Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-lrblm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T10:03:26.352Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The discourse of anarchy in IR

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 September 2015

Jack Donnelly*
Affiliation:
Josef Korbel School of International Studies, University of Denver, Denver, Colorado, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Contemporary International Relations (IR) typically treats anarchy as a fundamental, defining, and analytically central feature of international relations. Furthermore, it is usually held that IR since its inception has been structured around a discourse of anarchy. In fact, however, until the 1980s anarchy was rarely employed as a central analytical concept, as I show by examining 145 books published between 1895 and 1978. The conceptual and analytic centrality of anarchy is not imposed on us by international reality. Rather, it is a recent and contingent construction. Given the shortcomings of standard uses of ‘anarchy’ – especially the facts that there is no clear, generally agreed upon definition, that ‘the effects of anarchy’ are not effects of anarchy (alone), and that anarchy is not the structural ordering principle of international systems – I argue for returning to earlier practice and putting anarchy back in the background of IR.

Type
Original Papers
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2015 

Contemporary IR typically treats anarchy as a ‘fundamental’ (Milner Reference Milner1991, 67; Schmidt Reference Schmidt1998, 1; Miller Reference Miller2002, 10; Holmes Reference Holmes2011, 291) feature of international relations; ‘the defining characteristic of international politics’ (Krasner Reference Krasner1992, 48). ‘Virtually all scholars agree that relations between states are anarchic and that this is one of the most unique, important, and enduring features of world politics’ (Lake Reference Lake2009, 2). It is also commonly held that ‘the field of international relations has, from its earliest years, been structured by a discourse about anarchy’ (Schmidt Reference Schmidt1998, 41).

Actually, however, until the 1980s IR rarely employed anarchy as a central analytical concept. Part One shows that anarchy, rather than a constant and objectively necessary feature of the study of international relations, is a recent discursive construction.

Part Two argues that American IR’s construction of anarchy as both demarcating the discipline and a major structural and explanatory variable cannot succeed. Any definition that plausibly makes anarchy a feature of (nearly) all international systems has no interesting substantive implications. Any definition that gives ‘anarchy’ determinate effects or makes it a plausible structural ordering principle, however, renders anarchy a feature of a subset of international systems.

Part Two shows that (American) IR uses ‘anarchy’ in multiple, shifting senses; that anarchy has no effects; and that anarchy does not structure international systems. I conclude by further explicating the idea of the construction of anarchy and arguing for putting anarchy (back) in the background of the discipline.

Part one: the construction of anarchy in contemporary IR

I begin by demonstrating a fundamental discursive transformation following the publication in 1979 of Kenneth Waltz’s Theory of International Politics.

The pattern of usage

This section lays out the evidence, looking quantitatively at more than 200 books published between 1895 and 2013; surveying the general pattern of usage before 1979; and examining six interwar books that make central reference to anarchy.

Quantitative evidence

I begin by counting occurrences of ‘anarchy’ and ‘anarchic’ in 92 books published between 1895 and 1945, 53 published between 1946 and 1978, and 62 published between 1979 and 2013.Footnote 1 Appendices 1–3, which for reasons of space are available online,Footnote 2 list the books and the number of occurrences per book. (Works cited in this essay – a third of the total – have the author’s name in small caps in the reference list and the number of occurrences in square brackets at the end of the entry.) Appendices 1 and 2 also quote all electronically available passages in pre-1979 books that use the terms less than 20 times, allowing interested readers access to most of the ‘raw data’ for the pre-1979 period.

Table 1 shows a striking pattern. Before 1979 the median number of uses of ‘anarchy’ or ‘anarchic’ is 2. After 1978 the median is 24. Before 1979 three-fifths of the books use ‘anarchy’ or ‘anarchic’ three or fewer times. After 1978 four-fifths use these terms 10 or more times. Moreover, the pattern is essentially the same for 1895–1945 and 1946–78. A sharp transition occurs around the publication of Theory of International Politics.

Table 1 Occurrences of ‘anarchy’ and ‘anarchic’ in selected books

This transition is nicely illustrated in ‘handbooks’ of the discipline. The IR volume of Fred Greenstein and Nelson Polsby’s (Reference Greenstein and Polsby1975) Handbook of Political Science contains 11 occurrences of ‘anarchy’ or ‘anarchic,’ six of which are in the chapter by Waltz, with a seventh in the index (which references only pages in the Waltz chapter). The Handbook of International Relations, edited by Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse, and Beth Simmons, (Reference Carlsnaes, Risse and Simmons2002, Reference Carlsnaes, Risse and Simmons2013) contains 86 occurrences in both its 2002 and 2013 editions. Christian Reus-Smit and Duncan Snidal’s (Reference Reus-Smit and Snidal2008) The Oxford Handbook of International Relations has over a hundred.

The same pattern is evident in James Dougherty and William Pfaltzgraff’s Contending Theories of International Relations, a well-known IR Theory textbook. The 1971 and 1981 editions use ‘anarchy’ and ‘anarchic’ five and seven times, respectively. The 1990 and 1997 editions use them 20 and 56 times.

‘Anarchy’ was not even widely employed in pre-Waltzian realism. For example, the term occurs only twice, in passing, in E. H. Carr’s (Reference Carr1964 [1946], 28, 162) The Twenty YearsCrisis, in George Kennan’s (Reference Kennan1951, 33, 149) American Diplomacy, and in Henry Kissinger’s (Reference Kissinger1957, 17, 25) A World Restored. None of the seven editions of Morgenthau’s Politics Among Nations contains an index entry for anarchy.Footnote 3 Scientific Man versus Power Politics (1946, 117) refers once to ‘the international anarchy of our age,’ not international relations in general; In Defense of the National Interest (1951, 102, 103) uses the term twice, both times indicating disorder.

The pattern of usage in pre-1979 IR

A quarter of my pre-1979 books do not use ‘anarchy’ or ‘anarchic’ at all. Another quarter use them only once or twice.Footnote 4 Moreover, of those that do employ the terms, almost half (52 of 107) use the ordinary language sense of disorder in half or more of the total occurrences.Footnote 5

This largely explains the relatively infrequent use of anarchy. As ‘anarchy’ lacked a well-established technical sense there was little reason to use it often.

In a few, usually isolated, passages anarchy is presented as a general feature of international relations.Footnote 6 The most common ‘technical’ sense, however, indicates the external juridical consequences of state sovereignty.Footnote 7 ‘Sovereignty was a doctrine of legal anarchy’ (Fenwick Reference Fenwick1934, 47). ‘Juristically speaking, there exists a condition of anarchy’ (Hill Reference Hill1911, 15, cf. 140). Most strikingly, Frank Russell (Reference Russell1936, 540) writes of ‘an “anarchy of sovereignties”’.

Sometimes, though, anarchy is presented as the condition that exists in the absence of a system of sovereign states. (Sovereignty is here understood to involve mutual legal recognition and restraint that puts an end to anarchic lawlessness (Hill Reference Hill1911, 140, 173; Walsh Reference Walsh1922, 123, 221; Herz Reference Herz1959, 59–60.) For example, medieval (but not modern) international relations is described as anarchic (Walsh Reference Walsh1922, 57; Hodges Reference Hodges1931, 57 [sic]) – because there were no sovereign states. Some authors draw a similar distinction between the early and later modern periods (Lawrence Reference Lawrence1898 [1895], 35; Follett Reference Follett1920, 269; Potter Reference Potter1922, 40, 457; Reference Potter1929, xiii, 25; Potter and West Reference Potter and West1927, 4; Hodges Reference Hodges1931, 48; Schuman Reference Schuman1933, 39; Fenwick Reference Fenwick1934, 49, cf.; Russell Reference Russell1936, 90; Earle et al. Reference Earle, Craig and Gilbert1943, 33; Herz Reference Herz1959, 43–44; Wright Reference Wright1964 [1942], 180).

Finally, a disparate residual set of uses contrasts sharply with contemporary usage. For example, Quincy Wright argues that when defense predominates ‘international anarchy has sometimes resulted’ and that ‘universal empire or anarchy has usually followed balance-of-power periods’ (Reference Wright1964 [1942], 63, 127, cf. Follett Reference Follett1920, 307). Morton Kaplan argues that bipolar war leads to ‘a hierarchical international system if one side wins or international anarchy if both sides are exhausted. Almost any kind of system may replace this state of anarchy’ (Reference Kaplan1957, 49). Both Alfred Zimmern (Reference Zimmern1936, 40, 62) and F. H. Hinsley (Reference Hinsley1963, 220) contrast the rise of international conferences in the nineteenth century to the anarchy of the eighteenth century. Nationalism (Angell Reference Angell1921, 98; Woolf Reference Woolf1940, 76), the will to power (Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1932, 18), and ‘the backwardness of weak states’ (Lippmann Reference Lippmann1915, 127, cf. 114) are presented as sources of anarchy. For Mary Parker Follett ‘anarchy means unorganized, unrelated difference’ (Reference Follett1920, 35, cf. 305). For Frederick Hicks ‘international anarchy … implies absolute disrespect for law on the part of all states’ (Reference Hicks1920, 7). Before 1979, such passages, rather than infrequent oddities, comprise a sizable portion of total uses that do not simply indicate disorder.

Earlier authors did, of course, address issues that today are considered matters of anarchy. It was uncommon, though, to view them through the lens (or as manifestations) of anarchy. Moreover, ‘anarchy,’ which had several meanings, rarely defined international relations or explained behavior in international systems in general.

Anarchy, states systems, and international relations

Six (7%) of my pre-1946 books do employ anarchy as a major explanatory variable: G. Lowes Dickinson’s The European Anarchy (1916) and The International Anarchy (1926), Frederick Schuman’s International Politics (1933), Philip Henry Kerr (Lord Lothian)’s Pacifism in Not Enough (1935), Nicholas Spykman’s America’s Strategy in World Politics (1942), and Edward Vose Gulick’s The Balance of Power (1943). (This set, fortuitously, includes two ‘idealists’ (Dickinson and Kerr), two ‘realists’ (Schuman and Spykman), and a pacifist (Gulick) who seems pulled in both directions.) Only one book, though, understands anarchy as the absence of government or a defining feature of international relations.

Dickinson, according to John Mearsheimer (Reference Mearsheimer2006, 234), ‘invented the concept of international anarchy’. Andreas Osiander argues that ‘whether or not [Dickinson] actually coined the term, he contributed greatly to its popularity’ (Reference Osiander1998, 413, cf. Long Reference Long1995, 314). Dickinson also figures prominently in Brian Schmidt’s The Political Discourse of Anarchy, the best-known early history of the discipline.

