Published online by Cambridge University Press: 15 August 2005
The view that “cultural property internationalism” (Merryman) is represented by the Hague Convention 1954 and that it has been departed from in later UNESCO instruments can be challenged. Words which carry particular connotations can distort the argument—property is one of them, so cultural property is already a loaded term. The historical sources used to buttress the modern argument for more liberal trade in cultural objects bear other interpretations. Similarly, UNESCO's mandate has been narrowed in a way not justified by its constitution. UNESCO's later instruments, such as the 1970 Convention, do not represent an aversion to the art market, as is witnessed by its development on an international Code for Dealers. However, the art trade at present is based on the secrecy of transactions, and this has led to a number of scandals. Neither assessment of the interests at stake nor treaties on human rights or trade require tolerance of these practices.
In the last issue of this journal, a key contribution was the paper by John Merryman on Cultural Property Internationalism.1
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism.”
Merryman, “A Licit Trade,” 2004 The European Fine Arts Foundation (hereafter cited as TEFAF), 24–5.
In the spirit of rational debate, which John Merryman, one of the founders of this journal, has always encouraged, I want to put forth an alternative view. His point that an initial value promoting cultural property internationalism has gradually disappeared in favor of cultural nationalism (or “national retention”3
“Mere retention” seems to have appeared first in Merryman and Elsen, “Hot Art,” 8–11, where it was named as a separate interest from other specified interests of “exporting nations”, an article written at the time of the debate on ratification of the 1970 Convention by the United States. It was developed with an emphasis on the “retentionism” of national protection or “hoarding” in the same authors' Law, Ethics and the Visual Arts 1 (2nd ed. 1987), 53–56.
First, it must be said that the choice of terms in which to conduct such a discussion is unfortunately often predisposed toward a particular view. For example, protection for Merryman means protection of the object or protection of the international interest, whereas he terms the policy of states' protection of objects within their country, retention. The word protection in national heritage legislation, however, shows a wide variety of other interpretations: protection of access, protection of education of creative artists and of the public in their own cultural traditions, protection of minority communities' special requirements for the handling of their cultural creations, as well as protection of the object.
Similarly, cultural property, in my view, necessarily carries with the phrase a whole baggage of associations and implications, in particular, the view in the common law (based on a philosophy broadly shared by the legal systems of continental European countries) that property and ownership rights clearly authorize exploitation, alienation (that is, divestment to any other person at will), and exclusion of others from access—all elements that, in modern heritage law, may well be restricted. For this reason, I would argue that heritage should be preferred, as it is in all recent UNESCO instruments. (I leave aside the term patrimony, which seems to be a particular United States usage not reflected in the international instruments, with a single exception in Article 9 of the UNESCO 1970 Convention, incorporating a United States proposal and obviously not made consistent with the standard terminology in the rest of the Convention.) In a discussion of the experts who early on met to discuss the drafting of the UNIDROIT Convention on Stolen or Illegally Exported Cultural Objects 1995, Merryman urged the use of property, and I urged the use of heritage (which has associations of handing on and guardianship). The term objects in the title and text of the Convention was finally adopted as a compromise.
While it is perhaps inevitable that there are different interpretations of these terms, it is important that every scholar spells out his own usage, and it will be clear from this that there are important implications attached to the terms currently in use.4
Prott and O'Keefe, “‘Cultural Heritage’ or ‘Cultural Property’?”
Hoarding (national retention or “excessive retention”5
Merryman, TEFAF, 19.
Merryman, TEFAF, 31.
Accusations that those who support stronger market controls indulge in “rhetoric”7
Merryman, TEFAF, 20.
Merryman, TEFAF, 16, 18.
Merryman, TEFAF, 34, 41.
Merryman is also critical of the definitions of cultural property or cultural objects used in the UNESCO 1970 and UNIDROIT Conventions (this “pallid definition”10
Merryman, TEFAF, 21.
UNESCO Convention 1970 Article 1; UNIDROIT Convention 1995 Article 2.
Finally, it has been pointed out that the 1970 Convention, which was the first to use this phrasing, was designed to be exhaustive, describing the ambit within which objects are to be selected for export and import control; not exemplary, as was the case with the Hague Convention, which could be further expanded by the participating states12
Niec, Ojczyzna Dzieta Szuki; cf. Nahlik, “Review.”
Merryman prefers to speak of cultural property as “the sorts of things that dealers deal in, collectors collect, and museums acquire and display: principally works of art, antiquities and ethnographic objects” that are “the foci of a social subsystem we can call ‘the cultural property world’ that is populated by artists, collectors, dealers and auction houses, museums and their professionals, art historians, archaeologists and ethnographers, and source nation cultural officials.” Tellingly missing from this list are those groups not comfortable with having their cultural objects considered as commodities for the market: tribal and indigenous communities and creators of various sorts not regarded within their communities, or regarding themselves, as artists but as bearers of a communal tradition.
