Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-s22k5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-10T19:03:40.202Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

WHY THE FRENCH DON'T LIKE THE BURQA:1LAÏCITÉ, NATIONAL IDENTITY AND RELIGIOUS FREEDOM

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 August 2012

Myriam Hunter-Henin
Affiliation:
Senior Lecturer in Law, University College London, m.hunter-henin@ucl.ac.uk.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article examines the controversies over and implications of the 2010 French ban on the covering of the face. It carries out an internal critique of the new law and, in a broader European context, questions its compatibility with the European Convention on Human Rights. It argues that the ban has strayed away from the confines of laïcité (the separation of State and religion in the public sphere) by encompassing activities and people who in no way emanate from the State. Far from being a flagship of a secularism—à la française—or a French way of life, the ban—it is argued—goes against entrenched French legal traditions and unduly conflates the concept of national identity at the cost of individual liberties, thus forgetting the true goal of secularism: the conciliation of different beliefs and values. Assuming that the defence of secularism is nevertheless (for reasons we will explore) upheld by the European Court of Human Rights as a legitimate aim pursued by the law, the French ban, it is argued, is likely to fall foul of European requirements for lack of proportionality.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © British Institute of International and Comparative Law 2012

I. INTRODUCTION

If the salient question of the twentieth century was race, first as manifested in European imperialism and then in international decolonization and domestic civic rights movements, the corresponding question of the twenty-first century may well be religion, particularly Islam.Footnote 2

As the issue of the public display of religion hits the headlines again,Footnote 3 recent events seem to lend some truth to Fadel's prediction. Movements to ban the full Islamic veil have gained ground across Europe. Polls in Italy, Spain, Germany and Britain have indicated widespread supportFootnote 4 and very recently, two Western European countries—France and Belgium—have legislated to ban the covering of the face in public spaces.Footnote 5 These recent developments have reignited old conceptual divides between multiculturalism and secularism, between the public and the private spheres, between a British and a French legal tradition.

On 11 April 2011, the French banFootnote 6 came into force, followed closely, on 23 July 2011, by the Belgian Act.Footnote 7 Whilst The NetherlandsFootnote 8 and some cities in SpainFootnote 9 have followed suit, other European countries, amongst which Britain, are resisting the trend. Shadow Chancellor and Former Schools Secretary Ed Balls for example said in January 2010 that it was ‘not British’ to tell people what to wear in the street after the UK Independence Party called for all face-covering Muslim veils to be banned.Footnote 10 Conversely, the 2010 ban has been defended by its supporters in France as a manifestation of a French tradition.

In this article, I will contest the allegation that the French ban embodies a secularist or French tradition. The differences between secularism and multiculturalism, often associated respectively with French and British traditions, should not be exaggerated. As Brenna Bhandar has very convincingly shown:

if multiculturalism rests on the recognition of diversity which it then seeks to accommodate whereas secularism purports to construct a transcending common unity, both multiculturalism and secularism are deployed as techniques to govern difference that is perceived to violate dominant norms and values defined in reference to the Christian cultural heritage of the nation-state.Footnote 11

Protecting common values is key to both secularism and multiculturalism. The differences lie in the methods used to protect these common fundamental values: whereas the secularist countries will to some extent relegate religious expression to the private sphere, multiculturalist countries will not rely upon the public/private sphere divide so strictly.Footnote 12 Focusing on the 2010 French legislative ban, this article will contest the allegation that the ban on the burqa Footnote 13 corresponds in any way with a secularist or any other French tradition.

Undeniably, the 2010 Act is not the first instance of a prohibition of religious symbols in France. In 2004, the French ban on ostentatious religious symbols in public schoolsFootnote 14 was received—whether welcomed or criticized—as a French peculiarity, a symbol itself of a ‘laïcité à la française’. As this French ‘tradition’ was then upheld by the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR)Footnote 15 and social tensions in French public schools subsided,Footnote 16 one could have thought that the 2004 ban was the end of the road. One would have been wrong. Six years later, with the new ban on the covering of the face, this ‘laïcité à la française’ is now allegedly taken out of schools and onto the streets. If both the 2004 and 2010 laws adopt a neutral phraseology—targeting respectively ‘ostentatious religious symbols’ and ‘the covering of the face’—it has escaped no one's attention that the first law was primarily aimed at the Islamic headscarf or hijab whilst the latter is to condemn the practice of the full Islamic veil, ie the wearing of the burqa or niqab, that is a form of veiling which hides the body completely except for the hands and with the latter, for a gauze panel or slit for the eyes. Both Acts could therefore be described as the legal expression of the French sensitivity to the presence of Islam in the public sphere. Despite the similarities between the two Acts, the continuity between the two pieces of legislation will be challenged in this article.

The 2010 Law which was adopted on 11 October 2010,Footnote 17 with the blessing of the French Constitutional Council, the Conseil constitutionnel,Footnote 18 originated in a Presidential comment. On 22 June 2009, before both Houses of Parliament in Versailles, President Nicolas Sarkozy declared that ‘the burqa wasn't welcome in France.’Footnote 19 This feeling is not uniquely French. On this side of the Channel too, politicians and journalists have at times confessed their uneasiness towards the burqa. Jack Straw had publicly acknowledged his discomfortFootnote 20 and similar feelings have been found expressed by Matthew Parris in the Opinion columns in The Times. Footnote 21 But the French (and now Belgian and possibly soon to be Dutch) specificity resides in the political determination to turn this dislike into a legal prohibition whereas in Britain social norms are seen as the best response.Footnote 22