Dickinson’s explanations of state action are regularly embedded in a system of anarchy (Reference Dickinson1917 [1916], 14, 19, 26–27, 42, 71, 73, 80, 96–98, 127–29, 136–37). He insists, even in the midst of World War I, that although Germany bears considerable responsibility for the outbreak of fighting ‘the real culprit was the European anarchy’ (Reference Dickinson1917 [1916], 101, cf. 144; Reference Dickinson1926, 325, 471). Most strikingly, Dickinson argues that ‘whenever and wherever the anarchy of armed states exists, war does become inevitable’ (Reference Dickinson1926, v).

His aim, however, is to analyze the ‘general situation’ that results from ‘the juxtaposition of a number of states, independent and armed. This was the condition of civilization in the three periods of European history that are most studied – ancient Greece, Renaissance Italy, and modern Europe; and under that condition war is not an accident’ (Dickinson Reference Dickinson1926, 3–4, emphasis added). Dickinson, in other words, addresses not international relations in general but states systems.

More particularly, Dickinson’s topic is ‘the European anarchy’ that produced World War I.Footnote 8 His book by that name begins ‘in the great and tragic history of Europe there is a turning-point that marks … the definite acceptance of international anarchy. That turning-point is the emergence of the sovereign State at the end of the fifteenth century’ (Reference Dickinson1917 [1916], 13). In the final sentence, he concludes that ‘the European anarchy is the real cause of European wars’ (Reference Dickinson1917 [1916], 144).

Furthermore, ‘the international anarchy’ for Dickinson includes much more than sovereign states interacting in the absence of overarching law and authority.

States armed, and therefore a menace to one another; policies ostensibly defensive but really just as much offensive; these policies pursued in the dark by a few men who, because they act secretly, cannot act honestly; and this whole complex playing upon primitive passions, arousable at any moment by appropriate appeals from a Press which has no object expect to make money out of the weakness of men – that is the real situation of the world under the conditions of international anarchy (Dickinson Reference Dickinson1926, 47, cf. Dickinson Reference Dickinson1920, 17, 34–36, 49–52, 63–81, 82).

‘The international anarchy’ identifies a particularly perverse, historically contingent form of power politics. ‘What was wrong? Germany? England? No. The European tradition and system’ (Dickinson Reference Dickinson1917 [1916], 78).

This thick definition of anarchy also explains Dickinson’s (to our ears awkward) use of the definite article in both the titles and the text of his books. He addresses not international anarchy (in general) but the (very particular) ‘international anarchy’ of his time.

Schuman, Spykman, and Gulick also address systems of sovereign states – and the modern western states system in particular.

Schuman argues that ‘if anarchy involves the absence of government, the pursuit by each of his own ends, and the use of violence in the service of such ends, then the practice of international politics can indeed be described accurately as “international anarchy”’ (Reference Schuman1933, 514). This passage, however, concludes a paragraph that addresses ‘Sovereign States’ interacting in ‘a State System’ (Reference Schuman1933, 514).

For Schuman, state sovereignty, not anarchy, defines modern international relations. ‘The sovereignty of the territorial State remains in the twentieth century, as in the sixteenth, … the most characteristic feature of the entire Western State System’ (Reference Schuman1933, 53, cf. 502). ‘The concept of State sovereignty, the principles of international law, and the politics of the balance of power may be regarded as the three cornerstones upon which the Western State System has come to rest’ (Reference Schuman1933, 49, cf. 52).

Furthermore, as these passages suggest, Schuman’s subject is not international relations in general but the Western state system. (The book’s subtitle is An Introduction to the Western State System.) He addresses ‘western civilization and the systems of international politics which that civilization has developed’ (Reference Schuman1933, 536), aiming ‘to describe the Western State System realistically and objectively in terms of its cultural origins, its institutionalized forms, its dynamic forces, and its apparent prospects’ (Reference Schuman1933, xiii, cf. 831).

In Spykman’s America’s Strategy in World Politics, a number of passages do sound strikingly similar to Waltz. ‘The international community is without government, without a central authority to preserve law and order’ (Reference Spykman1942, 446, cf. xiii, 7, 18). ‘The so-called sovereign independence of states, the absence of higher authority, and the freedom from external restraints … give to interstate relations their peculiar character of anarchy’ (Reference Spykman1942, 16).

This last passage, however, continues ‘This historical state system consisting of sovereign independent units …’ (Spykman Reference Spykman1942, 16). Spykman, like Schuman and Dickinson, sees anarchy as characteristic of a particular contingent configuration. ‘War is unpleasant, but it is an inherent part of state systems composed of sovereign independent units’ (Spykman Reference Spykman1942, 25).

Gulick similarly argues that international anarchy, understood as ‘the absence of any over-all authority,’ is the ‘central’ and ‘outstanding characteristic’ of ‘the system of sovereign, independent states’ (Reference Gulick1943, 12, 34, 38). He addresses not international relations in general but ‘an anarchic system of sovereign, independent states’ (Reference Gulick1943, 55). This type of international system is characterized by balance of power politics, which is the particular subject of Gulick’s book. ‘The ancient Chinese had a taste of it, as well as early middle-eastern State-systems, the Greek City States, and others. Moreover, it has been consciously applied by European statesmen for the last four hundred or more years’ (Gulick Reference Gulick1943, 1, cf. 11–12, 14, 15). In the eras of Rome, Charlemagne, and the Holy Roman Empire, however, ‘the absence of a State-system meant the absence of the Balance of Power’ (Gulick Reference Gulick1943, 14).

Lord Lothian’s Pacifism is Not Enough is the one book in my pre-1946 sample that uses ‘anarchy’ very much like contemporary IR does. Lord Lothian speaks repeatedly of the ‘anarchy of sovereign states’ (Kerr Reference Kerr1935, 13, 16, 23) and the anarchy ‘inherent in state sovereignty’ (Kerr Reference Kerr1935, 14, 37, 47–48). Moreover, unlike most others in early IR, he neither understands sovereignty and states as juridical concepts nor considers states systems to be historically contingent constructions. By ‘state’ Lord Lothian means, roughly, polity and by ‘sovereignty’ statehood (Kerr Reference Kerr1935, 8ff.). Furthermore, like Waltz, he sees anarchy and government as binary terms that exhaust the range of political possibilities (Kerr Reference Kerr1935, 40–42).

Lord Lothian, however, in sharp contrast to contemporary IR, emphasizes the connection of anarchy with war, lawlessness, and disorder (Kerr Reference Kerr1935, 8, 10, 11, 18, 23, 24, 26, 34–35, 37–38, 41, 48–49). The term, in fact, seems chosen precisely for its negative connotations. For Lord Lothian anarchy arises from the absence of international government but means avertible violent disorder.

The rise of a discourse of anarchy

‘Anarchy,’ of course, did not spring, full-grown, from the head of Waltz in 1979. Important precursors in my sample include Martin Wight’s Power Politics (1946), Waltz’s Man, the State and War (Reference Waltz1959), Herbert Butterfield and Wight’s edited volume Diplomatic Investigations (Reference Butterfield and Wight1966), and, at the very end of the period, Robert Jervis’ Perception and Misperception in International Politics (Reference Jervis1976) and Hedley Bull’s The Anarchical Society (Reference Bull1977).

These precursors point to the sources of contemporary IR’s discourse of anarchy: Waltz, social-scientific rationalism, and the English School. What follows tells (only) the American side of the story, partly for reasons of space but also because of the rapid embrace and continuing predominance of a particular discourse of anarchy in American IR.

Waltz’s role was decisive. Man, the State, and War laid the foundation for placing ‘anarchy’ at the heart of structural theory. His 1975 Handbook article which was well known at the time, outlined the argument of (and created considerable anticipation for) Theory of International Politics – the impact of which would be hard to overestimate.

Three elements seem to me to go a long way in explaining American IR’s embrace of Waltz. He endorsed a vision of social-scientific theory that was in the early stages of establishing its hegemony in the mainstream of the American discipline. (The first chapter of Theory of International Politics lays out his conception of theory. A later essay is pointedly titled ‘Realist Thought and Neo-Realist Theory’ (Waltz Reference Waltz1990).) Waltz aspired to general theory; theory of international politics (in general). Furthermore – and I think decisively – he employed anarchy at the heart of a seemingly elegant and powerful substantive theory (structural realism) that appeared to explain some important features of international systems (states in anarchy balance and pursue relative gains). That this theory breathed new life into realism and systems approaches probably was also significant.

Rational choice analysis more or less simultaneously picked up on anarchy,Footnote 9 especially in the wake of Robert Axelrod’s work on the prisoner’s dilemma (Reference Axelrod1981, Reference Axelrod1984, cf. Gowa Reference Gowa1986). The October 1985 Special Issue of World Politics, published in 1986 as Cooperation Under Anarchy (Oye Reference Oye1986), placed the fusion of anarchy and rationalism at the heart of the American discipline.Footnote 10 It also can be seen to mark the adoption by neo-liberal institutionalism (the other leading substantive research program of the era) of the Waltzian account of the anarchic structure of international relations.Footnote 11 The publication in 1986 of Neorealism and Its Critics (Keohane Reference Keohane1986) signaled a reorientation of American IR Theory around a Waltzian discourse of anarchy.

The spread of anarchy was also facilitated by the fact that Waltz presented it not as a substantive assumption of neorealism but as an analytically neutral demarcation criterion. ‘Anarchy’ quickly replaced ‘politics among nations’ as the defining feature of international relations – and was almost unthinkingly accepted as the structural ordering principle of international systems.

We can chart these changes in the spread of the language of ‘the effects of anarchy.’ A Google Scholar search for ‘effects of anarchy’ or ‘effects of international anarchy’ and ‘international relations’ yields only three insignificant results from 1900 to 1974.Footnote 12 There is one result for 1975–79: Jervis’s influential article ‘Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma’ (Reference Jervis1978, 173).Footnote 13 In the 1980s, ‘effects of (international) anarchy’ appears in seven works, including major articles by John Ruggie (Reference Ruggie1983, 284), Harrison Wagner (Reference Wagner1983, 385), Michael Doyle (Reference Doyle1983, 232), and Joseph Grieco (Reference Grieco1988, 502).Footnote 14 In the 1990s, however, there were almost 100 results; almost 250 in the 2000s; and more than 200 for 2010–15.

