These results can inform the debate on enforcement and capacity building as avenues to international compliance (Chayes and Chayes, Reference Chayes and Chayes1995; Downs et al., Reference Downs, Rocke and Barsoon1996; Tallberg, Reference Tallberg2002). If the incentive to build capacity depends on the enforcement mechanism, it is not possible to understand one without understanding the other. This finding suggests that empirical and theoretical future research should integrate insights from both schools and serves as a warning against favoring one line of reasoning over the other in policy formation.

The argument is also relevant to the broader relationship between distributional conflict and enforcement. Fearon (Reference Fearon1998) argues that while a large ‘shadow of the future’ facilitates enforcement because states assign higher cost to institutional breakdown, it creates incentives to engage in costly heavy-handed bargaining.Footnote 6 My argument shows that the choice of enforcement mechanism has direct implications for distributional conflict. Since the compensation mechanism results in ‘regressive foreign aid’ from the recipient to the donor, it is even possible that the recipient refuses to engage in costly international negotiations if the compensation mechanism is on the table. Thus, the compensation mechanism could prevent international cooperation. This is a stronger effect than an increase in bargaining cost, and it could explain why powerful states often prefer reversion over compensation.

The argument can inform the debate about the role of legitimacy in international cooperation (Young, Reference Young1989; Chayes and Chayes, Reference Chayes and Chayes1995; Hurd, Reference Hurd1999; Wendt, Reference Wendt1999; Clark, Reference Clark2003; Thompson, Reference Thompson2006; Chapman, Reference Chapman2007).Footnote 7 Although legitimacy appears to be an important determinant of compliance with international rules and standards, it is not obvious what the implications for the choice of enforcement mechanisms are. Should we consider reversion illegitimate because it imposes costs on an innocent state? According to my theory, this counterargument to reversion is often invalid because reversion prompts preference alignment ex ante and thus appears equitable. The compensation mechanism opens a window of opportunity for exploitation, so weak states and foreign publics concerned with the normative implications of international cooperation have good reasons to view reversionary enforcement as legitimate.

The relationship between enforcement and capacity building is also important for the political economy of development assistance. Recently, many scholars have argued that foreign aid could harm economic growth and democratization unless domestic institutions incentivize the recipient government to use resources for the provision of various public goods (Svensson, Reference Svensson2000; Easterly, Reference Easterly2002; Smith and Bueno de Mesquita, Reference Smith and Bueno de Mesquita2007; Bueno de Mesquita and Smith, Reference Bueno de Mesquita and Smith2009). If the reader accepts the notion that capacity building promotes good governance, it could be that for the population, as opposed to the government, capacity building – not foreign aid per se – is the real benefit of international cooperation. Then reversion is particularly desirable because it ensures that even a self-interested donor cooperating with an autocracy can produce valuable public goods.

The most important assumption underpinning the theoretical analysis is that the recipient cannot credibly threaten to terminate cooperation unless capacity building is forthcoming. If the recipient could condition cooperation on capacity building, an equilibrium would exist in which capacity building occurs under compensation enforcement. But given the asymmetric power relationship between the donor and recipient, the range of circumstances in which such bargaining tactics can be successful appears narrow. This boundary condition is also useful because it produces a falsifiable empirical hypothesis that can be operationalized against data on relative bargaining power.Footnote 8

The analysis is robust to such variations as introducing multiple donors and recipients. As long as compliance is imperfectly observable, the fundamental problem of responding to perceived compliance failure remains intact. This problem is also present even if the donor holds ‘altruistic’ motivations and gives foreign aid to improve welfare in the recipient country. If the altruistic motive is strong enough, however, the commitment problem that I have identified could disappear because the donor holds an intrinsic preference for capacity building.