Since Nicolas Sarkozy's remark, committees, reports and parliamentary debates have in France searched for ways to translate this feeling of discomfort into French law. Instructed by the Prime Minister to suggest legal avenues for a ban on the burqa, the Conseil d'Etat Footnote 23 considered that a general dislike for the burqa could not transform into a general prohibition in all public spaces. No legal basis would allow for a prohibition of such general scope.Footnote 24 The special Committee set up to study the ‘practice of the wearing of the full veil on French national territory’Footnote 25 concluded firmly that the burqa was incompatible with the fundamental values of the French Republic but was evasive as to the appropriate legal response. Undeterred by the special committee's uncertainty or the Conseil d'Etat's warnings that a general prohibition would be likely to be incompatible with the Constitution and the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR),Footnote 26 the government decided to open the parliamentary stage of the debates.Footnote 27 Despite its legal fuzziness, the proposal for a general ban was approved by the lower house on 8 July 2010 and by the upper house on 14 September 2010. The political supportFootnote 28 behind the ban did not cure the text of its legal frailty. Implicitly acknowledging the legal weakness of the law, the Presidents of each house of the French Parliament—jointly—and so, for the first time in the legislative history of the French Fifth Republic—referred the newly voted law to the Conseil constitutionnel's scrutiny. The Conseil constitutionnel's brief and reverential decisionFootnote 29 allowed the law to be promulgated but—I will argue—this has not strengthened the legal basis for the ban nor removed the risk of incompatibility with the ECHR.

In this article, I will contest the allegation that the 2010 ban is but a next step in the promotion of secularism and feminism. The eradication of difference that is sought by the new law is alien to secularism which even in its most virulent forms is designed to manage rather than deny diversity of beliefs. Nor is the new law a crusade for feminism. The ideal and abstract female image it defends does not support the dignity of veiled women but seeks to protect the comfort of the majority. This article will in turn consider and reject all of the potential justifications put forward (explicitly or implicitly) in support of the 2010 ban: laïcité (Part I), dignity, gender equality (Part II) and public policy (Part III). It will further argue that these aims, however legitimate, would not qualify as justifications for a general ban before the ECtHR and if they did, would fail the test of proportionality when confronted with the interferences they cause in concrete cases to individual religious freedoms protected under Article 9 ECHR (Part IV).

II. A DISTORTION OF LAICITE

In many ways, the 2010 ban appears like the next logical step to the 2004 prohibition. And yet, this article will show that the reasoning behind the new Act has strayed away from the concept of laïcité which inspired the earlier ban. The contours of laïcité are restricted to public services or public officials where the presence of the State requires religious neutrality. No such demands of neutrality have ever been required under the French legal system from ordinary citizens in ordinary public places. As will be demonstrated in this section, banning the burqa altogether in all public places is therefore not a manifestation, but rather a distortion, of laïcité.

French secularism or laïcité is usually defined as a system in which there is a separation between religion and the State.Footnote 30 But French secularism has always been thought to be compatible to some degree with state intervention in religious matters. Indeed the principle of separation between religion and State, proclaimed by the law of 1905,Footnote 31 coexists with the principle of freedom of conscience, also asserted in the 1905 Law. French secularism therefore does not convey any hostility or even indifference towards religion. On the contrary it was devised as a means to ensure the free exercise of religion by all citizens. To the extent required by the principle of freedom of conscience, the principle of separation between religion and State may be loosened. The French State will for example fund private religious schools under contract.Footnote 32 Whilst such support for religion may seem at odds with the principle of separation between religion and State, it is actually in harmony with the 1905 legislative framework as long as such intervention is deemed necessary to protect freedom of conscience. Arguably, non-involvement of the State in private religious education would put religious parents at a disadvantage since only non-religious parents could benefit from the free state system of secular education while religious parents would need to pay high fees in order for their children to receive an education that reflects their religious convictions.Footnote 33 To ensure full respect for the religious convictions of parents and put an end to a conflict between secular France and Catholic France, the French State under the Debré 1959 Law now provides substantial financial assistance to private (religious) schools that have entered into a contract with the State.Footnote 34 The mere fact that the French State intervenes in matters of religion does not necessarily go against the core features of French secularism, as long as these interventions can be said to strengthen freedom of conscience. One fails to see however how the intervention of the French State to ban the burqa will reinforce freedom of conscience. There may be an assumption whereby the burqa is the manifestation of a group ideology the Salafist school of thought against which individuals should be protected by the State.Footnote 35 But as will be argued later on, evidence of group pressures on individuals would then need to be put forward for such a rationale to be supported.

Beyond individual freedom of conscience, the search of a ‘common good’, of a ‘civil religion’ runs through French history and also explains why at times laïcité may well be seen as being compatible with state intervention in matters of religion. Michel Troper traces this French tradition of a state morality back to the French Monarchy:

To make politics autonomous required the subordination of the religious by the affirmation of a divine right of the King independent of the views of the Church. Each King was thus designated by God from which the duty of absolute obedience followed. (…) The royal power thus had to affirm itself independently and eventually in opposition to the Church but it was able to do so on a religious basis. The idea that the role of the sovereign State at least includes propagating essential values if not articles of faith was never completely abandoned in France even when the State became secular.Footnote 36

If this tradition of state values has survived the shift to the Republican State, its foundation is now clearly defined by opposition to religion. It manifests itself in the positive side of laïcité, which carries its own teaching and its own places of worship (town halls, official state buildings, state schools).Footnote 37 Today it is asserted in order to maintain a sphere free of the influence of the Church and is consequently restricted to the confines of the State's natural domain of public agents and public services. With its extension to the whole of the public sphere, the 2010 ban therefore does no more than seek to protect a state areligious identity as it strives to strengthen the exercise of individual religious freedom.