Many early constructivists, being focused on other issues, left Waltz’s anarchy-centric conception of international relations unchallenged even as they rejected his neorealist account of the effects of anarchy. For example, Friedrich Kratochwil, whose Rules, Norms, and Decisions was a major early constructivist work, limits his criticism to the idea that anarchy implies the absence of norms (Reference Kratochwil1989, Ch. 2). Even Alexander Wendt’s classic 1992 article ‘Anarchy is What States Make of It,’ while emphasizing the variety of types of anarchy, leaves anarchy’s central place untouched.Footnote 15

By the mid-1990s, anarchy had become ‘naturalized’ across much of the discipline; treated as a taken-for-granted foundational assumption. Neorealism and neoliberalism, the leading research programs of the era, even incorporated anarchy into their ‘hard core’ that no contrary evidence or argument can be permitted to challenge (Elman and Elman Reference Elman and Elman2003, x, 19, 25-27, 61-62, 73, 75, 80).Footnote 16

Words and concepts

One might argue that I have focused on the word ‘anarchy’ but ignored ‘the concept.’ I am suspicious of the underlying account of the relationship between words and concepts, which seems to suggest that anarchy is an ‘objective’ ‘thing’ ‘out there’ to which a variety of labels can be more or less arbitrarily attached.Footnote 17 Nonetheless, this argument merits attention. (Readers convinced by the argument above, however, might want to skip to the subsection A discourse of sovereignty (not anarchy).)

Searching (electronically) for the concept of anarchy

We can begin with a modified version of the search strategy used above. In my pre-1979 books for which electronic full text is available,Footnote 18 I searched for ‘absence’ and ‘government,’ separately (to capture references to lack of government that did not use the word ‘absence’). To avoid an overly narrow focus on the word ‘government,’ I also searched for ‘central authority’ and ‘higher authority.’ Based on my reading of early works that did refer to anarchy, I looked as well for ‘sovereign,’ ‘sovereignty,’ and ‘state.’ Finally, on hunches, I searched for ‘state of nature,’ ‘lawless,’ and ‘lawlessness.’

This procedure, for all its limitations, should reveal any substantial discourse of anarchy. The broad sweep of these searches, though, makes simple counts of little interest. I can thus report only my qualitative assessment of the relevant results.

In books that do not make significant use of ‘anarchy,’ searches for absence, government, and central or higher authority produced only scattered references with uses even close to those of contemporary IR (see, e.g., Lawrence Reference Lawrence1898 [1895], 159; Leacock Reference Leacock1906, 103, 104). Conversely, books that do make significant reference to anarchy produced numerous hits (e.g., Spykman Reference Spykman1942, 16, 18, 446; Gulick Reference Gulick1943, 6, 12; Wight Reference Wight1978 [1946], 101, 105, 184; Waltz Reference Waltz1959, 5, 11, 35, 96, 188; Bull Reference Bull1977, 44, 45, 46, 48, 49, 57, 59, 62, 69, 110, 125, 126, 129, 182). This strongly suggests that the concept of anarchy was not regularly referenced independent of the word.

Arguments for the necessity or possibility of international government were fairly common.Footnote 19 This, however, is no more evidence of a discourse of anarchy than talk about the possibility or desirability of peace is a discourse of war. Such arguments treat anarchy not as defining international relations but as a contingent and alterable feature of some international systems. Moreover, they focus not on the absence of government but on the possibilities of establishing its presence.

Furthermore, several authors argue that twentieth century international relations is characterized by the presence of international government (Trueblood Reference Trueblood1899, 138, 142; Hobson Reference Hobson1915; Lippmann Reference Lippmann1915, 130–31, 145; Woolf Reference Woolf1916, 141–43, 149, 153–55, 267, 312; Smuts Reference Smuts1918; Potter Reference Potter1922, 12–14, 23, 269, 369, 381; Mitrany Reference Mitrany1933). As Schuman puts it, ‘the net result of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries has been the emergence and development of habits and institutions of cooperation between States to which it is now customary to apply the terms “international organization” or “international government”’ (Reference Schuman1933, 231). A significant portion of the discipline – including realists like Schuman – denied the ‘fact’ of anarchy.Footnote 20

The other searches likewise provided no significant evidence of a concept of anarchy expressed in other terms. (I was surprised to find almost no references to absence of a sovereign. Moreover, ‘state of nature,’ which is used with moderate frequency in discussions of origins and theories of the state, rarely has the sense that international anarchy does in contemporary IR.Footnote 21 ) As it seems highly unlikely that other words were used but not my search terms, I conclude that anarchy was not an analytically central concept in pre-Waltzian IR.

An early political discourse of anarchy?

A critical examination of Schmidt’s The Political Discourse of Anarchy, a leading example of the argument of continuity, suggests the same conclusion. Schmidt insists that ‘the concept of anarchy employed in this book is not an externally or retrospectively imposed theme … but instead represents an indigenous construct around which discussions about the subject matter of international relations have continuously evolved’ (Reference Schmidt1998, 1–2, cf. 16). However, in the three principal chapters, which cover more than a hundred pages, Schmidt quotes only eight passages from authors other than Dickinson that employ the language of anarchy (Reference Schmidt1998, 94, 113, 172, 182, 186, 204, 208, 210). He thus must be implicitly advancing a concept-without-the-word argument.

Characteristic of Schmidt’s account are his claims that Stephen ‘Leacock articulated the theoretical limits of the concept of sovereignty for examining the external relations of states and, in doing so, outlined one of the main props of the political discourse of anarchy’ and that Westel Woodbury Willoughby’s ‘reference to the international milieu as being analogous to a state of nature is a major component of the political discourse of anarchy’ (Schmidt Reference Schmidt1998, 84, 90). As Schmidt’s further discussions indicate, though, Leacock and Willoughby actually address sovereignty, independence, authority, the state, and the state of nature – which have common meanings and uses entirely independent of anarchy. However, Schmidt presents no evidence that Leacock and Willoughby understood these notions in terms of anarchy. And, a look at their books indicates that they did not.Footnote 22

Willoughby examines the nature of the state, addressing international relations only briefly, near the end of the book (Reference Willoughby1896, 404–06ff.).Footnote 23 Moreover, his discussion does not even note the absence of international government (or any other marker of ‘anarchy’). Quite the contrary, Willoughby begins by claiming that ‘the most obvious fact is the increasing inter-nationality of interests that attends advancing civilization.’ He then goes on to argue that ‘the principles of international conduct that are generally accepted by all civilized peoples already constitute a very considerable body of procedure’ and ‘in many cases common administrative procedures have been established’ (Reference Willoughby1896, 404).

Leacock does devote a chapter to ‘Relation [sic] of States to One Another.’ It begins by noting that ‘theoretical isolation is the prime condition of [a state’s] existence as a state’ and that ‘viewed in a purely theoretical light, every state is an absolutely independent unit. Its sovereignty is unlimited, and it renders political obedience to no outside authority’ (Leacock Reference Leacock1906, 89). Immediately, though, Leacock goes on to argue that ‘it is nevertheless the case that in actual fact different states stand in close contact with one another in a variety of ways … [that] bring separate states into permanent relations demanding some sort of regulation’ and that ‘the action of modern states shows an increasing tendency to conform to a generally recognized usage’ (Reference Leacock1906, 89). Moreover, Leacock presents Westphalia as putting an end to ‘the anarchy of the state of nature’ to which ‘the savagery of the wars of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries’ had reduced Europe (Reference Leacock1906, 93).

For both Leacock and Willoughby the absence of an international government serves as a background condition that sets a context for analyses that focus on the presence of international governance. A discourse of anarchy is Schmidt’s anachronistic imposition.

A discourse of sovereignty (not anarchy)

Schmidt does demonstrate that ‘the most important theme that structured the early study of political science can be termed the theoretical discourse of the state’ and that ‘of all the issues that the theoretical discourse of the state encompassed, none was more weighty than the concept of sovereignty’ (Reference Schmidt1998, 44, emphasis in orginal, 30). His further argument, though, that ‘since state sovereignty is the constitutive principle of international anarchy,Footnote 24 the theoretical discourse of the state was also tacitly laying the groundwork for the political discourse of anarchy’ (Reference Schmidt1998, 45) both misrepresents early IR and elides important differences between anarchy and sovereignty.

As we saw above, several early scholars did closely associate sovereignty with anarchy (Hill Reference Hill1911, 15, cf. 140; Fenwick Reference Fenwick1934, 47).Footnote 25 Others, though, saw sovereignty as ending anarchy, making ‘anarchic systems’ and ‘systems of sovereign states’ opposites. Both ancient (Walsh Reference Walsh1922, 57; Hodges Reference Hodges1931, 57 [sic]) and medieval (Potter Reference Potter1922, 40, 457; Reference Potter1929, xiii, 25; Potter and West Reference Potter and West1927, 4; Hodges Reference Hodges1931, 48; Russell Reference Russell1936, 90; Schuman Reference Schuman1933, 39; Wright Reference Wright1964 [1942], 180; Herz Reference Herz1959, 43–44, cf. Follett Reference Follett1920, 269) international relations, in contrast to modern international relations, are presented as anarchic. T. J. Lawrence and Charles Fenwick, in addition to Leacock, see the Peace of Westphalia putting an end to (rather than codifying) anarchy (Lawrence Reference Lawrence1898 [1895], 35; Fenwick Reference Fenwick1934, 49, cf. Earle et al. Reference Earle, Craig and Gilbert1943, 33). Wright sees the anarchy of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries replaced by state sovereignty in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries (Reference Wright1964 [1942], 191–92). John Herz opposes sovereignty, which provides ‘agreed upon standards and rules,’ to ‘real “anarchy”’ (Reference Herz1959, 59–60). Schuman fears that ‘Fascist nationalism … would return with a vengeance to the conditions of international anarchy’ (Reference Schuman1933, 293) by eliminating the constraints and protections of sovereign statehood. Moreover, the substantial majority of my pre-1979 authors, it must be remembered, offer no evidence that they saw any analytically significant connection between anarchy and sovereignty.

Schmidt replaces a particular account in terms of sovereignty – and in which there was no consensus on the relation between sovereignty and anarchy – with a general and discipline-wide account in terms of anarchy. However, as Schmidt (rightly) notes, ‘the concept of anarchy is more a function of internal disciplinary debate than a self-referential empirical fact of the external world’ (Reference Schmidt1998, 231). How we refer to ‘things’ like the absence of an international government – the terms of discourse – matter, sometimes decisively. And, the terms in early IR were sovereignty and the state, not anarchy.

Finally, to the extent that anarchy is a consequence of sovereignty, it is neither a defining feature of international relations nor of any real analytic significance. (Any ‘effects of anarchy’ are reducible to effects of sovereignty.) The discourse of sovereignty thus further explains the absence of an early discourse of anarchy.

Part two: the false promise of anarchy

So what? Disciplinary history may be interesting. Certainly, though, the crucial question is whether IR’s turn to anarchy has been analytically fruitful.

I argue that it has not.

The transformation of American IR involved much more than introducing the word ‘anarchy’ to refer to the absence of an international government. Anarchy became a demarcation criterion, a master explanatory variable, and the structural ordering principle of international systems. Contemporary (American) IR claims that anarchy both identifies and structures international systems and explains some fundamental features of their functioning. The following three sections challenge these claims.