A similar viewpoint emerges from the suggestion that cultural internationalism is an observable fact because of the activities of London and Berlin ethnographic museums, the Metropolitan Museum (New York), Japanese and Swiss dealers, and Dutch and German collectors, who deal in, exhibit, and collect “important art and antiquity collections of works from Europe, Africa, East and South Asia, the Middle East” and both Americas. The one-sidedness of this kind of cultural internationalism is evident—it looks far more like cultural imperialism, based as it seems to be on the activities of those from wealthy countries with each other and with poorer states whose cultural resources are flowing in one direction, without an equal exchange. It is an observable fact that far more is flowing in the direction of wealthy countries than the reverse; it is far from an exchange and, indeed, looks rather more like exploitation.
The suggestion that Grotius was the first since classical times to argue for moderation in destruction of cultural property, is not borne out by research into the ideas of other cultures. Both Muslim and Hindu rulers made rules against it many centuries before the West began to catch up.13
Bugnion, “Origin and Development,” 4–8; Prott, “Cultural Heritage Law,” 25–26.
Merryman's reliance on Quatremère de Quincy's protest against the Napoleonic takings14
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 15.
Fiedler, Internationaler Kulturgüterschutz [International Protection of Cultural Property], 54–55 and n. 162.
The Marquis de Somerueles case cited does not seem to give greater support than Quatremère. True, Dr. Croke makes some fine pronouncements such as this:
The arts and sciences belong to all Europe, and are no longer the exclusive property of one nation… It is as a member of this universal republic of the arts and sciences, and not as an inhabitant of this or that nation, that I shall discuss the concern of all parts in the preservation of the whole.16
Quatremère de Quincy, Lettres au général Miranda [Letters to General Miranda], 88, 99, cited by Merryman in “Marquis de Somerueles,“ 324.
However, the very fact that the phrase “not the property of one nation” is used by Dr. Croke to insist on the artworks in question being restored to the arrangements made by their owners is not to excuse their taking. Further notable is that he appears to equate “the universal republic of the arts and sciences” with “civilized Europe”—a position that hardly commends itself as a basis for assessing the problems of illicit trafficking among the 192 states of the contemporary world. Finally, after his study of Quatremère and Croke, Merryman's suggestion is bizarre that the conflict between the humane internationalist ideal to which he appealed and the nationalist glorification of military campaigns that the French under Bonaparte had embraced “persists today in the international law of cultural property;” there is no conflict about the wrongfulness of destruction of cultural property in wartime—a number of international treaties assert it, and its principle is now one of international customary law. These authors were not attempting to solve questions of trade and trafficking between nations at peace, and to use their arguments to justify ignoring the efforts of countries to preserve access to cultural heritage for their cultural communities is an argument that goes beyond interpretation. Moreover, an attentive reading of the penultimate paragraph above will suggest that Quatremère's words can equally be used, with a similar interpretive stretch, as a justification for precisely the opposite position.
Similar arguments can be made about Merryman's use of the later precedents from United States scholars, which were focused on protection in wartime. One dangerous statement, however, is that the Roerich Pact “is in practice a dead letter.” I am not aware that it has been denounced by any of the parties to it (10 Latin American states and the United States), and it is therefore all the more important that no doubt be cast on its current validity, since a number of parties to it, including the United States, have refrained from becoming party to the Hague Convention and its protocols. No doubt many believe that the principles of the Roerich Pact are sufficient to protect them, assessing warlike threats from other parts of the world as unlikely. During the 1970s, suggestions were made that the Hague Convention itself was a dead letter; the emergence of new local conflicts has made its relevance very clear, and the fact that 113 states are now party to it is evidence of its vitality.
In support for his internationalist view, Merryman cites the wording of the Hague Convention for the Protection of Cultural Property in the Event of Armed Conflict 1954: “cultural property is ‘the cultural heritage of all mankind.’ ”17
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 11. To be fair, he quotes the article in full on p. 19, but fails to analyze it in detail or to relate it to the later provisions of the Convention and Protocol.