Whatever interpretation of the concept may be used, the 2010 ban therefore steps outside of French traditions on laïcité. Unsurprisingly, the special committee set up to consider the issue of the wearing of the full veil had to admit that the concept of laïcité was not relevant to the discussionFootnote 38 and the government's text which led to the 2010 law did not rely on the notion. By contrast, the supporters and opponents of a ban on religious symbols at school each embodied one version of laïcité. Whereas the contours and meaning of laïcité were thus at the heart of the debates surrounding the 2004 Act, laïcité was no more than a political slogan in 2010.

For the detractors of the 2004 ban, the prohibition of religious symbols throughout school premises, whether worn by staff or by pupils was already a step too far. These advocates of an ‘open laïcitéFootnote 39 considered that religious neutrality could and should be required from public agents and removed from public premises but that it should not extend to users of those services. Consequently, in a school context, laïcité would be a reason to object to religious symbols being displayed in the classroom or worn by teachers but could not be invoked against manifestations of religious freedom by pupils. Indeed whereas the former—directly or indirectly—reflect the State's attitude towards religion, the latter mainly convey allegiance to individually held religious beliefs.

In addition to the diversity of its meanings within the French context, the principle of laïcité may also vary in its application across States. For example, despite the clear connection with the State, the presence of crucifixes in state schools is a regular occurrence in Italy where the principle of laïcité is construed as encompassing the Catholic heritage of the nation rather than as a way of resisting it like in France.Footnote 40 Crucifixes in Italian state schools recently survived a challenge before the ECtHR. The Grand Chamber held in the Lautsi case that the mere presence of crucifixes did not amount to a violation of Article 2 Protocol 1 of the Convention protecting parents' right to ensure that their children receive education and teaching that conforms with their own religious and philosophical beliefs nor did it raise any separate issue in respect of Article 9 of the Convention protecting freedom of religion and conscience.Footnote 41 This conclusion is not to suggest however that the ECtHR prefers an Italian secularism to a laïcité ‘à la française’. The Grand Chamber's decision is not about the correct meaning of laïcité:

[it] is not for the court to rule on the compatibility of the presence of crucifixes in state school classrooms with the principle of secularism as enshrined in Italian Law (para 57).

Rather the Court's assessment focused on the reconciliation of crucifixes with the principle of pluralism. Having regard to the wide margin of appreciation granted to Member States in this area,Footnote 42 the Grand Chamber went on to hold that the crucifix merely constitutes a passive religious symbolFootnote 43 which, put in perspective with the openness of Italian state schools towards other religions,Footnote 44 cannot in itself amount to a violation of Convention rights.

It will be interesting to examine whether the wide margin of appreciation granted to Member States in respect of the principle of secularism and its consequences would be sufficient to secure the fate of the French 2010 ban on the burqa in Strasbourg.Footnote 45 Suffice to note here how different the concept of laïcité may be in France and Italy, to the point, in the Italian specific context, of allowing what would be construed by all in France as the exact denial of laïcité: an endorsement of religion (and indeed of a particular religion) by the State.

In the case of teachers, the link to the State is only indirect. If teachers as public agents are emanations of the State, as individuals, they are also holders of fundamental rights, including that of freedom of religion. Would the wearing of a headscarf by a teacher in a state school therefore necessarily contradict the idea of separation between State and religion that the notion of laïcité implies or should it be construed as an expression of the teacher's individual faith? This individual dimension prompted Quebec to moderate the demands of laïcité against public staff and allow the wearing of headscarves by civil servants as long as the headscarf did not interfere with their tasks and mission. Conceptually, the comparison with Quebec reveals once moreFootnote 46 how accommodating towards religion the concept of laïcité may be.Footnote 47 But the comparison also highlights the strikingly different historical and sociological approaches towards religion in Canada and France respectively. Concerned from the outset to ensure a harmonious cohabitation between different religious communities—Catholic and Protestant—Quebec has always been willing to accommodate ‘reasonable’ religious claims.Footnote 48 The concept of laïcité in this context has always been devoid of any positive content itself.

In France on the other hand, where the fight was historically against Catholic forces perceived as anti-republican and conservative, laïcité was not only constructed as a legal tool to manage the diversity of religious beliefsFootnote 49 but also, at least in some of its social and political narratives, as a concept conveying a positive belief in itself to be opposed to Catholic forces. Given this positive side of laïcité,Footnote 50 the absence of religious symbols in France is regarded in itself as an emblem of a state philosophy—to be reflected if not celebrated in certain key national events and key national institutions and respected by public agents.Footnote 51 In France therefore the divide between an ‘open’ and ‘closed’ version of the concept of laïcité Footnote 52 coincides with the divide between employees and users of public services. Even supporters of an ‘open’ version of laïcité will in France deny public servants the right to express their religion lest they betray the state philosophy they are bound to be seen to adhere to. Adopting an ‘open’ interpretation of the concept of laïcité, the Conseil d'Etat has consistently held that public servants are tied to a strict duty of neutralityFootnote 53 but simultaneously, until the 2004 ban, it considered on the other hand that as users of a public service, pupils should be allowed to wear religious symbols at school subject only to the requirements of public security and public order. The case law that ensued was criticized by someFootnote 54 for its inconsistencies. If the state of the law appeared incoherent to some, it was because divergent appreciation of the principle of laïcité could occur from one school to the other, from one student to the other depending on specific circumstances.Footnote 55 These local variations seemed in contradiction with the unified force of the principle of laïcité—which etymologically comes from the Greek term laos, meaning unified people/society—and which historically, under a ‘closed’ conception of the notion, is associated with the centralized characteristics of the French State. Moreover heads of schools and teachers resented the powers forced upon them and the media attention that their decisions provoked. Gradually, legislative action thus appeared more and more indispensable. Based on one of the recommendations of a report drafted by a Committee known as the Stasi Committee,Footnote 56 the 2004 ActFootnote 57 was passed and the ‘closed’ version of laïcité proclaimed in all state French primary and secondary schools. Despite the generality inherent in the ‘closed’ version of laïcité, the 2004 prohibition is restricted to primary and secondary schools of the state sector—thus leaving universities and higher education institutions as well as private schools outside the scope of the Act.