Defining anarchy

Most in IR today, I suspect, would agree with David Lake that ‘scholars of international relations do not differ in their conception of anarchy’ (Reference Lake2009, 2). This is suggested by the fact that in many (perhaps even most) uses, the term is not defined or glossed,Footnote 26 its sense being taken to be obvious. In fact, however, there is deep definitional disarray, both in Waltz and in the discipline generally.

Waltz, government, and hierarchy

Waltz, in the first paragraph of the subsection on ‘Ordering Principles’ in Chapter 5 (Political Structures) of Theory of International Politics, writes: ‘Domestic political structures have governmental institutions and offices as their concrete counterparts. International politics, in contrast, has been called “politics in the absence of government”’ (Reference Waltz1979, 88). He then asks ‘if international politics is “politics in the absence of government,” what are we in the presence of?’ (Reference Waltz1979, 89). The answer, of course, is anarchy.

In the remainder of the chapter, however, Waltz opposes anarchy not to government but to hierarchy (Reference Waltz1979, 93, 97, 100, 101). Similarly, in Chapter 6 (Anarchic Orders and Balances of Power) he begins by speaking of ‘anarchy, or the absence of government’ and ‘the distinction between anarchy and government’ (Reference Waltz1979, 102, 103). After that, though, Waltz contrasts anarchy to hierarchy nearly a dozen times (Reference Waltz1979, 104, 113, 114 [twice], 115 [five times], 116 [twice]). Absence of government makes only one additional appearance (Waltz Reference Waltz1979, 114) – at the beginning of the subsection on ‘Anarchy and Hierarchy.’

The obvious problem – although a problem that is widely overlooked – is that hierarchy and government are very different things. (For example, government is only one possible source or form of hierarchy.) All international systems may lack government. Most, however, have hierarchy (e.g., Hobson and Sharman Reference Hobson and Sharman2005; Donnelly Reference Donnelly2006; Reference Donnelly2009, 55–71; Reference Donnelly2012, 622–23; Lake Reference Lake2009; Hobson Reference Hobson2014), in the sense of a stratified system of differentiated social positions arranged ‘in relations of super – and subordination’ (Waltz Reference Waltz1979, 88). For example, great power states systems are defined by the formal hierarchical superiority of states over nonstate actors and the (at least informal) rights, liberties, and responsibilities of great powers.

Waltz was an extraordinarily careful writer, with a strong aspiration to (and a considerable reputation for) analytical rigor. The explanation for this systematic conceptual slippage, I want to suggest, is that it is required by the Waltzian project of theory of international politics.Footnote 27

Waltz aimed to reveal ‘a small number of big and important things’ (1986, 329) about international systems. To do so on the basis of anarchy, anarchy must be both a demarcation criterion (allowing him to speak about international systems in general) and a major explanatory variable (allowing him to say some big and important things). Any particular definition, however, can fulfill (at most) one of these roles.

Anarchy plausibly demarcates international relations only if defined as absence of a government (or a comparable institution). This, however, has few if any interesting implications. (For example, a system without a government may or may not have higher authority, rules, or enforcement and may or may not generate self-help balancing and the pursuit of relative gains.) Conversely, although various other absences have analytical bite – for example, systems without hierarchy do have very particular characters – they comprise only a subset of international systems. Waltz seems to have been deceived by the word ‘anarchy’ into believing that he could have it both ways.

In criticizing other arguments, Waltz complains that ‘anarchy is taken to mean not just the absence of government but also the presence of disorder and chaos’ (Reference Waltz1979, 114). He, however, takes anarchy to mean not just the absence of government but also as the absence of hierarchy. And by failing to appreciate that absence of government and absence of hierarchy identify very different sets of ‘anarchic’ systems, Waltz illegitimately extends substantive conclusions about systems without hierarchy, which are rare, to systems without government (i.e., international systems in general).Footnote 28 This conceptual and analytical blunder, it seems to me, would be inconceivable were it not obscured by ‘anarchy.’

Waltz’s account, it is important to emphasize, is not an ‘ideal type’ in the Weberian sense of an analyst-created model that may (or may not) be more or less closely approximated in the world. Waltz claims not that some international systems resemble this model. (Anarchy thus understood would be a feature of a subset of international systems, not international systems in general – which Waltz insists is his referent.) He really does argue that, as a first approximation, (nearly all) international systems do lack not only government but also hierarchy.

This, however, is not even close to true – as Waltz himself acknowledges. ‘Inequality is what much of politics is about’ and ‘internationally, inequality is more nearly the whole of the political story’ (Waltz Reference Waltz1979, 142. 143). ‘The inequality of nations is … the dominant political fact of international life’ (Waltz Reference Waltz1979, 144). I can think of no more striking example of the unfortunate impact of anarchy on contemporary IR. The core concept of the discipline has been constructed in such a way that it not merely ignores but denies the existence of what its leading proponent calls the dominant political fact of international life.

Anarchy over ‘anarchy’

Waltz, however, is just the tip of the iceberg of conflicting definitions. Appendix 5, available online,Footnote 29 identifies 20 definitions of anarchy, each documented by five citations (most from the past two decades).

Most of these definitions, which focus on the absence of various types and sources of authority, differ from many others only in minor ways. As a set, though, they cover a very wide range of senses. They fall into three broad groups that, with a bit of mnemonic license, I label absence of a ruler, absence of rule, and absence of rules.

Absence-of-a-ruler definitions identify an authoritative institution or actor that is missing in international systems. Standard examples are a central, higher, common, or overarching authority, an enforcer (of rules or agreements), and a sovereign.Footnote 30 Absence of a government also falls here.

Absence-of-rule definitions identify a missing function or kind of authority. Common examples are enforcement and higher, overarching, central, common, superior, and superordinate authority.

Absence of an institution (a ruler), however, does not entail the absence of ‘rule;’ that is, the absence of either a function characteristically performed or a type of authority characteristically held by that institution. For example, government is but one possible source of any of these kinds of authority and only one mechanism to provide enforcement.Footnote 31

Finally, anarchy is also regularly defined as the absence of ‘rules;’ of authority simpliciter. For example, Lake claims that ‘the core assumption of the discipline of international relations is that the international system is anarchic or devoid of authority’ (Lake Reference Lake2009, ix). Stephen Krasner contends that ‘the defining characteristic of international politics is anarchy, the absence of authority’ (Reference Krasner1992, 48).Footnote 32 Waltz’s absence of hierarchy also falls here.Footnote 33

These are not relatively minor differences of detail (on the level of, e.g., the fact that higher or superior authority need be neither supreme (or sovereign) nor centralized). Absence of an authority of a particular type (a ruler), absence of a particular type of authority (rule), and absence of all authority (rules) – like absence of government and absence of hierarchy – are fundamentally different notions. (Different concepts are expressed by the same word.)

Furthermore, as we move from a ruler to rule to rules, the scope of ‘anarchy’ constricts, dramatically. All international systems lack a government. Few, if any, lack (any/all) authority. Moreover, neither absence of rule nor absence of rules provides a plausible demarcation criterion.

This multiplicity of definitions seems to be driven by the desire, shared with Waltz, of using anarchy both to define the discipline and serve as a major explanatory variable – which is possible only by switching between absence of a ruler and absence of rule or rules. In any case, all of these definitions are standard in contemporary IR. The differences between them are regularly elided or ignored. And, it is distressingly common to generalize claims that rely (explicitly or implicitly) on the absence rule or rules to ‘international relations’ defined by the absence of a government.Footnote 34 In addition, although this problem has been well known for decadesFootnote 35 it persists, largely unaddressed (as Appendix 5 illustrates). The ‘naturalization’ of anarchy – its unthinking acceptance as an obvious and essential feature of international relationsFootnote 36 – has allowed us to blithely ignore the confusion at the conceptual core of the discipline.

We should also note that this proliferation of definitions – in particular, adding the ‘thick’ senses of absence of rule and rules to the ‘thin’ sense of absence of a ruler – is substantively biased toward ‘realist’ accounts (which minimize the international significance of rule and rules). Moreover, despite protestations that disorder, lawlessness, and violence are not what ‘anarchy’ means in IR – if that is true, why don’t we just talk about the absence of an international government, a much clearer and more precise notion? – these ordinary language connotations are almost inescapable. As Inis Claude puts it ‘anarchy is a symbol of peril – the peril of uncontrollable disorder’ (Reference Claude1962, 212).Footnote 37

Anarchy has no effects

All of this might still be tolerable if anarchy in some sense(s) had more or less determinate effects in most international systems. In the 1980s it seemed that it did. Rationalist modeling, however, soon demonstrated that anarchy has no effects.Footnote 38

Formal analysis revealed that rational actors in a world without government do not necessarily pursue relative gains – and that even those that do often rationally cooperate (e.g., Powell Reference Powell1991, Reference Powell1993; Snidal Reference Snidal1991a, b). Informally, Wendt (Reference Wendt1992) showed that self-help balancing and the pursuit of relative gains are not effects of anarchy (absence of government) but of a particular type of international system that happens to be anarchic. By the mid-1990s it was clear, as Robert Powell (Reference Powell1994, 314) put it, that ‘what have often been taken to be the implications of anarchy do not really follow from the assumption of anarchy. Rather, these implications result from other implicit and unarticulated assumptions about the states’ strategic environment’.Footnote 39

If anarchy means absence of a government – the only sense in which it applies across the whole of international relations – it simply is not true that ‘self-help is necessarily the principle of action in an anarchic order’ (Waltz Reference Waltz1979, 111, cf. Mares Reference Mares1988, 456; Walt Reference Walt2002, 135; Copeland Reference Copeland2006 [2000], 9); that ‘little can be done to ameliorate the security dilemma as long as states operate in anarchy’ (Mearsheimer Reference Mearsheimer2001, 36, cf. Schweller and Wohlforth Reference Schweller and Wohlforth2002, 72); or that ‘the systemic imperatives of anarchy require states to view their gains and losses in relative, not absolute, terms’ (Copeland Reference Copeland2003, 434–35). Such claims can be charitably dismissed as rhetorical exaggerations. It remains standard, though, to identify such ‘effects of anarchy’ but to acknowledge that outcomes may be altered by ‘intervening variables.’

Anarchy, in this reading, pushes states in certain directions. The effects of anarchy are universal. Outcomes, however, vary depending on anarchy’s relative causal efficacy. As Waltz puts it, the predictions of a structural theory are ‘indeterminate,’ in the sense that ‘the outcome is indeterminate’ (Reference Waltz1979, 124, 134).

Determinate effects can be deduced, though, only by adding something to the absence of a government. The purported ‘effects of anarchy’ thus actually are effects of (anarchy and) something else. And those effects vary, considerably, with the ‘something else’ in question.Footnote 40 Similarly, if ‘anarchy’ means absence of rule or rules, that additional absence, not absence of a government (a ruler), does the explanatory work.