Being convinced that damage to cultural property belonging to any people whatsoever means damage to the cultural heritage of all mankind, since each people makes its contribution to the culture of the world
The phrases “belonging to any people” and “each people makes its contribution to the culture of the world” add an emphasis that is integral to this paragraph on the importance of culture to each people as well as to the heritage of mankind. They also assume importance in view of the content of the Convention, which requires states' parties to “support the competent national authorities of the occupied country in safeguarding and preserving its cultural property” (Article 5(1)—emphasis added), to refrain from requisitioning it (Article 4(3)), and to prevent its exportation (Protocol (1954) Article 1). It seems a strange interpretation to use this as the justification for wider market access. As Turner points out, the effect of the preamble is to provide that “the interests of the states possessing cultural objects are also seen as interests of the whole of the world community”18
Turner, in Fiedler, Internationaler Kulturgüterschutz [International Protection of Cultural Property], 67.
Merryman's statement that “the international interest in protecting cultural property from the hazards of war began to expand into a more general cultural property internationalism” seems, therefore, to make a hazardous leap from a philosophy designed for a particular purpose to embrace first, a particular interpretation of the philosophy of the Convention, and second, to assume that the universalism of the European Enlightenment is the natural basis of any protective scheme, whereas protection first at the local level might seem to be a priority. It can also be argued that the protection from exploitative removal by military power expanded naturally in peacetime to protection from exploitation of economic or political power and has the same result—an interpretation of the Convention that is certainly equally valid.
Merryman's discussion of UNESCO's mandate again reveals a particular view. UNESCO's constitution does not, in fact, mention cultural property. The full text of the relevant provisions is:
(c) Maintain, increase and diffuse knowledge:
By assuring the conservation and protection of the world's inheritance of books, works of art and monuments of history and science, and recommending to the nations concerned the necessary international conventions;
By encouraging cooperation among the nations in all branches of intellectual activity, including the international exchange of persons active in the fields of education, science and culture and the exchange of publications, objects of artistic and scientific interest and other materials of information;
Merryman argues that something is missing from this mandate; namely “preservation,” which he describes as protecting the object and its context from impairment. In any event, the words conservation and protection seem quite adequate to cover the concept of preservation and have certainly been applied in that sense. Merryman's discussion of protection seems to leave out the interest of a community in the continuance of its cultural traditions. For example, an anthropologist might see the use of an object by its traditional community as a primary way of preserving centuries of traditional use and the vitality of rituals and practices of that community. The object's ultimate impairment and replacement, as has occurred since time immemorial for that community, may be a price that has to be paid. This problem is not solved by his emphasis on access; access to a museum collection (even when the museum is in an accessible locality, which is often not the case) does not ensure appropriate treatment of that object for that community. In fact, in the case of objects from wide swathes of humanity, it almost certainly ensures its inappropriate treatment. Such an object, even if displayed rather than hidden in a museum reserve collection, has lost its place in the cultural life of that community.
Merryman has argued for a “related triad of regulatory imperatives”19
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 11; “Nation and the Object,” 64–65.
However, truth for many does not reside only in contextual information but in the community's continued re-endorsement of value by use within that community. Scholars and the general public from wealthy countries can now have access to virtually any country in the world. Access to the universal museums of the West is denied simply on economic grounds to many communities distant from them. Private collections are, of course, not accessible to them at all.
So Merryman's triad of preservation, truth, and access leaves out substantial interests of large parts of the world's population.
There is also a universal concern to protect cultural diversity, and UNESCO in recent years has had no difficulty in reading this into its mandate. This concern builds on the need to preserve multiple human life styles (parallel to the concern to preserve as much biological diversity as possible) and to respect other people's cultural traditions in order to avoid conflict. The display in many museums or dealers' windows of items that are of a sacred or secret nature to their makers does not engender intercommunal harmony. It is also a general concern that the care of an object be associated with its original creators, and this means fighting to keep their cultural traditions alive. How can a community continue to build boats when every major ocean-going vessel has now been out of their country for decades, as is the case of a once vibrant tradition in the Cook Islands? How can contemporary Easter Islanders have any idea of the unique and vigorous carving of their ancestors and adapt their skills to their current place in the world, when every major piece (numbering hundreds, if not thousands) are in museums remote from this distant community? In other words, whole chapters of a cultural tradition can be lost by inordinate trade and outright illegal acquisition. In these cases, exchange, even if it were to be more balanced, would not preserve or restore cultural traditions.
Why is this important? Because in the words of the Hague Convention, “each people makes its contribution to the culture of the world.” As anthropologists and others have pointed out, it is not clear that agrarian and industrial societies (very recently developed, as measured against the lengthy survival of traditional hunter/gatherer communities) will survive a technological disaster or the exhaustion of resources. The life skills of those from nonindustrial, even nonagrarian, societies may prove to be essential for our descendants. Even a regional disruption of industrial products on which, in a globalized world, people in every community are increasingly reliant, could cause disaster: boats, fishing nets, and string bags will be needed when steel and plastic are no longer available.