Theoretical analysis has two counterintuitive empirical implications. First, reversion should be most common in issue areas that require capacity building, such as regulatory and judicial reform or environmental conservation, and if the recipient is a least developed country. While an empirical test is beyond the scope of this study, this result is particularly important in light of the current emphasis on conditionality in the allocation of foreign aid (Vreeland, Reference Vreeland2003; Stone, Reference Stone2008). While some form of conditionality is necessary to incentivize the recipient, capacity building requires that the donor cannot exploit the conditions to demand compensation from the recipient.

Second, reversion should be less common if the two states operate in a highly institutionalized and legalized environment, such as the European Union, where credible commitments are possible.Footnote 9 If the donor can commit to capacity building, reversion can be augmented with compensation to the advantage of donor. And the donor could even increase the provision of foreign aid in exchange to ensure that both parties benefit from the compensation mechanism. But all this is only possible if mutual commitment capacity is readily available.

To conclude, the analysis creates opportunities for progressive theoretical research in international politics. The simple setup that I have used offers an accessible and flexible platform for game-theoretic analyzes of international cooperation between weak and powerful states. The mechanics of the baseline model are simple, so it is easy to add such new elements as domestic or transnational actors to it (Keck and Sikkink, Reference Keck and Sikkink1998; Dai, Reference Dai2002). The model can be applied to various international cooperation problems and the rationalist premises can be relaxed to incorporate sociological or constructivist theories of international politics (Ruggie, Reference Ruggie1998; Hurd, Reference Hurd1999; Wendt, Reference Wendt1999; Checkel, Reference Checkel2001). Ideally, the theoretical analysis contributes to the research program on compliance with international agreements beyond the question that I have addressed.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Jennifer Kavanagh, the anonymous reviewers, and the editors of International Theory for their valuable comments and advice.

Footnotes

1 ‘ “ Corruption” in Indonesia Logging War’. BBC News 14 January 2003.

2 ‘Indonesia World’s No. 3 Greenhouse Gas Emitter: Report’. Reuters 4 June 2007.

3 For a review, see Tallberg (Reference Tallberg2002: 611–614).

4 See Svolik (Reference Svolik2006) for an application to democratic transparency in international cooperation.

5 All results hold if donor behavior is misperceived with a small enough probability.

6 See Bearce (Reference Bearce2002) for institutional breakdown and Krasner (Reference Krasner1991) for the power politics of international cooperation.

7 For legitimacy in social theory, see Suchman (Reference Suchman1995).

8 For complications of power analysis in international politics, see Baldwin (Reference Baldwin1979, Reference Baldwin1986) and Barnett and Duvall (Reference Barnett and Duvall2005).

9 See Abbott and Snidal (Reference Abbott and Snidal2000) and Goldstein et al. (Reference Goldstein, Kahler, Keohane and Slaughter2000) for legalization in international politics.