Anarchy understood as a general feature of international relations is not an independent variable with uniform effects (that may or may not be mitigated or overcome). It is an interactive and contextual variable associated with multiple equilibria. The effects of anarchy, not just its outcomes, vary – often dramatically.

The Waltzian project of employing anarchy as a master explanatory variable has failed. Anarchy provides no significant analytical payoff for the discipline as a whole.Footnote 41 Therefore, there is no good reason to give a prominent place to a technical term of art that not only is readily subject to misunderstanding but is regularly and systematically used in shifting (and substantively biased) senses.

Anarchy and structure

Even Waltz’s critics usually accept that anarchy structures international systems. It does not.

Anarchy is not the ordering principle of international systems. Absence of an international government (or a comparable institution) is not an ordering principle. (It simply indicates one way in which the system is not ordered.) Absence of hierarchy may be an ordering principle. It is not, however, the ordering principle of international systems. (Most international systems are hierarchical.) And the other absences noted above all run up against one or the other of these fatal problems.

The Waltzian account confuses demarcation and structure. Consider a biological analogy. Mammals can be demarcated from other vertebrates as milk-producing animals with hair, three bones in the middle ear, a neocortex, and a lower jaw made of a single bone. These features, however, do not define the structure of mammals. That A differs structurally from B by c does not make c the structure of A. Demarcation criteria and structural ‘ordering principles’ are very different things.

Equally problematic is the idea that all international systems have a single ordering principle; that they are all structured (arranged) in fundamentally the same way. This is no more true of international systems than national political systems, societies, or economies. Once we stop pretending that the absence of a government structures (arranges or orders rather than defines) international systems, their diverse structures become evident.Footnote 42

Even the idea that each international system has a single ordering principle reflects little more than aesthetic prejudice. There was no single ordering principle in, for example, the Mediterranean system in the third and second centuries bce or the European system of the thirteenth and fourteenth (or the sixteenth and early seventeenth) centuries – or in today’s globalizing world. Multidimensional, ‘hybrid,’ and sui generis systems are normal features of international relations.

Waltz, it seems to me, was right to try to specify a small number of elements that characteristically structure international systems. Anarchy, however, is woefully inadequate to that task.Footnote 43

An anarchy-centric conception of structure focuses attention on something that tells us nothing about how international systems are structured. And in its Waltzian form, ‘anarchy’ denies the reality of vital features that actually do structure/arrange international systems. For example,

  • Anarchy understood as the absence of hierarchy denies the existence of stratification, which in fact is central to the structure of most international systems.

  • Waltz claims that because international systems are anarchic they lack functional differentiation (Reference Waltz1979, 97). In fact, however, states and nonstate actors have different functions, rights, and obligations in states systems. And Waltz himself devotes a chapter of Theory of International Politics to ‘The Management of International Affairs,’ addressing the ‘special responsibilities’ of great powers (Reference Waltz1979, 198) and arguing that ‘neither the United States nor the Soviet Union can behave as “ordinary” states because that is not what they are’ (Reference Waltz1979, 199).

  • Neither is it true that ‘in a system without central governance … there are no effective laws and institutions to direct and constrain’ actors (Waltz Reference Waltz1999, 698). Just as actors are ‘differently placed by their power and differences in placement help to explain both their behavior and their fates’ (Waltz Reference Waltz1990, 31), they are differently placed and shaped by their authority, status, and roles, by the rules that govern them, and by the institutions and practices in which they participate.Footnote 44

The Waltzian construction of anarchy leaves us without a vocabulary or conceptual framework to even identify the ways in which any international system is actually arranged (structured) – let alone explore the ways in which the differing arrangements of the parts of different types of international systems have differing consequences for the character of international societies and the behavior of their members.

Waltz’s account of structure, we should note, cannot be defended as making admittedly inaccurate assumptions that provide predictive leverage. A structural explanation claims that a system is arranged in a certain way and that that arrangement explains the phenomena in question. Some simplification is, of course, necessary. Structural models, however, must be fundamentally accurate – or they are analogical or metaphorical, rather than explanatory in a stronger sense of that term. Moreover, the divergence between Waltzian anarchic international orders and the actual structure of international systems is so extreme that even an analogical argument is highly implausible.

Conclusion: towards a post-Waltzian IR

The arguments above, it seems to me, suggest not only the possibility but the desirability of a post-Waltzian IR in which anarchy is, at the very least, decentered. I introduce that suggestion, though, by stepping back to elucidate the claim that anarchy is a constructed concept. (In the available space I can state (but not defend) my understanding, in order to clarify what would have to be debated in order to develop a ‘deeper’ argument for or against my account.)

Anarchy as a constructed concept

All concepts are constructed. About that there is little disagreement in contemporary philosophy of science. The central issue of genuine controversy, it seems to me, is the mix between analytical practices and the resistance of the world in shaping any particular concept.

To what extent is ‘anarchy’ imposed on us by the world? To what extent could we just as well construct IR and its subject matter in some (but not just any) other way(s)? Obviously, I see anarchy as a contingent construction – as illustrated by the fact that for two-thirds of the history of academic IR, realists and nonrealists alike successfully practiced their craft without central reference to anarchy.

But isn’t the absence of an international government a ‘fact’ that IR simply must comprehend? Let us grant that it is.Footnote 45 ‘Anarchy,’ however, is only one of many possible ways – or, in contemporary IR, a fairly wide and disparate set of ways – to do that.

Consider, again, discourses of sovereignty and anarchy. They partially overlap. However, they differ fundamentally not only in reference and meaningFootnote 46 but also in implication and connotation. For example, a discourse of sovereignty neither implies international disorder nor suggests the absence (or even the weakness) of international law, institutions, or authority. And where a discourse of sovereignty recognizes that the absence of international government takes different forms, anarchy, in its contemporary American conception, is a universal feature of international systems that largely specifies their structure (and tells us something of importance about their operation).

Or consider states systems, understood as a type of international society that prioritizes the autonomy of its members and thus radically decentralizes authority. States have many interests that can only be realized through cooperation. Horizontally generated rules and institutions thus are neither a puzzle to be explained nor a mechanism to mitigate the effects of anarchy but an expected result of a particular type of distribution of authority. Moreover, when rules and institutions develop beyond minimal mechanisms of coexistence, the resulting governance structure is, at best, misleadingly described as absence of international government.Footnote 47

To take a final example, consider the (Hobbesian) ‘state of nature’ that contemporary IR often associates with ‘anarchy.’ International systems in fact rarely (if ever) resemble such a formless void. Almost all formally privilege some actors (e.g., states in states systems). Inequalities of power commonly create further qualitative differences (e.g., great powers). And internal processes arrange actors as parts of a system (rather than atoms in a void or mere elements of an aggregate).

Unfortunately, though, Lake seems correct when he suggests that ‘we are drawn by our dominant theories to see the international system as an anarchy, a state of nature’ (Reference Lake2009, 16). Most strikingly, Waltzian anarchy, understood as absence of hierarchy, effectively amounts to such a formless void.Footnote 48

It simply is not true, though, that ‘authoritative rules within hierarchies allow states to escape at least in part the anarchic state of nature in which they would otherwise find themselves’ (Lake Reference Lake2009, 101, emphasis added) or that we should compare particular international arrangements and institutions to ‘the anarchic state of nature they [states] would otherwise inhabit’ (Lake Reference Lake2009, 34, emphasis added, cf. 7, 9, 62, 93). Rarely if ever are polities confronted with the need to escape from, or the possibility of falling into, a state of nature. There is nothing ‘natural’ about the ‘state of nature.’ It is a particular (substantively biased) representation of the absence of government.

‘Anarchy’ is not an analytically neutral ‘thing’ lying ‘out there,’ waiting for us to bang our heads against or otherwise dis-cover and then come to grips with. Rather than something ‘objective’ that can be conceptualized in varying ways, it is a particular (and thus contentious) representation of certain states of the world. As Waltz notes, ‘theoretical notions are defined by the theory in which they appear’ (Reference Waltz1979, 10). ‘Even descriptive terms acquire different meanings as theories change’ (Reference Waltz1979, 12).

Putting anarchy back into the background

The meanings given to anarchy in contemporary IR, I have argued, have impeded understanding the actual structure of real international systems. And nothing of substantive interest has been explained by the absence of an international government (alone).Footnote 49 The Waltzian project of an anarchy-centric IR has proved, at best, a dead end.Footnote 50

Although the pervasive presence of a professional discourse of anarchy makes it unrealistic to imagine ‘anarchy’ soon returning to an ordinary language concept indicating disorder and lawlessness, we may perhaps reasonably aspire to restrict the term to the thinnest and most neutral conception presently employed. I thus propose that ‘anarchy’ be understood (1) to mean (only) absence of ‘a ruler’ (an authoritative governing institution or actor) and (2) to be (only) a demarcation criterion.

Thus understood, anarchy is a background condition. Absence of an international government poses problems.Footnote 51 Nothing more. But nothing less either. The particular problems that anarchy poses limit the range of possible solutions. That range, though, is considerable.

Abandoning anarchy, however, does not suggest jumping on the hierarchy bandwagon. The denial of international hierarchy is indeed a particularly perverse consequence of the Waltzian construction of anarchy. Giving hierarchy its due place thus is an important remedial project. But hierarchy – pace John Hobson’s recent suggestion (Reference Hobson2014) – is not IR’s core concept. Hierarchy is at least as characteristic of national as international systems. Moreover, the simple fact that international systems are hierarchic ought to be obvious and uninteresting to anyone who has not undergone professional training in academic IR.

In particular, hierarchy provides almost as poor an account of the structure of international (and national) systems as anarchy. It simply states that the pattern of stratification is not flat. It does not tell us how a system is stratified – or anything else about the (many and varied) ways in which international systems are structured.

A focus on hierarchy, like a focus on anarchy, gives in to the siren song of simple universal patterns; of general, transhistorical ‘theory of international politics.’Footnote 52 Even Economics, though, does not claim to have something of substantive interest to say about all economies at all times. We need more modest – and more realistic – expectations of international theory in general and structural theory in particular.

We need an IR that strives to comprehend, in methodologically and theoretically pluralistic ways, the complexity and diversity of international systems; an IR that neither minimizes nor obscures the careful analysis of the varied and typically complex structures of international systems.Footnote 53 If we must use the language of anarchy and hierarchy, our focus should be on the considerable variety of types of hierarchies and anarchies, rather than the ‘facts’ – the simple existence – of anarchy and hierarchy.Footnote 54

The absence of an international government (anarchy) certainly is significant to the character and conduct of international relations. It is not, however, analytically central. Anarchy neither is a structural ordering principle nor has determinate effects. It is best understood, I have argued, as a background condition that differentially constrains and enables the security strategies and policy choices of international actors. As such, we ought to put anarchy back into the background of IR – where it was before Waltz.