Strangely, in view of his acceptance of the need for source nation regulations to protect the cultural heritage when it is fragile or of religious/ritual importance, to prevent dismemberment of monuments or the destruction of context, or to ensure a representative collection of at least the most important categories of its own cultural heritage,20
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 12–13.
Merryman deprecates leaving states free to make “their own self-interested decisions,” and also the way the Convention “condones and supports the widespread practice of overretention or, less politely, hoarding of cultural property.”21
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 22.
There are other issues that market supporters sometimes appear to be particularly unaware of. The push for the 1970 Convention came after decades of colonial exploitation and abuse of positions of power practiced on the emerging states. The policies that Merryman finds overretentive are in most cases a reaction against the losses that have already occurred when communities were unable, for one reason or another, to resist them. These events have created resentment and suspicion. The exposure of contemporary conspiracies to corrupt their officials and subvert their laws, such as the cases involving the London dealer Tokeley-Parry22
〈http://www.mcdonald.cam.ac.uk/IARC/cwoc/issue10/investigation.htm1〉 (accessed 25 February 2005)
United States v. Schultz 178 F.Supp.2d 45 (2003); 333 F.3d 393 (2003).
Abranches, Report on the Situation in Africa, 3.
If countries with strong export prohibitions over all or most categories of cultural property are to loosen those prohibitions, it will not be as a result of accusations of hoarding. There is a need for a substantial effort to understand the important feelings involved and the arguments these countries make, while seeking to show that there are real advantages in the exhibition of, and resulting interest generated in, their culture in other countries. There are few countries that would not be proud to have their culture valued by others. Unfortunately, successful exhibitions such as that of Te Maori (New Zealand)25
The successful Te Maori exhibition opened at the Metropolitan Museum of Art in New York in 1984, then toured several other United States cities. While the taonga (treasures) were created many generations ago, they are regarded as tupuna (ancestors) to whom Maori are personally linked, and so the taonga were appropriately accompanied by traditional rituals. Consequently, each exhibition of the taonga became an expression of te ao Maori (the Maori world) as a vibrant, living culture.
In some of his other writings, Merryman has sought to confront some of the arguments of those supporting other countries' export prohibitions. For example, in several articles,26
Such as Merryman, “Nation and the Object,” 65–66; Merryman, TEFAF, 20; Merryman, “A Licit Trade,” 21–22; Merryman, “Retention,” 482–486.
… what is the proper response to claims by tribal groups … for the return of ritual, ceremonial, or religious objects? In many cases the objects, if returned, will be exposed to the elements or consumed or otherwise destroyed or, if protected, will be kept in secret places, available for viewing only by a select few or on infrequent occasions and generally inaccessible for scholarly purposes or public enjoyment. Should the objects be returned … even though object-related values will consequently be seriously impaired? And if the answer is yes, what justifies this sacrifice of object-related values?27
Merryman, “A Licit Trade,” 13.
The answer is, of course, person-related values. The damage done to the intangible heritage and the complex beliefs and practices of tribal peoples in this situation can produce a sense of desecration of sacred objects that has a profound effect on a society whose beliefs should be respected. By what moral principle does one justify values related to an object (which is, in any case, a value much more highly respected in commercial societies) above those related to people and central to their well being? By what right should an object meant by its creators to be seen only by authorized persons be made accessible to the public at large?
His redefinition of a licit trade in that same article28
Merryman, “A Licit Trade,” 29.
Merryman also argues that in “poorer countries, the orderly marketing of surplus cultural objects could pro tanto displace the black market, while providing a significant source of income to the source nation and its citizens.”29
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 23.
Egypt's Law No. 117 on the Protection of Antiquities 1983 forbids trade in antiquities (ss. 6–7), replacing the system of the previous Law on the Protection of Antiquities No. 215 1952 ss. 22 ff. Syria repealed Chapter 5 ss.56–65 of its Ordinance No. 222 26 October 1963 in 1986.
Merryman criticizes three other UNESCO instruments, the Recommendation Concerning the International Exchange of Cultural Property 1976, Recommendation for the Protection of Movable Cultural Property 1978, and Convention on the Protection of the Underwater Cultural Heritage 2001 as providing no place for private collectors or an active art trade, no scope for a licit market, and no recognition of the historic roles of collectors and dealers in supporting artists and promoting their work in building private collections that ultimately enrich museums, or in pioneering the collection of objects that eventually are recognized for their cultural importance. There seems no recognition that all these advantages are seen from the sole viewpoint of persons in wealthy, commercially oriented societies where artists are individually (not communally) responsible for their creations, where there are dealers who promote the role of creators in that society and ensure their adequate representation, and where there are wealthy collectors who can afford private collections and indulge their personal tastes. Which are the museums that are enriched? Such arguments must sound hollow to many creative artists who do not regard their work as a commodity and who need and wish to respect communal rules as to how their creations are used, as was the case in Milpurru v Indofurn,31
Intellectual Property Reports (Australia, 1994) 209.