References

Abbott, K.W.Snidal, D. (1998), ‘Why states act through formal international organizations’, Journal of Conflict Resolution 42(1): 332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Abbott, K.W.Snidal, D. (2000), ‘Hard and soft law in international overnance’, International Organization 54(3): 421456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
al-Nasser, N.A. (2004), Submission of the Group of 77, New York, NY: Group of 77.Google Scholar
Alesina, A.Dollar, D. (2000), ‘Who gives foreign aid to whom and why?’, Journal of Economic Growth 5(1): 3363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, R. (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation, New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Axelrod, R.Keohane, R.O. (1985), ‘Achieving cooperation under anarchy: strategies and institutions’, World Politics 38(1): 226254.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baldwin, D.A. (1979), ‘Power analysis and world politics: new trends versus old tendencies’, World Politics 31(2): 161194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baldwin, D.A. (1986), Economic Statecraft, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Barnett, M.Duvall, R. (2005), ‘Power in international politics’, International Organization 59(1): 3975.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrett, S. (1994a), ‘The biodiversity supergame’, Environmental and Resource Economics 4(1): 111122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrett, S. (1994b), ‘Self-enforcing international environmental agreements’, Oxford Economic Papers 46(Suppl): 878894.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrett, S. (1999), ‘A theory of full international cooperation’, Journal of Theoretical Politics 11(4): 519541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barrett, S. (2007), Why Cooperate? The Incentive to Supply Global Public Goods, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bearce, D.H. (2002), ‘Institutional breakdown and international cooperation: the European agreement to recognize Croatia and Slovenia’, European Journal of International Relations 8(4): 471497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bueno de Mesquita, B.Smith, A. (2009), ‘A political economy of aid’, International Organization 63(2): 309340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burnside, C.Dollar, D. (2000), ‘Aid, policies, and growth’, American Economic Review 90(4): 847868.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrubba, C.J. (2005), ‘Courts and compliance in international regulatory regimes’, Journal of Politics 67(3): 669689.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrubba, C.J. (2009), ‘A model of the endogenous development of judicial institutions in federal and international systems’, Journal of Politics 71(1): 5569.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chapman, T.L. (2007), ‘International security institutions, domestic politics, and institutional legitimacy’, Journal of Conflict Resolution 51(1): 134166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chayes, A.Chayes, A.H. (1995), The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Checkel, J.T. (2001), ‘Why comply? Social learning and European identity change’, International Organization 55(3): 553588.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, I. (2003), ‘Legitimacy in a global order’, Review of International Studies 29(1): 7595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clémençon, R. (2006), ‘What future for the Global Environment Facility?’, Journal of Environment and Development 15(1): 5074.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Conybeare, J.A.C. (1987), Trade Wars: The Theory and Practice of International Commercial Rivalry, New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Dai, X. (2002), ‘Information systems in treaty regimes’, World Politics 54(4): 405436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, G.W. (1997), ‘Enforcement and the evolution of cooperation’, Michigan Journal of International Law 19: 319344.Google Scholar
Downs, G.W. (2000), ‘Constructing effective environmental regimes’, Annual Review of Political Science 3: 2542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, G.W.Rocke, D.M. (1995), Optimal Imperfection? Domestic Uncertainty and Institutions in International Relations, Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Downs, G.W., Rocke, D.M.Barsoon, P.N. (1996), ‘Is the good news about compliance good news about cooperation?’, International Organization 50(3): 379406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Easterly, W. (2002), The Elusive Quest for Growth, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Farrell, J.Maskin, E.S. (1989), ‘Renegotiation in repeated games’, Games and Economic Behavior 1(4): 327360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fearon, J.D. (1998), ‘Bargaining, enforcement, and international cooperation’, International Organization 52(2): 269305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finger, J.M.Schuler, P. (2000), ‘Implementation of Uruguay round commitments: the development challenge’, World Economy 23(4): 511525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilligan, M.J. (2004), ‘Is there a broader-deeper trade-off in international multilateral agreements’, International Organization 58(3): 459484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldstein, J., Kahler, M., Keohane, R.O.Slaughter, A.-M. (2000), ‘Introduction: legalization and world politics’, International Organization 54(3): 385399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guzman, A.T.Simmons, B.A. (2005), ‘Power plays and capacity constraints: the selection of defendants in world trade organization disputes’, Journal of Legal Studies 34(2): 557598.