Acknowledgements

I thank Raslan Ibrahim and Robert Jervis for their comments on earlier drafts. I also thank the anonymous reviewers and editors of International Theory for three rounds of extremely helpful criticisms and suggestions.

Supplementary Material

For Appendices 1–5, please visit http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1752971915000111.

Footnotes

1 In selecting pre-1979 sources I relied primarily on Schmidt (Reference Schmidt1998), Olson and Onuf (Reference Olson and Onuf1985), and Long and Wilson (Reference Long and Wilson1995). The choice of later works reflects my own judgment.

3 Furthermore, most of the passages in the first edition associate anarchy with disorder and violence (Morgenthau Reference Morgenthau1948, 138, 174, 210, 310, 311, 361, 378, 431).

4 See Appendix 4.A, available online at http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1752971915000111.

5 See Appendix 4.B, available online at http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1752971915000111.

6 ‘The only alternative to anarchy is government’ (Woolf Reference Woolf1916, 312). ‘The power which prevents anarchy in intra-group relations encourages anarchy in intergroup relations’ (Niebuhr Reference Niebuhr1932, 16). See also Lawrence Reference Lawrence1898 [1895], 19; Hobson Reference Hobson1902, 174; Mackinder Reference Mackinder1919, 6; Hicks Reference Hicks1920, 117; Mowat Reference Mowat1931, 13; Simonds and Emeny Reference Simonds and Emeny1935, 138; Sharp and Kirk Reference Sharp and Kirk1940, 397; Burton Reference Burton1965, 45–46; Osgood and Tucker Reference Osgood and Tucker1967, 13.

7 In addition to the works cited in the remainder of this paragraph, see Willoughby (Reference Willoughby1896, 196), Leacock (Reference Leacock1906, 89, 95), Mahan (Reference Mahan1912, 2), Woolf (Reference Woolf1916, 125), Politis (Reference Politis1926, 6), Mitrany (Reference Mitrany1933, 165), Simonds and Emeny (Reference Simonds and Emeny1935, 28, 563), and Hinsley (Reference Hinsley1963, 326, 327). See also the sections Anarchy, states systems, and international relations and Words and concepts.

8 Even the apparently more general The International Anarchy is largely an expanded version of The European Anarchy. It is subtitled 1904–1914 and identifies ‘the special subject of this book’ as ‘the series of events and situations which led up to the Great War’ (Dickinson Reference Dickinson1926, 3).

9 Taylor (Reference Taylor1976) was influential, explicitly linking anarchy to the question of coopearation (although not in an international context). Snyder and Diesing (Reference Snyder and Diesing1977) was an important early application of game theory to IR. (It is not included in my sample because I cannot find an electronic edition.) See also Young (Reference Young1978).

10 Earlier ‘scientific’ IR, I would suggest, did not adopt anarchy because it is not operationalizable in any way that leads to substantively interesting conclusions. Moreover, if anarchy really is a feature of all international systems, it is correlated with any pattern that one finds in any set of international systems – making it an inapprorpiate explanatory variable for correlational methodologies. Only in a rationalist nomological-deductive conception of social science does anarchy become an attractive master explanatory variable.

11 For example, Keohane and Nye (Reference Keohane and Nye1987, 745) explicitly adopt ‘the neorealist sense’ of structure. A decade earlier, though, in the book that this article updates (Keohane and Nye, Reference Keohane and Nye1977), they do not use ‘anarchy’ or ‘anarchic.’

12 Two are works in IR: Duggan (Reference Duggan1919, 27) (‘here and there some voice was raised against the almost intolerable effects of anarchy’) and Lijphart (Reference Lijphart1974, 52) (Woodrow Wilson ‘feared the efects of international anarchy even among democracies’). The third is in a history of the growth of the United States.

13 In addition, Jervis’ Perception and Misperception in Internationl Politics is the first book that I can find by an American author other than Waltz that makes central use of ‘anarchy’ in the Waltzian sense (Reference Jervis1976, 20, 62, 63, 67, 68, 75, 76, 83, 273, 340). In private correspondence, Jervis recalls first encountering anarchy through the teaching of Glenn Snyder at Berkeley (who was strongly influenced by Waltz, who had not yet moved to Berkeley).

14 The other references are in Murphy (Reference Murphy1983), Snyder (Reference Snyder1988), and a law review article on Grenada and Realpolitik.

15 There were, of course, exceptions. Ashley (Reference Ashley1988) is perhaps the leading example. See also Onuf (Reference Onuf1989, Ch. 5) and Walker (Reference Walker1993, 33–43, 63–74, 150–52, 172–76).

16 Andrew Moravscik (Reference Moravcsik2003, 190) goes so far as to argue that anarchy is part of the ‘hard core’ of ‘nearly all major IR theories.’

17 Cf. the section Anarchy as a constructed concept.

18 This includes only a little more than a third (52 of 145) of these books, two-thirds of which were published before 1923. (For the books in this subsample, see Appendix 4.C.) I cannot see, though, that any systematic bias is introduced. If anything, one would expect better-known books to be overrepresented. And I know of no argument that usage changed significantly anywhere between 1923 and 1978.

19 In addition to the passages in the following paragraph, see Trueblood (Reference Trueblood1899, 3, 125, 126, 130, 135, 137), Lippmann (Reference Lippmann1915, 129–30, 142–45, 185, 187), Hicks (Reference Hicks1920, 117), and Kerr (Reference Kerr1935).

20 See footnote 31 for a more precise formulation of this point.

21 Raymond Aron (Reference Aron2003 [1966], especially 339) is the principal exception.

22 Each uses ‘anarchy’ or ‘anarchic’ six times, always to indicate disorder (except for two passages in Willoughby that reference anarchism) (Willoughby Reference Willoughby1896, 71, 85, 90, 318, 320, 340; Leacock Reference Leacock1906, 93, 101, 112, 114–15, 289, 374).

23 The word ‘international’ appears less than 30 times in more than 400 pages, usually in reference to international law.

24 Note that this is not the standard Waltzian understanding. (Absence of either international government or hierarchy has many sources in addition to the presence of state/national sovereignty.)

25 See footnote 9 and the section Anarchy, states systems, and international relations.

26 For example, of the 35 articles published in International Organization between 2000 and 2012 that use (international) ‘anarchy,’ only two (Snyder Reference Snyder2002, 7; Donnelly Reference Donnelly2012, 620) define it explicitly. Similarly, only 1 of 29 articles in International Security between 2000 and 2012 (Taliaferro 2000–Reference Taliaferro2001, 128) defines (international) ‘anarchy.’ More broadly, in August 2013 I searched Google Scholar for ‘anarchy’ and ‘international relations’ and then examined the first, eighth, and fifteenth sources on the first seven pages of results. 12 of the 21 works in this sample used ‘anarchy’ with no definition or explication of any sort.

27 Without overstating the point, it seems to me important to highlight the systematic nature of this slippage. Waltz defines international relations in terms of absence of government. He explains international behavior, however, by absence of hierarchy. I am suggesting that this reflects neither conscious dissimulation nor accident but is an unintended consequence of a particular theoretical orientation and project, facilitated by the ambiguity of the word ‘anarchy.’

28 For example, although systems without hierarchy may be ‘horizontal, decentralized, homogeneous, undirected, and mutually adaptive’ (Waltz Reference Waltz1979, 113) this is not true of (all) systems without a government (e.g., great power and hegemonic systems, cf. footnote 44).

30 Citations for these senses – and those in the following paragraphs – are in Appendix 5, available online at http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1752971915000111.

31 We can now more precisely formulate the claim above (at footnote 20) that early-twentieth-century international relations was characterized by international government rather than anarchy. There was government, understood as a function – governance, as we would say today – desipte the absence of a single hierarchical governmental authority (a government). There was rule without a ruler.

32 Cf. Katzenstein et al., Reference Katzenstein, Keohane and Krasner1999, 658; Inoguchi and Bacon Reference Inoguchi and Bacon2001, 5; Hoddie and Hartzell Reference Hoddie and Hartzell2005, 22; Lentner Reference Lentner2006, 103; Holmes Reference Holmes2011, 291; Vucetic Reference Vucetic2011, 29; Polat Reference Polat2012, 1.

33 This sense is also present in early IR where anarchy (understood as the absence of rules) is contrasted to sovereignty (which involves at least rules, and perhaps also rule, even in the absence of a ruler). See the second paragraph of the section ‘A discourse of sovereignty (not anarchy)’ (above).

34 See, for example, the passages in the third paragraph of the next section.

35 For example, Helen Milner’s classic article ‘The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations Theory’ gave considerable attention (Reference Milner1991, 71–74) to the difference between absence of government and absence of authority.

36 For example, an anonymous reader of an earlier draft wrote that ‘anarchy is understood by many as being a system in which states interact within a structure that is defined by rules and institutions that are weak in their behavioral effects.’ The logic would appear to be: international relations is anarchic; this is how international relations typically is structured; therefore, anarchy means this. However, of course, it does not (which is why almost all accounts say it means something else, even when this is the kind of international system intended to be referenced by anarchy).

37 These misleading connotations are further encouraged by analogies to the Hobbesian state of nature (which I criticize in the sixth and seventh paragraphs of the section Anarchy as a constructed concept).

38 The following paragraphs, for reasons of space, often assert (or cite to) claims that ought to be argued.

39 For a particularly spirited refrain, see Wagner (Reference Wagner2007, 16–18, 21–29).

40 For example, simple immediate-return forager societies, composed of equal, functionally undifferentiated, and equally armed individuals and bands that confront each other in the absence of government and hierarchy, are warless societies that neither practice self-help balancing nor pursue relative gains but employ a security strategy that I call binding through sharing (Donnelly Reference Donnelly2012, 610–16).

41 My argument, however, says nothing about structural realism (or any other substantive theory that employs a thick sense of anarchy or supplements absence of a government with other features) – as long as it is understood as a model or theory of a particular type of international system.

42 For illustrations, see Donnelly (Reference Donnelly2006, 153–57; Reference Donnelly2009, 58–71; Reference Donnelly2012, 610–20).

43 In the Waltzian account, anarchy does almost all the work. For example, anarchy (alone) is held to explain self-help balancing, the pursuit of relative gains, and the security dilemma. It is thus surprisingly common to speak not only of the anarchic structure of international relations but of the ‘structure of anarchy’ (e.g., Keohane Reference Keohane1989, 152; Ruggie Reference Ruggie1998, 143, 144, 152; Vasquez, Reference Vasquez1998, 197, 211; Buzan and Waever Reference Buzan and Waever2003, 249; Little Reference Little2007, 175; Reus-Smit and Snidal Reference Reus-Smit and Snidal2009, 695). Cf. Waltz (Reference Waltz1979, 116): ‘two, and only two, types of structures are need to cover societies of all sorts.’ A Google Scholar search in May 2015 for ‘structure of anarchy’ and ‘international relations’ produced more than 200 results since 2000.