Watson, Sotheby's, 170–198.
These arguments may be better appreciated among those countries where at least some artists live on the proceeds of their art and intend to sell at least a proportion of their output as a commodity. But even within the European Union (EU), Council Directive of 15 March 1993 on the Return of Cultural Objects Unlawfully Removed from the Territory of a Member State 199333
Directive 93/7/EEC Official Journal L 74 of March 3, 1993.
Merryman, “Nation and the Object,” 63.
Merryman reserves particular opprobrium for the UNESCO Convention on the Protection of the Underwater Cultural Heritage 2001. Its provision against commercial exploitation he regards as “breathtaking.” However, one could see it as the natural result of an unregulated situation, such as Merryman would apparently approve, which has led to commercial salvage of, and treasure hunts for, historic shipwrecks with, in many cases, complete destruction of the historic shipwreck and no cultural benefit for any of the peoples associated with it, through history, location, origin of ship, or origin of cargo. Such a situation has not been tolerated in land excavations for decades, and the slowness of adopting controls in the maritime areas (due to complications with the law of the sea), has created a situation of such dire emergency that further commercial exploration is likely to wreck the last vestiges of an irreplaceable archaeological resource.
Interestingly enough, this provision and the Rules of the Annex, which spell this principle out in detail, were accepted by every single delegation without exception at the negotiations. Even states such as the United States, which is unlikely to ratify the Convention at present, has expressed its complete accord with it. In other words, the difficulties of protecting historic shipwrecks are so apparent to both archaeologists and those responsible for the protection of the heritage that this was seen as the only possible way of ensuring it.
The UNESCO Convention for the Safeguarding of the Intangible Cultural Heritage 2003 does not have any provisions directly mentioning commerce. Merryman's questions as to how international trade or retention policies might be relevant overlook the most important one of all: the removal of key items used in the practice of intangible cultural heritage will cause damage and probably destruction of the intangible heritage. Bowls used in ritual ceremonies such as the Saanich bowl and regarded as desecrated;35
Henry, “Back from the Brink,” 8–10.
The abstraction of textiles from the Altiplano area around Coroma in Bolivia is movingly related by members of one of these communities in the television documentary El Camino de las Almas produced by Cristina Bubba Zamora.
Schick, The Gods are Leaving the Country.
Merrill et al., “The Return of the Ahaya:da.”
In response to Merryman's argument that UNESCO has deviated from its internationalist mission, others might well argue that instead of adopting the views of a minority of countries and populations for a particular view of its internationalist mission, it has done its best to respect the views of all peoples in how best to protect the great diversity of cultures represented among its member states. Which is the more internationalist?
UNESCO has certainly not ignored the useful function of dealers and collectors. In 1997 the UNESCO Intergovernmental Committee for Promoting the Return of Cultural Property to its Countries of Origin or its Restitution in Case of Illicit Appropriation adopted a report39
O'Keefe, Trade in Antiquities.
Although the Code was based on the existing codes of dealer organizations and on discussions with them, its promulgation has been met with either apathy or criticism from the dealer community. It seems rather unfair to speak of UNESCO's “market aversion;”40
TEFAF, 13.
What has always been surprising in this debate is that the dealers themselves have done nothing to distance themselves from the more disreputable elements of the trade. After all, there is no particular qualification that distinguishes a dealer of the highest expertise and ethical standards from the dodgy character who buys from a thief and sells from the back of a truck. A number of cases have shown exactly how easy it is to arrange passage from a source country through the hands of a number of villains into the hands of a dealer of the highest repute. Peter Wilson, in a personal capacity but with his reputation as chairman of Sotheby's behind him, sold the Sevso treasure to Lord Northampton. The export certificates accompanying them were found to be forged, and Lord Northampton subsequently recovered damages both from Wilson and from his legal advisers. Robert Huber, an art dealer from New York, sold to Steinhardt a gold phiale from Sicily that was held by the U.S. 2nd Circuit of Appeals to be stolen according to Italian law. A treasure from Aidonia in Greece was displayed in New York in his gallery by the dealer Michael Ward before it was claimed by the Greek government.41
〈http://www.culture.gr/6/68/684/e68403.html〉 (accessed February 25, 2005).
Even more worrisome is the direct implication of some apparently respectable dealers carrying high positions in the art trade, in some extraordinarily unethical behavior. The Schultz case42
333 F.R.(3rd) 393.
United States v. Schultz 333 F.3d 396, 397.