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hicks, R.L., Parks, B.C., Roberts, J.T.Tierney, M.J. (2008), Greening Aid? Understanding the Environmental Impact of Development Assistance, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurd, I. (1999), ‘Legitimacy and authority in international politics’, International Organization 53(2): 379408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ikenberry, G.J. (2000), After Victory: Institutions, Strategic Restraint, and the Rebuilding of Order after Major Wars, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Keck, M.E.Sikkink, K. (1998), Activists Beyond Borders: Advocacy Networks in International Politics, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Keohane, R.O. (1984), After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Keohane, R.O. (1986), ‘Reciprocity in international relations’, International Organization 40(1): 127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keohane, R.O.Levy, M.A. (1996), Institutions for the Earth: Sources of Effective International Environmental Protection, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kolk, A. (1998), ‘From conflict to cooperation: international policies to protect the Brazilian Amazon’, World Development 26(8): 14811493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koremenos, B. (2005), ‘Contracting around international uncertainty’, American Political Science Review 99(4): 549565.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koremenos, B. (2007), ‘If only half of international agreements have dispute resolution provisions, which half needs explaining?’, Journal of Legal Studies 36(1): 189212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koremenos, B., Lipson, C.Snidal, D. (2001), ‘The rational design of international institutions’, International Organization 55(4): 761799.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krasner, S.D. (1991), ‘Global communications and national power: life on the Pareto frontier’, World Politics 43(3): 336366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langlois, C.C.Langlois, J.-P. (2001), ‘Engineering cooperation: a game theoretic analysis of phased international agreements’, American Journal of Political Science 45(3): 599619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lohmann, S. (1997), ‘Linkage politics’, Journal of Conflict Resolution 41(1): 3867.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mailath, G.J.Samuelson, L. (2006), Repeated Games and Reputations: Long-run Relationships, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maxwell, S.Riddell, R. (1998), ‘Conditionality or contract: perspectives on partnership for development’, Journal of International Development 10(2): 257268.3.0.CO;2-S>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGillivray, F.Smith, A. (2000), ‘Trust and cooperation through agent-specific punishments’, International Organization 54(4): 809824.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Michalopoulos, C. (1999), ‘The developing countries in the WTO’, World Economy 22(1): 117143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitchell, R.B. (1994), ‘Regime design matters: intentional oil pollution and treaty compliance’, International Organization 48(3): 425458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reus-Smit, C. (2003), ‘Politics and international obligation’, European Journal of International Relations 9(4): 591625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosendorff, B.P. (2005), ‘Stability and rigidity: politics and design of the WTO’s dispute settlement procedure’, American Political Science Review 99(3): 389400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosendorff, B.P.Milner, H.V. (2001), ‘The optimal design of international trade institutions: uncertainty and escape’, International Organization 55(4): 829857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruggie, J.G. (1998), ‘What makes the world hang together? Neo-utilitarianism and the social constructivist challenge’, International Organization 52(4): 855885.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shaffer, G. (2005), ‘Can WTO technical assistance and capacity-building serve developing countries?’, Wisconsin International Law Journal 23(4): 643686.Google Scholar
Smith, A.Bueno de Mesquita, B. (2007), ‘Foreign aid and policy concessions’, Journal of Conflict Resolution 51(2): 251284.Google Scholar
Snidal, D. (1996), ‘Political economy and international institutions’, International Review of Law and Economics 16(1): 121137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stone, R.W. (2008), ‘The scope of IMF conditionality’, International Organization 62(4): 589620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Streck, C. (2001), ‘The Global Environment Facility: a role model for international governance?’, Global Environmental Politics 1(2): 7194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suchman, M.C. (1995), ‘Managing legitimacy: strategic and institutional approaches’, Academy of Management Review 20(3): 571610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suwa-Eisenmann, A.Verdier, T. (2007), ‘Aid and trade’, Oxford Review of Economic Policy 23(3): 481507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Svensson, J. (2000), ‘Foreign aid and rent-seeking’, Journal of International Economics 51(2): 437461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Svolik, M. (2006), ‘Lies, defection and the pattern of international cooperation’, American Journal of Political Science 50(4): 909925.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tallberg, J. (2002), ‘Paths to compliance: enforcement, management, and the European Union’, International Organization 56(3): 609643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, A. (2006), ‘Coercion through IOs: the Security Council and the logic of information transmission’, International Organization 60(1): 134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
VanDeveer, S.D.Dabelko, G.D. (2001), ‘It’s capacity, stupid: international assistance and national implementation’, Global Environmental Politics 1(2): 1829.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vreeland, J. (2003), The IMF and Economic Development, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wendt, A. (1999), Social Theory of International Politics, New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, O.R. (1989), ‘The politics of international regime formation: managing natural resources and the environment’, International Organization 43(3): 349375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, O.R. (1999), Governance in World Affairs, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 Payoffs from international cooperation. The first (second) payoff is for the donor (recipient).