This restriction of the 2004 ban to state schools lies at the heart of the justification of the 2004 legislation and ties the 2004 ban to the concept of laïcité. The principle of laïcité has indeed a particular force and meaning in the context of education and of children.Footnote 58 Since the reforms of Jules Ferry,Footnote 59 schools through free, compulsory, public education for all have become the symbol of integration for all into the Republican State. In that sense, schools are at the epicentre of laïcité.

The French view school as the perfect institution to teach future citizens to exploit their faculties of reason and to help them exercise freedom of thought. (…) Freedom of thought ensures that pupils enjoy the right to independently re-examine beliefs received from family, social group and society as a whole. This way a person can freely adhere to these beliefs, adapt them or turn from them to something else.Footnote 60

In France, the ideal of a ‘common school’ is thus diametrically opposite to the British model—be it at times merely an aspiration—of a microcosm of society where pupils are encouraged to be involved in their local community and exposed to the diversity and problems of the world.Footnote 61 In France, the ideal school—be it again merely an aspiration—is a haven, safe from the turmoil of the world, a place of culture where a common intellectual quest and discussion of concepts transcends everyday life and everyone's differences.Footnote 62 The prohibition of religious symbols which are perceived as signs of diversity (if not division) at school is consistent with this idea/ideal that knowledge and culture by contrast can achieve universality:

“the subject who accedes to the truth simultaneously and immediately breaks away from any self-centeredness; he/she realises the opposition between a universal consciousness and a subjective, mysterious and obscure unconscious mind.”Footnote 63

Confined to state schools, the 2004 prohibition of ostentatious religious can therefore be construed as an application of the principle of laïcité. Taking the prohibitive stance outside of schools and targeting not just civil servants but any passer-by, the new restrictions on individual religious freedoms under the 2010 Act by contrast fall outside of the bounds of laïcité. If the 2010 ban is a manifestation of laïcité, its wide ambit is unjustifiable:

If the laïc State is neutral, if the principle of neutrality of public services imposes absolute constraints on public agents who are not allowed to express the slightest religious conviction, it is for the sake of users' and citizens' right to believe or not to believe. In this laïc setting, seeking to regulate the expression of religious freedom outside of public services and independently of any threat to public order is problematic.Footnote 64

It confuses laïcité (which implies the separation of State and religion) with secularisation (which describes the decreasing influence of religion in society).Footnote 65 It blurs the distinction between the normative and the descriptive and extends unduly the realm of the law. This unduly wide scope of the prohibition explains why part of the opposition abstained from voting in favour of the ban. The Socialist Party wished the ban to be limited to public services. Instead, the 2010 law extends the prohibition to all public places. As a result, laïcité can no more be invoked to justify the ban than the ban can be used to criticize the French model of laïcité. The two phenomena are totally unrelated. If laïcité is not at stake, what therefore could be the basis for a prohibition? The Committee reporting on the wearing of the full veil suggested that the full veil amounted to a violation of broader Republican values:Footnote 66 equality, liberty and fraternity. Of the Republican values referred to by the Committee, the government relied explicitly on the concepts of dignity and equality in the proposal which led to the law. But as we will show below, these do not offer a more secure basis for the 2010 law.

III. A PATERNALISTIC VIEW OF DIGNITY AND EQUALITY

Fighting the burqa was described in France as a combat for equality and dignity for women. However in this section, I will argue that the ban is actually not about promoting women's dignity and equality. The enforcement of a prohibition against autonomous decisions made by adult women is a paternalistic and outdated view of women that reverses feminist achievements and that will worsen the marginalization that it is said to be combating.

During the Parliamentary debates leading to the ban, all saw the full veil as an unacceptable oppression towards women:

All of us are against the burqa. All of us are fighting for women's dignity and for promoting equality between men and women. This is not where the disagreement lies. But as far as we're concerned we see it as extremely important that the law should have a strong legal basis (and therefore that the ban should have a more limited scope).Footnote 67

However, if the burqa does violate women's dignity, isn't it logical and indeed desirable to extend the prohibition to the whole of France? The scope of the 2010 Act would therefore suggest that dignity rather than laïcité is the concept underlying the prohibition against the burqa. The question raised is then whether the burqa does indeed amount to a violation of women's dignity. The lack of empirical evidence to support Parliament's assumption that women's dignity is curtailed by the wearing of the full veil is striking.

The case for a ban for the sake of dignity was also made in 2004 to justify the prohibition of ostentatious religious symbols in French state schools. It was thus reported in the Stasi CommissionFootnote 68 prior to the 2004 legislation that young girls from impoverished areas known as the ‘cités’ were pressurized into wearing the headscarf by their family or by young male adults from their neighbourhood. Providing for a neutral zone at school was seen as the only way to ensure that these young girls had a space where their freedom not to wear the veil could be exercised. Even then, a general ban may have appeared disproportionate given that in the majority of cases,Footnote 69 the wearing of the hijab was the result of a voluntary choice. Assuming that dignity was a legitimate justification for the 2004 ban, why not—if young adult women were subjected to similar family or social pressures—protect women's dignity more fully and take the prohibition further to the streets and all public spaces?Footnote 70 However, the legislator in 2004 took the view that the presumption of vulnerability could not easily be applied to people over 18.Footnote 71 Clearly departing from this position, the 2010 ban therefore stands in opposition with the previous 2004 Act.