〈http://www.mcdonald.cam.ac.uk/IARC/cwoc/issue10/investigation.htm〉 (accessed February 25, 2005).
Another example is provided by the Bumper Development case.45
Bumper Development Corp., Ltd. v. Commissioner of Police of the Metropolis and Others (Union of India and Others, Claimants) All England Law Reports, 4, 638 (1991).
Unless the ethical dealers make some greater effort to control the unethical and illegal practices in the trade, one can hardly wonder that those concerned with heritage protection trust governmental and intergovernmental agencies more than they do private persons and their organizations, most of whom have not only made no particular effort to screen the licit trade from the results of scandalous activity but have even actively supported some of the perpetrators of it.
Why have dealer groups not joined actively with UNESCO to stamp out organized criminal mafias who have taken over sectors of the trade? UNESCO has close relations with INTERPOL on these matters, and it is a serious concern. A dealer in icons in Berlin was murdered some years ago at a time when border controls with the former Eastern Bloc had weakened, and icons were arriving in truckloads from Russia and other countries formerly out of bounds to the illegal trade. Press speculation circulated that the dealer had failed to agree with his suppliers or perhaps to pay protection money. Should this not be a very serious concern to the dealers?
Behind all this debate, behind the mutual suspicion and criticism, there is one undeniable fact: the art trade is the only major sector of international trade where it is regarded as normal, indeed essential, that provenance is not required as a normal element of any acquisition. The natural reaction of any lawyer new to the field to this practice is one of amazement. Even Bator expressed this view:
The most striking thing to a lawyer who comes upon the art world is how deep and uncritical is the assumption that transactions within it should normally be—are certainly entitled to be—secret… No dealer or auction house will normally reveal the provenance of an object offered for sale; it is assumed that buyers and the public have no business knowing where and when and for how much the object was acquired…. Indeed, the tradition is that such information is rarely even sought … [T]he art treasure with a full and documented pedigree is rare precisely because the custom has always been to ask as few questions as possible. Too much information may spoil the acquisition of a stunning and desirable treasure. It is the propriety of secrecy which is assumed; and it is a secrecy which enables persons, otherwise aspiring to the highest standards of personal probity, to become accomplices in the acquisition of looted masterpieces.46
Bator, “An Essay,” 360.
The results of this willful blindness have, alas, been only too clear to see with the revelation of just how many museums, collectors, and dealers handled material looted during the Second World War, although evidence of its tainted source and its illegality, such as catalogs of missing objects, was available.
Whether one wishes to acquire a motor vehicle, shares, real property, a mining lease, or any other valuable property on the international market, a thorough search of title is required of any purchaser if he expects protection of his acquisition by the legal system. Yet any effort to require this in respect of cultural objects has been virulently opposed by those in the art trade. Why is this so, especially as this attitude goes along with assertions that the illicit trade is only a tiny, indeed virtually negligible, proportion of the trade as a whole? If this is the case, where are the thousands of objects looted from archaeological sites, the untraced thefts from museums, churches, and other institutions going? In the Bumper Development case, an Inspector General of Police for the CID in the state of Tamil Nadu (one of the 28 states and seven territories of the Indian Union) said that there had been 800–1,000 thefts of idols in that state alone during the preceding 10 years. It is not surprising that those in source countries battling to preserve a reasonable representation of their own cultural heritage and those in communities faced with continuing losses of significance regard with extreme skepticism the suggestion that concealment of sources is a necessary step in a legitimate art trade.
The failure to accept any responsible change in that practice has increased reliance on steps that Merryman deprecates, such as countries taking ownership of undiscovered antiquities and more draconian export regulations than he would wish. If source countries had any confidence that there would be some real control over the transition of suspicious material into the licit market, they would perhaps be more inclined to lessen controls at their end.
In the introductory section of his most recent article, Merryman states that
No thinking person argues for free trade in cultural property. Regulation is necessary in order to preserve cultural property and to support its proper international circulation…
… [S]ource nation regulations preserve the cultural heritage when and to the extent that they protect fragile objects that are likely to be damaged or destroyed by movement and when they prevent the dismemberment of complex objects, like the panels of an altarpiece or the components of a sculptural group. When antiquities are removed from their contexts in order to preserve, study and enjoy them, archaeologists rightly urge and source nations rightly require that the removal be done with care and that it be accompanied by full documentation. It seems right that objects of ritual/religious importance to living cultures remain with or be returned to the representatives of those cultures … And finally, it is internationally important that the inhabitants of every nation, including the poorest survivors of colonial exploitation, have access to a fully representative collection of objects that represent their history and culture.47
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 3.