44 All of these errors are rooted in falsely generalizing to systems without government features of systems without hierarchy.

45 This, however, is (by itself) not a compelling reason to grant it any analytic (as oppsed to definitional) privilege.

46 For example, systems of sovereign states are ‘anarchic’ in the sense of lacking a government. But so are hegemonic systems, imperial systems, heterarchic systems involving multiple types of actors arranged in multiple ways (as in medieval Europe and many scenarios of globalization), and systems of autonomous polities that are not sovereign (as in Classical Greece or China during the Warring States period).

47 Some readers may suggest that this account is very close to the English School vision of anrachical international societies. I would note that this is how Schuman, Gulick, Wright, Herz, and many others in pre-Waltzian IR understood the ‘facts’ that contemporary IR understands as anarchic international orders.

48 ‘Most realists, including Waltz, use the term anarchy to mean not simply the absence of hierarchical government but the presence of a Hobbesian state of nature’ (Vasquez Reference Vasquez1993, 268).

49 One might imagine that something of substantive interest about international relations in general must be explained by absence of an international government. I honestly, though, cannot think of anything.

50 I have chosen ‘dead end’ carefully. For example, the literature on ‘cooperation under anarchy,’ although often illuminating, is essentially a remedial effort to undo the damage caused by the idea of anarchy as an ordering principle with determinate effects. (Before Waltz, the fact that states cooperate was not thought to merit articles in major journals.) Moreover, if the frame of anarchy is fundamentally mistaken, as I have argued, then the substance (as opposed to the instigation) of the contributions of this literature has come despite (rather than as a result of) the turn to anarchy.

51 In the context of this essay, it is interesting to note that Waltz (Reference Waltz1990, 36) claims that classical realists treat ‘anarchy [a]s a general condition rather than a distinct structure. Anarchy sets the problem that states have to cope with.’

52 A less systematic survey of the books in my sample has convinced me that ‘hierarchy’ was also absent from pre-Waltzian IR. Both sides of the anarchy-hierarchy binary are Waltz’s construction. (He indicates no sources, precursors, or inspirations – and I have been able to find none.) Moreover, each, I am suggesting, has similar analytical shortcomings (because they are mutually co-constituting opposites).

53 Donnelly (Reference Donnelly2012, 622–28) sketches one such account. There are, however, many other potentially productive paths forward.

54 Escaping the anarchy-hierarchy binary would also allow us to treat structural change as no less a theoretical possibility than continuity. (Both anarchy and hierarchy, in the Waltzian construction, are constant, not variable.)