In 2010, the concept of dignity is clearly used to protect adult women despite and against themselves and to ban practices chosen freely. Before the 2004 ban was passed, the Commission Stasi set up to draft the preliminary report had produced examples of coerced wearing of the headscarf. By contrast, the superficial research carried out by the ‘full veil Committee’ on the reasons behind the wearing of the burqa could at most reveal an influenced choice:

Indeed, there is some kind of pressure in wearing the burqa but it is not an external social pressure exercised by an Imam or by family members. It is more of a self-imposed pressure by the woman herself. (…) Women wearing the burqa see it as a sign of increased Islamic religiosity, the mark of membership to an elite, to a proper Islam susceptible to guide other fellow Muslims.Footnote 72

In other words, the little evidence gathered revealed at most an ‘influence’—mostly through reading the internet—rather than a ‘coerced’ decision to wear the burqa. If we were to discard influenced decisions as not being the exercise of genuinely free choices, how many—if any—of our decisions would still qualify as expressions of free will? More crucially, even if there were to be no room for true freedom, this moral/philosophical determinism should be no obstacle to maintaining an illusion of freedom and autonomy at the heart of our legal systems.Footnote 73 The social pressures that may limit our individual freedoms should not be an excuse for adding state interferences and pressures. The lack of substantial clear empirical evidenceFootnote 74 to support the claim that decisions to wear the burqa are coerced choices is matched by a similarly lack of evidence to the contrary. However, the lack of evidence either way does not put the terms of the alternative between banning and allowing the burqa on the same standing. Unless coercion is proven to have taken place, a presumption of autonomy must be posed. By reversing this presumption, the 2010 Act fundamentally disturbs civil liberties and human rights protection which first and foremost safeguards individual liberties—however illusory—against illegitimate interferences from the State and its agents. It also crudely suggests that autonomy, feminism and religious beliefs can never be reconciled.Footnote 75

To undermine the importance of the legal shift, supporters of the 2010 Act have sought to establish a connection between the 2010 prohibition and previous case law based on dignity. But I will argue that the connection is unconvincing. Whether relating to laïcité or dignity, the 2010 Act cannot relate to an established French legal tradition. On the contrary, on both counts, it signals a radical and worrying shift in approaches. The supporters of the 2010 ban argue that the burqa relegates its wearers to an inferior status incompatible with French notions of equality and women's dignity. By veiling her face completely, the veiled woman would deny her own identity and deprive herself from social contacts. Relying expressly on the work of Emmanuel Lévinas,Footnote 76 the reasoning underscores the social and philosophical value attached to communication which an uncovered face, open to dialogue, would symbolize. But the fundamental question remains: how can departing from this philosophy violate the veiled woman's dignity if the different philosophy she embraces is freely chosen? Of course, dignity has been invoked in the past to strike down consensual arrangements. In the famous case of Commune de Morsang,Footnote 77 the Conseil d'Etat held void contracts whereby dwarves had consented to being part of a ‘show’ involving them being thrown up in the air. These agreements despite being consensual were held to be contrary to human dignity. Save for bioethics legislation, the concept of dignity is however rarely used to oppose consensual practices. The case of Commune de Morsang has remained isolated and involved an ex-post balancing process of the indirect pressures exercised by the remuneration provided to the participating dwarves against the low public interest involved in having ‘throwing of dwarves’ shows available.

By contrast, the ban on the burqa applies in all circumstances save for the limited exceptions of private places—where it is not needed—and places of worship. Moreover, unlike in the dwarves' case, the decision to wear a burqa is not prompted by any promise of remuneration and covers a myriad of motivations. Reducing them all to one—the subordination of women—is necessarily too crude. It also carries a (negative) value judgment on the decision to wear the burqa which would arguably be better left to social conventions than the law. It is fair to say that absolute prohibitions imposed in the name of human dignity in spite of the complexities of participants' feelings and motivations have at times been pronounced in French Law. Article 16–7 of the French Civil Code for example prohibits on that ground voluntary surrogacy arrangements, whether commercial or not, whatever the circumstances. But the general prohibition of surrogacy, itself often controversial,Footnote 78 would be no justification by analogy for a general ban on the burqa. Indeed, whereas there is no recognized fundamental right to a child, there is an uncontested individual right to freedom of religion.Footnote 79 The Conseil d'Etat itself thought that the concept of dignity could not legally justify a general ban on the burqa. Footnote 80 Denying adults' choices in the name of dignity is problematic when autonomy is more and more regarded as an essential component of dignity.Footnote 81

Besides, in the case of the full veil, one may suspect the French legislator of hypocrisy:

Strangely enough what indeed seems to disturb critics the most is the voluntary veil, voluntary manifestation in public rather than the imposed veil. But as it is unassailable per se precisely because it is indeed voluntary, it will be criticized for being what it is not, ‘veiling by constraint’.Footnote 82

The wearing of the burqa may for many signal archaic practices which diminish the feminist achievements of the twentieth century. But fighting it with paternalistic measures may all the same go against the feminist tradition of claiming equal rights with men and rebutting the presumption that women cannot make free choices for themselves. Long-term effects of the ban may therefore worsen rather than improve women's dignity. Moreover, the situation of veiled women can only deteriorate after a ban. Penalizing women who wear the burqa does not liberate them. There is a concern at European level that a general ban on the burqa would backfire: Commissioner Thomas Hammarberg, Council of Europe Commissioner for Human Rights, thus took the view that banning women who wear the burqa from public institutions/places like hospitals or government buildings may result in them avoiding such places entirely.Footnote 83 Integration will not be improved by the ban. A report from the Open Society FoundationFootnote 84 already reveals that since the debate on the face veil began in France, 30 of 32 burqa-wearing women interviewed had experienced verbal abuse, and some had also been physically assaulted. As a direct result they preferred to limit the amount of time they spent outside the home, the NGO found. Consequently, the European Parliament adopted both a recommendation and a resolution whereby Member States are advised not to legislate against the wearing of the full veil.Footnote 85