The list includes important concessions that, interestingly enough, are not listed in the TEFAF article. However, the big problem with this position is that, given the insistence on the secrecy of transactions, how can one distinguish those objects that may properly be traded and those which, because retention is justified and protected by national export prohibition, may not? Once an object arrives in the licit market, detached from any information as to its provenance (origin) or provenience (subsequent transactions), how can anyone possibly tell whether it is being legitimately traded or not, or indeed, stolen? Provision in the UNIDROIT Convention that an object be returned without compensation unless due diligence (that is, proper inquiry made by the purchaser) has been shown, is being furiously resisted. Why? If the illicit trade is such a small part of the market, this provision is not threatening. Cynics may take the view that it is exactly because many in the art trade know that such objects are a principal source of their stock that they so vehemently resist it.
In his TEFAF article, Merryman also justifies his defense of the art trade by assessing the interests at stake. Though superficially attractive, this argument is defective. The articulators of this theory recognized that some interests are usually asserted as social or public interests, but others are more familiar to us as assertions of interests of the citizen seen as an individual. Roscoe Pound, the originator of this kind of analysis of legal policymaking in the United States, is insistent, however, that these are not separate categories. Social or public interests are still interests of individuals, just as individual interests may be looked upon as public or social interests. It is axiomatic that the same interest may be looked at from each standpoint, and Pound was unambiguously insistent that interests, however labeled, must be mutually translatable to one level to allow comparison. This is important, for if an interest is labeled as individual, it may, if your bent is individualism, automatically be given priority over a public or social interest. If you are, on the other hand, from a culture where the focus is on the community rather than the individual, you may naturally give priority to an interest expressed in that way.48
Stone, Social Dimensions, 171–178,II181; Pound, Social Control through Law, 2.
Merryman's comparison of archaeologists pursuing their own, as opposed to the international interest, falls precisely into that trap. Archaeologists' and other cultural workers' interest in the survival of cultural objects and their proper handling can be seen as a social interest, as can the anthropologists' interest in the survival of threatened cultures.
If the interests of the art trade are asserted as international, so must the interests of the others be categorized on the same level.49
Merryman's article “Public Interest” has the same problem.
I would also suggest that in analyzing interests to be accounted for in making legal policy, all the interests involved must be taken into account. This is not the place to enter into a full analysis of all the interests involved in the protection of the cultural heritage: elsewhere Patrick O'Keefe and I have attempted to do so, at least for the protection of the archaeological heritage.50
Prott & O'Keefe, Law and the Cultural Heritage, 1: 15–28.
Merryman regards as an established principle of private international law the fact that courts judicially enforce foreign private law rights (such as ownership) but not foreign public law rights (such as export regulations).51
Merryman, TEFAF, 28.
Merryman also considers the rights of private owners to be preferred over the rights of the state as owner, the more so as state assertions of ownership may in fact be “merely a disguised form of export control.”53
Merryman, TEFAF, 28.
Attorney-General of New Zealand v. Ortiz [1982] 1Q.B.349; [1982] 3 W.L.R. 571 (Court of Appeal); [1983]2 W.L.R. 809 (House of Lords).
Human rights arguments are to be handled with care by nonspecialists in this important area. There have been many debates about whether certain human rights should have precedence over others, in particular whether civil and political rights should be regarded as having a legal character denied to the economic, social, and cultural rights. After decades of debate, numerous international declarations uphold their equal validity, such as that of the World Conference on Human Rights in Vienna in 1993 that “[all] human rights are universal, indivisible and interdependent and inter-related.”55
Niec, “Casting the Foundations,” 177.
This applies of course to property rights and cultural rights. To state the latter at the most basic level, Article 15 of the International Covenant on Economic Social and Cultural Rights provides:
There is in this formulation a careful balancing of the needs of individuals in respect to their own culture and its support by preservation or by interchange (“take part in cultural life”, “conservation … development and … diffusion of … culture”, “international contacts and cooperation in the scientific and cultural fields”). The rights guaranteed by it are not put into a hierarchy; the rights of citizens are regarded both in their individuality and in their collectivity. International cooperation is essential; so is access. Neither has priority. So there is no priority among cultural rights themselves, and there is no priority between property rights and cultural rights.
This leaves us with a delicate balancing act to perform in order to do justice between states and individuals. With an observable movement of cultural objects in one particular direction (to Europe, United States, and Japan), the need for countervailing mechanisms seems clear.
A final legal justification for increased liberalization of trade in cultural movables is based by Merryman on trade agreements.56
Merryman, “Cultural Property Internationalism,” 12; Merryman, TEFAF, 27–28.