References

Angell, Norman. 1921. The Fruits of Victory: A Sequel to “The Great Illusion”. New York: The Century Co. [12].Google Scholar
Aron, Raymond. 2003 [1966]. Peace and War: A Theory of International Relations. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. [11].Google Scholar
Ashley, Richard K. 1988. “Untying the Sovereign State: A Double Reading of the Anarchy Problematique.” Millennium 17(2):227–262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, Robert. 1981. “The Emergence of Cooperation Among Egoists.” American Political Science Review 75(2):306–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Axelrod, Robert. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Bull, Hedley. 1977. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics. New York: Columbia University Press. [100+].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burton, J. W. 1965. International Relations: A General Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [7].Google Scholar
Butterfield, Herbert, and Wight, Martin. 1966. Diplomatic Investigations: Essays in the Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [31].Google Scholar
Buzan, Barry, and Waever, Ole. 2003. Regions and Powers: The Structure of International Security. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlsnaes, Walter, Risse, Thomas, and Simmons, Beth A., eds. 2002. Handbook of International Relations. London: SAGE Publications. [86].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carlsnaes, Walter, Risse, Thomas, and Simmons, Beth A., eds. 2013. Handbook of International Relations, 2nd ed. London: SAGE Publications. [86].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carr, Edward Hallett 1964 [1946]. The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations, 2d ed. New York: Harper Collins. [2].Google Scholar
Claude, Inis L. 1962. Power and International Relations. New York: Random House. [16].Google Scholar
Copeland, Dale C. 2003. “A Realist Critique of the English School.” Review of International Studies 29(3):427–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copeland, Dale C. 2006 [2000]. “The Constructivist Challenge to Structural Realism: A Review Essay.” In Constructivism and International Relations: Alexander Wendt and His Critics, edited by Stefano Guzzini and Anna Leander, 120. Milton Park, Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
Dickinson, G. Lowes. 1917 [1916]. The European Anarchy. New York: The Macmillan Company. [100+].Google Scholar
Dickinson, G. Lowes. 1920. Causes of International War. London: Swathmore Press. [1].Google Scholar
Dickinson, G. Lowes. 1926. The International Anarchy, 1904–1914. New York: The Century Co. [100+].Google Scholar
Donnelly, Jack. 2006. “Sovereign Inequalities and Hierarchy in Anarchy: American Power and International Society.” European Journal of International Relations 12(2):139–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnelly, Jack. 2009. “Rethinking Political Structures: From ‘Ordering Principles’ to ‘Vertical Differentiation’ – and Beyond.” International Theory 1(1):49–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnelly, Jack. 2012. “The Elements of the Structures of International Systems.” International Organization 66(4):609–643.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, James, and Pfatzgraff, William. 1971. Contending Theories of International Relations: A Comprehensive Survey. Philadelphia: Lippincott.Google Scholar
Dougherty, James, and Pfatzgraff, William. 1981. Contending Theories of International Relations: A Comprehensive Survey, 2nd ed. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Dougherty, James, and Pfatzgraff, William. 1990. Contending Theories of International Relations: A Comprehensive Survey, 3rd ed. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Dougherty, James, and Pfatzgraff, William. 1997. Contending Theories of International Relations: A Comprehensive Survey, 4th ed. New York: Longman.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael W. 1983. “Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign Affairs.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 12(3):205–235.Google Scholar
Duggan, Stephen Pierce, ed. 1919. The League of Nations: The Principle and the Practice. Boston: The Atlantic Monthly Press.Google Scholar
Earle, Edward Mead, Craig, Gordon A., and Gilbert, Felix, eds. 1943. Makers of Modern Strategy: Military Thought from Machiavelli to Hitler. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [3].Google Scholar
Elman, Colin, and Elman, Miriam Fendius, eds. 2003. Progress in International Relations Theory: Appraising the Field. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fenwick, Charles G. 1934. International Law, 2nd ed. New York: D. Appleton-Century Company. [12].Google Scholar
Follett, M. P. 1920. The New State: Group Organization the Solution of Popular Government. New York: Longmans, Green and Co. [11].Google Scholar
Gowa, Joanne. 1986. “Anarchy, Egoism, and Third Images: The Evolution of Cooperation in International Relations.” International Organization 40(1):167–186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenstein, Fred I., and Polsby, Nelson W., eds. 1975. Handbook of Political Science, Volume 8: International Politics. Reading: Addison-Wesley Publishing Company. [11].Google Scholar
Grieco, Joseph M. 1988. “Anarchy and the Limits of Cooperation: A Realist Critique of the Newest Liberal Institutionalism.” International Organization 42(3):485–507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gulick, Edward Vose. 1943. The Balance of Power. Philadelphia: The Pacifist Research Bureau. [8].Google Scholar
Herz, John H. 1959. International Politics in the Atomic Age. New York: Columbia University Press. [11].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hicks, Frederick Charles. 1920. The “New World Order:” International Organization, International Law, International Cooperation. Garden City: Doubleday, Page & Company. [2].Google Scholar
Hill, David Jayne. 1911. World Organization as Affected by the Nature of the Modern State. New York: Columbia University Press. [11].Google Scholar
Hinsley, F. H. 1963. Power and the Pursuit of Peace. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [9].Google Scholar
Hobson, J. A. 1902. Imperialism: A Study. New York: James Pott Company. [2].Google Scholar
Hobson, J. A. 1915. Towards International Government. London: George Allen & Unwin. [0].Google Scholar
Hobson, John M. 2014. “The Twin Self-Delusions of IR: Why ‘Hierarchy’ and Not ‘Anarchy’ is the Core Concept of IR.” Millennium 42(3):557–575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobson, John M., and Sharman, J. C.. 2005. “The Enduring Place of Hierarchy in World Politics: Tracing the Social Logics of Hierarchy and Political Change.” European Journal of International Relations 11(1):63–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoddie, Mathew, and Hartzell, Caroline. 2005. “Signals of Reconciliation: Institution-Building and the Resolution of Civil Wars.” International Studies Review 7(1):21–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hodges, Charles. 1931. The Background of International Relations: Our World Horizons, National and International. New York: John Wiley & Sons. [5].Google Scholar
Holmes, Marcus. 2011. “Something Old, Something New, Something Borrowed: Representations of Anarchy in International Relations Theory.” International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 11(2):279–308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inoguchi, Takashi, and Bacon, Paul. 2001. “The Study of International Relations in Japan: Towards a More International Discipline.” International Relations of the Asia-Pacific 1(1):1–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jervis, Robert. 1976. Perception and Misperception in International Politics. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [10].Google Scholar
Jervis, Robert. 1978. “Cooperation under the Security Dilemma.” World Politics 30(2):167–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaplan, Morton A. 1957. System and Process in International Politics. New York: John Wiley & Sons. [2].Google Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J., Keohane, Robert O., and Krasner, Stephen D.. 1999. “ International Organization and the Study of World Politics.” International Organization 52(4):645–685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennan, George F. 1951. American Diplomacy, 1900–1950. New York: New American Library. [2].Google Scholar
Keohane, Robert O, ed. 1986. Neorealism and Its Critics. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Keohane, Robert O——. 1989. International Institutions and State Power: Essays in International Relations Theory. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Keohane, Robert O., and Nye, Joseph S.. 1977. Power and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition. Boston: Little, Brown. [0].Google Scholar
Keohane, Robert O., and Nye, Joseph S.. 1987. “ Power and Interdependence Revisited.” International Organization 41(4):725–753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kerr, Philip Henry (Marquis of Lothian). 1935. Pacifism is Not Enough, Nor Patriotism Either. Oxford: Clarendon Press. [11].Google Scholar
Kissinger, Henry A. 1957. A World Restored: Metternich, Castlereagh and the Problems of Peace, 1812–22. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. [2].Google Scholar
Krasner, Stephen D. 1992. “Realism, Imperialism, and Democracy: A Response to Gilbert.” Political Theory 20(1):38–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratochwil, Friedrich V. 1989. Rules, Norms, and Decisions: On the Conditions of Practical and Legal Reasoning in International Relations and Domestic Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [27].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lake, David A. 2009. Hierarchy in International Relations. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Lawrence, T. J. 1898 [1895]. The Principles of International Law, 2nd ed. Boston: D. C. Heath & Co. [5].Google Scholar
Leacock, Stephen. 1906. Elements of Political Science. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company. [6].Google Scholar
Lentner, Howard H. 2006. “Hegemony and Power in International Relations.” In Hegemony and Power: Consensus and Coercion in Contemporary Politics, edited by Mark Haugaard and Howard H. Lentner, 89108. Lanham: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Lijphart, Arend. 1974. “The Structure of the Theoretical Revolution in International Relations.” International Studies Quarterly 18(1):41–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lippmann, Walter. 1915. The Stakes of Diplomacy. New York: Henry Holt and Company. [4].Google Scholar
Little, Richard. 2007. The Balance of Power in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, David. 1995. “Conclusion: Inter-War Idealism, Liberal Internationalism, and Contemporary International Theory.” In Thinkers of the Twenty Years’ Crisis: Inter-war Idealism Reassessed, edited by David Long and Peter Wilson, 302328. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Long, David, and Wilson, Peter, eds. 1995. Thinkers of the Twenty Years’ Crisis: Inter-war Idealism Reassessed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackinder, H. J. 1919. Democratic Ideals and Reality: A Study in the Politics of Reconstruction. New York: Henry Holt and Company. [2].Google Scholar
Mahan, A. T. 1912. Armaments and Arbitration or the Place of Force in the International Relations of States. New York: Harper & Brothers. [1].Google Scholar
Mares, David R. 1988. “Middle Powers under Regional Hegemony: To Challenge or Acquiesce in Regional Enforcement.” International Studies Quarterly 32(4):453–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York: Norton. [46].Google Scholar
Mearsheimer, John J. 2006. “Conversations in International Relations: Interview with John J. Mearsheimer (Part II).” International Relations 20(2):231–243.Google Scholar
Miller, Benjamin. 2002. When Opponents Cooperate: Great Power Conflict and Collaboration in World Politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Milner, Helen. 1991. “The Assumption of Anarchy in International Relations Theory: A Critique.” Review of International Studies 17(1):67–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mitrany, David. 1933. The Progress of International Government. New Haven: Yale University Press. [7].Google Scholar
Moravcsik, Andrew. 2003. “Liberal International Relations Theory: A Scientific Assessment.” In Progress in International Relations Theory: Appraising the Field, edited by Colin Elman and Miriam Fendius Elman, 159204. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1946. Scientific Man Versus Power Politics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [1].Google Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1948. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. [10].Google Scholar
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1951. In Defense of the National Interest: A Critical Examination of American Foreign Policy. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. [2].Google Scholar
Mowat, R. B. 1931. International Relations. New York: The Macmillan Company. [4].Google Scholar
Murphy, John F. 1983. The United Nations and the Control of International Violence: A Legal and Political Analysis. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1932. Moral Man and Immoral Society: A Study in Ethics and Politics. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. [16].Google Scholar
Olson, William, and Onuf, Nicholas. 1985. “The Growth of a Discipline: Reviewed.” In International Relations: British and American Perspectives, edited by Steve Smith. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood. 1989. World of Our Making: Rules and Rule in Social Theory and International Relations. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press. [48].Google Scholar
Osgood, Robert E., and Tucker, Robert W.. 1967. Force, Order, and Justice. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. [2].Google Scholar
Osiander, Andreas. 1998. “Reading Early Twentieth-Century IR Theory: Idealism Revisited.” International Studies Quarterly 42:409–432.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oye, Kenneth A, ed. 1986. Cooperation Under Anarchy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [100+].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Polat, Necati. 2012. International Relations, Meaning and Mimesis. Milton Park, Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Politis, Nicolas. 1926. New Aspects of International Law. Washington: Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. [3].Google Scholar
Potter, Pitman B. 1922. An Introduction to the Study of International Organization. New York: The Century Company. [13].Google Scholar
Potter, Pitman B. 1929. This World of Nations: Foundations, Institutions, Practices. New York: The Macmillan Company. [2].Google Scholar
Potter, Pitman B., and West, Roscoe L.. 1927. International Civics: The Community of Nations. New York: The Macmillan Company. [2].Google Scholar
Powell, Robert. 1991. “Absolute and Relative Gains in International Relations Theory.” American Political Science Review 85(4):1303–1320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powell, Robert. 1993. “Guns, Butter, and Anarchy.” American Political Science Review 87(1):115–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powell, Robert. 1994. “Anarchy in International Relations Theory: The Neorealist-Neoliberal Debate.” International Organization 48(2):313–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reus-Smit, Christian, and Snidal, Duncan, eds. 2008. Oxford Handbook of International Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [100+].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reus-Smit, Christian, and Snidal, Duncan. 2009. “Overview of International Relations: Between Utopia and Reality.” In The Oxford Handbook of Political Science, edited by Robert C. Goodin, 337. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ruggie, John Gerard. 1983. “Continuity and Transformation in the World Polity: Toward a Neorealist Synthesis.” World Politics 35(2):261–285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruggie, John Gerard. 1998. Constructing the World Polity: Essays on International Institutionalization. London: Routledge. [33].Google Scholar
Russell, Frank M. 1936. Theories of International Relations. New York: D. Appelton-Century Company. [14].Google Scholar
Schmidt, Brian C. 1998. The Political Discourse of Anarchy: A Disciplinary History of International Relations. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Schuman, Frederick Lewis. 1933. International Politics: An Introduction to the Western State System. New York: McGraw-Hill. [16].Google Scholar
Schweller, Randall L., and Wohlforth, William C.. 2002. “Power Test: Evaluating Realism in Response to the End of the Cold War.” Security Studies 9(3):60–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sharp, Walter R., and Kirk, Grayson L.. 1940. Contemporary International Politics. New York: Farrar & Rinehart. [10].Google Scholar
Simonds, Frank H., and Emeny, Brooks. 1935. The Great Powers and World Politics: International Relations and Economic Nationalism. New York: American Book Company. [14].Google Scholar
Smuts, Jan C. 1918. The League of Nations: A Practical Suggestion. New York: The Nation Press. [2].Google Scholar
Snidal, Duncan. 1991a. “International Cooperation Among Relative Gains Maximizers.” International Studies Quarterly 35(4):387–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snidal, Duncan. 1991b. “Relative Gains and the Pattern of International Cooperation.” American Political Science Review 85(3):701–726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, Glenn H., and Diesing, Paul. 1977. Conflict among Nations: Bargaining, Decision Making, and System Structure in International Crises. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Snyder, Jack. 1988. “Science and Sovietology: Bridging the Methods Gap in Soviet Foreign Policy.” World Politics 40(2):169–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, Jack. 2002. “Anarchy and Culture: Insights from the Anthropology of War.” International Organization 56(1):7–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spykman, Nicholas J. 1942. America’s Strategy in World Politics: The United States and the Balance of Power. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company. [8].Google Scholar
Taliaferro, Jeffrey W. 2000–2001. “Security Seeking Under Anarchy: Defensive Realism Revisited.” International Security 25(3):128–161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Michael. 1976. Anarchy and Cooperation. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Trueblood, Benjamin Franklin. 1899. The Federation of the World. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin and Company. [1].Google Scholar
Vasquez, John A. 1993. The War Puzzle. Cambridge: Cambribge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vasquez, John A. 1998. The Power of Power Politics: From Classical Realism to Neotraditionalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Vucetic, Srdjan. 2011. “Bound to Follow? The Anglosphere and US-Led Coalitions of the Willing, 1950–2001.” European Journal of International Relations 17(1):27–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, R. Harrison. 1983. “The Theory of Games and the Problem of International Cooperation.” American Political Science Review 77(2):330–346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wagner, R. Harrison. 2007. War and the State: The Theory of International Politics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walker, R. B. J. 1993. Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [39].Google Scholar
Walsh, Edmund A, ed. 1922. The History and Nature of International Relations. New York: The Macmillan Company. [4].Google Scholar
Walt, Stephen M. 2002. “Keeping the World ‘Off-Balance’: Self-Restraint and U. S. Foreign Policy.” In America Unrivaled: The Future of the Balance of Power, edited by G. John Ikenberry, 121154. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1959. Man, the State and War: A Theoretical Analysis. New York: Columbia University Press. [39].Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1975. “Theory of International Relations.” In Handbook of Political Science, Volume 8: International Politics, edited by Fred I. Greenstein and Nelson W. Polsby. Reading: Addison-Wesley Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. New York: Random House. [48].Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1986. “Reflections on Theory of International Politics: A Response to My Critics.” In Neo-Realism and Its Critics, edited by Robert O. Keohane. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1990. “Realist Thought and Neo-Realist Theory.” Journal of International Affairs 44(1):21–37.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1999. “Globalization and Governance.” PS: Political Science and Politics 32(4):693–700.Google Scholar
Wendt, Alexander. 1992. “Anarchy is What States Make of It: The Social Construction of Power Politics.” International Organization 46(2):391–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wight, Martin. 1978 [1946]. Power Politics. Leicester: Leicester University Press. [11].Google Scholar
Willoughby, Westel Woodbury. 1896. An Examination of the Nature of the State: A Study in Political Philosophy. New York: Macmillan and Co. [6].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woolf, Leonard. 1916. International Government: Two Reports. London: George Allen & Unwin. [1].Google Scholar
Woolf, Leonard. 1940. The War for Peace. London: G. Routledge & Sons. [8].Google Scholar
Wright, Quincy. 1964 [1942]. A Study of War. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [18].Google Scholar
Young, Oran R. 1978. “Anarchy and Social Choice: Reflections on the International Polity.” World Politics 30(2):241–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zimmern, Alfred E. 1936. The League of Nations and the Rule of Law, 1918–1935, 2nd ed. London: Macmillan and Company. [2].Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1 Occurrences of ‘anarchy’ and ‘anarchic’ in selected books

Supplementary material: PDF

Donnelly supplementary material

Appendix 1

Download Donnelly supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 159.8 KB
Supplementary material: PDF

Donnelly supplementary material

Appendix 2

Download Donnelly supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 117.9 KB
Supplementary material: PDF

Donnelly supplementary material

Appendix 3

Download Donnelly supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 99.5 KB
Supplementary material: PDF

Donnelly supplementary material

Appendix 4

Download Donnelly supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 118.5 KB
Supplementary material: PDF

Donnelly supplementary material

Appendix 5

Download Donnelly supplementary material(PDF)
PDF 112.1 KB