A general ban on the burqa does not therefore liberate veiled women but increases their stigmatization and isolation. Nor does it genuinely seek to do so. The dignity which is to be protected is in reality less that of the veiled woman than of other non-veiled citizens. Indeed the argument has been made that by shunning social contacts, veiled women are refusing to treat non-veiled citizens as equals and thereby encroaching onto their dignity. In our societies of intense communication, the woman who rejects the gaze, handshakes or services of male fellow passers-by, colleagues, doctors or teachers distances herself from modernity and offends social conventions. But is a legal prohibition the answer to such social dysfunction?Footnote 86 Are we to legislate to prohibit all practices that appear socially shocking asks David Koussens?Footnote 87 Can the right not to be offended rival a right to express one's religion? In its brief decision of October 2010, the Conseil constitutionnel suggested that legislation banning socially disturbing practices could be promulgated on the new ground of ‘social ordre public’. The ban on the burqa would be legitimate and constitutionally sound not because it seeks to protect laïcité, dignity or equality—which indeed are not referred to by the Conseil constitutionnel—but because the full veil would put the French social backbone, the French ‘vivre ensemble’ into jeopardy. However, this article will argue that this new legal basis represents an inflated and unconvincing conception of public policy.

IV. AN INFLATED CONCEPTION OF PUBLIC POLICY

Public policy has always been a valid reason for limiting individual freedom. If wearing the full veil violates public policy, a legislative reaction to ban its display will be legitimate. But how could a prescription of what constitutes socially acceptable head-wear amount to legislative protection of public policy? In this section, I will argue that the 2010 ban on the burqa relies on an illegitimate and inflated conception of public policy. The ban is not a reaction to any threats to public order or public safety. Nor does it fit within the broader trends throughout immigration laws in EU Member States to restrict individual religious freedom for the sake of national cohesion.

Has the protection of public policy turned into the protection of the conformity of appearances? Has France, ‘la Patrie des droits de l'homme’—the ‘land of human rights’—as it likes to call itself turned into the ‘land of blinkered thinking’—le ‘pays de la pensée unique’? As explained above, the 2010 Act represents an unprecedented and worrying expression of state morality. Such a move should be strongly condemned. But the risk of a slippery slope where the ban on the burqa could evolve for example into a ban on the ‘mini-skirt’ and then turn into a general positive list of acceptable clothing cannot be seriously entertained. Social norms may be more prescriptive in Paris than in London as to what amounts to ‘correct’ colour matching of garments but the law is no more likely to move into the territory of individual fashion in France than it is in Britain. The ban on the burqa only found its way through the legislative process because the wearing of the full veil was seen as a radical and extreme practice and the covering of the face was described as radically different from the covering of the body.Footnote 88 Because the intrusion of state morality appears at the margin, to condemn what is described as ‘extreme’—the complete dissimulation of the face, the full veil as opposed to a more moderate veil—and to oppose what appears as a sign of religious extremism—the salafist school of thoughtFootnote 89 as opposed to a moderate acceptable Islam—the ban on the burqa still superficially adopts the usual mould of public policy. It does not seek to prescribe what is acceptable but erects a barrier against practices which step outside the limits of the tolerable.

As a reaction against the extreme, as a limit to objectionable practices, the 2010 Act superficially seems to fit in with traditional legal reasoning. Philosophically and politically, it seems to support a modern and moderate form of liberalism in line with John Rawls' thinking.Footnote 90 Politically and philosophically, the 2010 Act would not embody an aggressive form of laïcité but, by seeking to eradicate the most archaic forms of religious manifestations and retain liberal religious traditions, it would promote a peaceful compromise between modern ideals and (religious) traditions.Footnote 91Laïcité indeed is not inherently contrary to Rawls' notion of consensus and justice. Khaled Beydoun has claimed that:

because secularism functions as France's guiding comprehensive doctrine, to the exclusion of a panoply of other worldviews adhered to by its citizens, an overlapping consensus of just governance cannot be had.Footnote 92

While this may be true of the most rigid accounts of laïcité, dominant in the narrativeFootnote 93 of the concept, the presentation of laïcité as an exclusivist concept does not reflect the nuanced ways in which it has been implemented in law.

Nevertheless, scratching underneath the surface, one has to acknowledge that the reasoning adopted under the 2010 law brings laïcité as a narrative into the realm of the law. Relying purely on political strategies and slogans, the new law is in my opinion flawed both in terms of its sociological premise and of its legal basis. The new ban cannot be justified because first and foremost the premise on which the legislative prohibition relies is wrong: empirical research has suggested that in most cases, the decision to wear the burqa is inspired by a personal quest for meaningFootnote 94 and identity rather than by an extremist religious position.

It is important to analyse subtly the relationship that individuals have with religion in order not to confuse religion as resource and support and religious radicalisation where religion becomes the unique source of truth and perspective on the world.Footnote 95

The decision to wear a full veil rarely conveys the imprisonment into religion associated with religious radicalization. Fully veiled women do not necessarily see the world through the unique prism of religion. And when elements of a religious radicalization can be detected, they do not generally carry any political agenda susceptible to threaten public policy but merely seek religious transformation and authenticity.Footnote 96