He cites Article 30 of the Consolidated Treaty of the European Community as admitting exception for the “protection of national cultural treasures” to the rule prohibiting export controls, but argues that this phrase should be interpreted narrowly. However; that treaty also contains the following clause:
This Treaty, drawn up in a single original in the Dutch, French, German, and Italian languages, all four texts being equally authentic, shall be deposited in the archives of the Government of the Italian Republic, which shall transmit a certified copy to each of the Governments of the other signatory States.
Pursuant to the Accession Treaties, the Danish, English, Finnish, Greek, Irish, Portuguese, Spanish and Swedish versions of this Treaty shall also be authentic.
The French text refers to “protection des trésors nationaux ayant une valeur artistique, historique ou archéologique.” It is the only one of the many other official texts currently available to me that reflects the concept of treasures. The others seem to state rather clearly that cultural heritage is within the exception: “beskyttelse af nationale skatte af kunstnerisk, historisk eller arkæologisk værdi” (Danish); “het nationaal artistiek historisch en archeologisch bezit” (Dutch); zum Schutze … des nationalen Kulturguts von künstlerischem, geschichtlichem oder archäologischem Wert” (German);” “protezione del patrimonio artistico, storico o archeologico nazionale” (Italian); “protección del patrimonio artístico, histórico o arqueológico nacional” (Spanish); “bevara växter, att skydda nationella skatter av konstnärligt, historiskt eller arkeologiskt värde” (Swedish); “protecção do património nacional de valor artístico, histórico ou arqueológico” (Portuguese) (listed, according to international practice, by alphabetical order of language). Note also that these phrases accurately reflect the definition in the 1970 Convention that Merryman found inadequate.
In support of his view, Merryman quotes Pierre Pescatore as saying that “[t]he Exception's purpose is not to preserve the totality of an artistic patrimony” but to safeguard its “essential and fundamental elements.”57
Merryman, TEFAF, 29.
Stamatoudi, “National Treasures,” 48.
Merryman also cites a similar text in the World Trade Organization (WTO) treaty (a full citation of the treaty is not given), but again, only the English text is cited, and there are other equally authentic language versions to be consulted. One also needs to be aware that so far the decisions that have been taken about this article, have been taken by tribunals that, like the International Court of Justice in the Preah Vihear case (a dispute about a temple on the Thai/Khmer border), have no professional background in heritage matters.
There is, as everyone is aware, a strong move, particularly by the United States, to remove the “cultural exception” from the general trade agreement (General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade 1947, taken over by the World Trade Organization Agreement 1994). A number of states are deeply concerned about this, and there will certainly be very tough negotiations on the subject.
All in all, I think the assessment that “a naive and misguided anti-market prejudice, excessive source nation retentionism and the excesses of the archaeologists' Crusade … supports [sic] source nation actions that violate (emphasis added) the cultural property provision of the WTO and EU treaties and related international arrangements” is certainly premature and may well be proven wrong.
One other thing needs to be said on the question of trade agreements. An argument frequently urged in favor of more liberal trade in antiquities and other movables is that they are not properly looked after in their homeland. If those in industrialized states concerned with their welfare were to lobby in their own states as hard for reduction of tariffs for agricultural and other goods produced by poorer countries as they do for liberalization of trade in cultural property, not only would millions of people no longer live in the most dire poverty, but increasing wealth would enable those countries to devote a greater proportion of their national resources to policing and conservation. A general liberalization of trade, rather than the partial one that has been occurring, would, in terms of assertions of interest and human rights, be a solution to some of the problems that Merryman has outlined. But a one-sided solution will only make things worse.
In this reality, it seems far-fetched to suggest that excessive restraints thwart internationalist goals and that there has been an artificial expansion of the meaning of illicit to reduce the possibilities of a licit cultural property trade. To the contrary, the restraints seek to ensure internationalist goals by ensuring that there is a fairer distribution of cultural objects and not a one-way flow.
Merryman asks in his conclusion, “Whither cultural property internationalism?” My own answer would be that cultural internationalism will flourish but not in terms of the very limited cultural property internationalism he espouses. I do not believe that the historical sources represent the form of internationalism that his description currently takes, and I think that many of the arguments being made in support of a far greater liberalization of trade in cultural movables are not well founded and ignore important social, political, and historical factors that have led to the current restrictiveness of many countries.
Finally, we should all be aware that problems like this are not solved by legal regulation alone. Where there are so many diverse and entrenched views, the involvement of the very wealthy, the utterly impoverished, and every level in between; states; private organizations; and individuals, all in active pursuit of their interests, will result in issues such as resources, education, and public awareness having a major impact on the solutions.