In order to capture these legally harmless but socially disturbing practices, the concept of public policy has been enlarged so as to include ‘a set of fundamental common social features, of common requirements and guarantees’. To some extent, this redefinition of core common values ‘around an ethic of surveillance which overcomes the ethic of autonomy’ feeds into a broader modern worrying trend which is not specific to France.Footnote 97 But this idea of a ‘social ordre public’ represents a distortion of ordre public which radically puts civil liberties in second position and public policy in first. It therefore amounts to what I see as the most fundamental flaw of the new law. Under the new legislative framework, the priority is no longer to protect individual freedoms save where a threat to security or other conflicting rights are present but rather to ensure that socially common fundamental standards are complied with.Footnote 98 Public policy thus becomes a standard in its own right and insidiously empowers the majority to sweep away human rights whenever their manifestation is offensive to the majority of citizens. The restriction of this ‘social ordre public’ to fundamental social values is of little consolation given that the majority alone—through its parliamentary representatives—can decide what behaviours and practices fall within or without this fundamental core of social values. Surprisingly, the Conseil constitutionnel Footnote 99 nevertheless implicitly gave credit to this notion of ‘social ordre public’ by referring to Article 5 of the 1789 Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen which states that ‘the legislator is only entitled to edict prohibitions against acts which are harmful to Society.’ This article in its negative phraseology was designed to restrict state interferences. Ironically, it has now thus become a source of justification for one of the most intrusive pieces of legislation passed in France.

Admittedly, there are other instances where the State has interfered with individual freedoms for the sake of public morality: the regulation of nudism and pornography for example fall under that category. However in these cases, the chosen path was to regulate and restrict these socially disturbing practices rather than prohibit them altogether. Until the 2010 ban, a similar approach was adopted in relation to the burqa. Prior to the 2010 law, a set of texts was already in place to prohibit the wearing of the burqa in many contexts: at school, in respect of school pupils or staff under the 2004 previous ban;Footnote 100 in public services in respect of public officials;Footnote 101 in the vicinity of demonstrations,Footnote 102 to quote but a few examples.Footnote 103 Moreover, there were many other instances provided for in specific legislative texts, regulations or case law where fully veiled women were to temporarily uncover their face either for security reasons or in exchange for a public service requiring identification. It is the extension under the new legislation of all these specific restrictions and prohibitions to the whole of the public space which marks a radically new turn in the French approach. Far from embodying a French legal tradition, the 2010 ban on the burqa therefore runs counter to a long-standing commitment to individual liberty as expressed by Article 4 of the Declaration.Footnote 104 Methodologically and legally, the shift is colossal.

However, the promoters of the new law here again argue that this social version of public policy belongs to the French legal tradition. According to the defenders of this social public policy, other instances of a ‘social ordre public’ would be noticeable in immigration law:Footnote 105 family members are thus only allowed to join a foreign migrant in France if they belong to a ‘normal’ family unit under French terms. In effect, polygamous marriages, however valid they may be according to private international rules, will be disregarded: only one of the wives of a polygamous husband settled in France will thus be able to invoke the right to be re-united with her husband.Footnote 106 In the 1993 Act relating to ImmigrationFootnote 107 French values are thus imposed against minority held beliefs and the protection afforded to the foreign immigrant's family life is restricted to forms of family life which qualify as ‘normal’ in the host country. The 1993 Act simultaneously seeks to improve integration of immigrants into French society and to eradicate the practice of polygamy which for many in France appears to be degrading for women. The reasoning here echoes the goals of the 2010 ban on the burqa which indeed seeks both to eradicate a practice that the majority would find degrading for women and to impose the host country's views of normality in the hope of fostering better integration of minority groups into French society. Didn't the Conseil d'Etat itself prepare the way for the prohibition when it denied French nationality to a veiled woman for want of assimilation into French society?Footnote 108

However, I contest the perceived similarities between previous legislation or case law and the new 2010 ban. Whereas the 1993 legislation and the Conseil d'Etat case law addresses the situation of prospective migrants or candidates to French nationality, the 2010 ban targets anyone present on the French territory, whether already a French citizen or a mere tourist. With respect to the former, a set of common values may constitute a legitimate threshold to set for those applying to a special status in the host country such as permanent residency or citizenship.Footnote 109 In the UK, pre-entry English language tests were introduced in November 2010 as a prerequisite for entry of migrants from outside the European Union. Debates about the need to promote ‘integration‘Footnote 110 and avoid disjointed societies were thus at the forefront in a vein reminiscent of discussions on the other side of the Channel.Footnote 111 As T Asad argues, ‘the idea that a successful modern nation-state rests on a dominant culture that encodes shared values is now commonplace’.Footnote 112

This shared conception is a tie between multiculturalism and secularism, two concepts which are often presented as conflicting with each other and which are usually associated with the British and French models of integration respectively. One should not exaggerate the differences between multiculturalism and secularism:Footnote 113 both strive to achieve a balance between majority (culturally Christian views) and minority beliefs. Like multiculturalism and secularism, the respective approaches to religious diversity in Britain and France are not as far apart as sometimes stated either. Indeed, neither country espouses one model fully: both countries borrow to varying degrees from both multiculturalism and secularismFootnote 114 and both countries strike the balance between national cohesion and conflicting human right requirements more or less favourably for the latter. If the 2010 French ban thus calls into question the commitment to the right to religious freedom, the extension in Britain of pre-entry language tests to spouses of UK citizens raises the question as to whether integration requirements infringe fundamental rights to family life.

Notwithstanding the resonances in immigration policies and debates on either side of the Channel and the interactions on each side of the Channel between the models of multiculturalism and secularism, the 2010 ban on the burqa I would argue stands out. To tighten requirements on entry into the French territory or French citizenship is one thing—which the UK is also familiar with. But to then claim to monitor the behaviour of everyone on the French territory and make sure they do not stray away from common values and do not adhere to the burqa is a completely different ambition, which cannot relate to British or indeed to French traditions. The set of common values is no longer one of the requirements on which the award of a particular privilege is dependent; it then becomes a permanent imperative that restrains everyone's moves and gestures in all (public) places.Footnote 115

Curiously, however, the absolute scope of the prohibition has been defended as a sign of its legitimacy. By contrast to the balancing approach recommended by the Conseil d'Etat and criticized for its complexity, the clear-cut solution contained in the law was praised for its ‘clarity’, ‘purity’ and ‘courage’.Footnote 116 The 2010 ban does convey a clear message: the burqa is not only unwelcome in France; it is now also illegal. However, there is no ‘purity’ but on the contrary sheer confusion and distortion of legal concepts—be it laïcité, dignity, equality or public policy. There is no ‘courage’ but astute political strategies in turning the social discomfort felt towards the burqa into a legislative position which is likely to drain the support of the extreme right and secure votes for the elections held in April 2012. The real courage would be to take up a politically and socially unpopular position against the ban and in favour of civil liberties. The unqualified nature of the ban may have increased its popularity in France. It will however in my view be the cause of its downfall before the European Court of Human Rights in Strasbourg.

V. LIKELY INCOMPATIBILITY WITH THE EUROPEAN CONVENTION ON HUMAN RIGHTS

Whereas the Conseil d'Etat had given an optimistic prognosis for the fate of the 2004 ban before the ECtHR,Footnote 117 it was extremely sceptical as to the compatibility of the 2010 law with the requirements of the ECHR.Footnote 118 On the first anniversary of the coming into force of the Act, around 300 women were reported to have been fined.119

There is no doubt that if their fines are upheld by higher Courts, the case will be taken to the ECtHR. A French Muslim property dealer, Rachid Nekkaz, said he had created a fund to pay women's fines and legal challenges, and encouraged ‘all free women who so wish to wear the veil in the street and engage in civil disobedience’.Footnote 119 Since then, a French couple who claimed to have been forced to emigrate to Britain to avoid sanctions under the French ban are reported to have filed a petition to the ECtHR.Footnote 120

The compatibility with the ECHR could also be raised before national courts as French courts have construed Article 55 of the French Constitution as allowing international treaties direct effect before French domestic courts.Footnote 121 Despite the blessing conferred by the Conseil constitutionnel's decision, the Cour de cassation could still therefore set aside the legislation on the basis that it violates Article 9 of the ECHR which protects the right to religious freedom.Footnote 122 But even if the Cour de cassation—as seems more likely—applies the 2010 Act, it is very doubtful that the legislation will survive a challenge before the ECtHR. Before Strasbourg, it is likely that the 2010 ban would be held to infringe Article 9 rights to religious freedom and that the infringement, assuming it is regarded as necessary to serve a legitimate aim, would then be held to amount to a disproportionate interference.

To escape censorship by the ECtHR, the 2010 French Law would first need to be proven to pursue a legitimate aim. Dignity and equality between genders have been implicitly recognized by European case-law but this may not (or no longer) be seen by the ECtHR as justification for paternalistic measures in the absence of immediate threats to public order.Footnote 123 Would the notion of a social ordre public save the French position in Strasbourg as it did before the Conseil constitutionnel? The risk of conflict has been upheld as a reason to restrict religious freedom in TurkeyFootnote 124 but it is doubtful that the risk posed by the full veil will be judged sufficiently tangible in the French context.Footnote 125 A broader notion of public policy does not exist under the case law of the ECtHR but arguably, under the wide margin of appreciation granted to Member States in areas where religious/secular national identities are at stake, this idea could be encompassed under the concept of laïcité. In that sense, laïcité would probably qualify more easily than other rationales as a legitimate aim pursued by the ban. One may question, however, whether laïcité is at stake where regulation of religious manifestation occurs outside of public services; I have argued above that it is not. But previous ECtHR case law suggests that the European Court will not enter into a discussion of what the notion of laïcité itself entails but on the contrary take for granted state claims in that respect.Footnote 126 However, the Court will be far less deferential when it comes to ascertaining how bans pronounced for the sake of laïcité have been enforced. It will thus assess whether the infringements of individual religious freedoms are proportionate to the alleged requirements of laïcité. A State may exceed its margin of appreciation by taking disproportionate measures in the name of national identity.Footnote 127 France therefore will not be able to escape the test of proportionality in Strasbourg and when it does, the 2010 ban in all its absolute clarity is highly unlikely to pass the test.

It is surprising that this lack of proportionality did not incur censorship by the Conseil constitutionnel. Disappointingly, the Conseil constitutionnel carried out a very superficial examination of the law and was content that it had passed the requirements of proportionality in view of the gradual system of sanctions put in place by the law.Footnote 128 But a measured system of penalties is no guarantee that the prohibition itself is in the first place a proportionate response. One may hope that the ECtHR will apply the proportionality test more convincingly by putting into the balance the aim(s) sought by the ban on the one hand and the restriction to religious freedom it causes on the other. The most recent case against Turkey, Ahmet Arslan Footnote 129 supports this view. In that case, the prohibition of a peaceful religious event in the streets was held to amount to a disproportionate interference with religious freedoms. The principle of laïcité, even in the Turkish tense context, could not justify an absolute prohibition of religious public display, in the absence of a present proven threat to public security. Several factors, according to the ECtHR, pointed to a lack of necessity for the prohibition in Ahmet Arslan: the targeting of mere ‘citizens’ (para 48), rather than public agentsFootnote 130 or teachersFootnote 131 who could be reasonably submitted to more stringent restrictions; and the extension of the prohibition to ‘ordinary public places’ such as public streets (para 49), rather than public buildings where the connection to the State could warrant a greater obligation of religious discretion. The Court also remarked that the plaintiffs were members of a group devoid of influence or political ambitions (para 51).

The facts of Ahmet Arslan would not fall under the scope of the French 2010 legislation. Under Article 2 of the French Act,Footnote 132 full covering of the face in the context of cultural or religious specific events escapes the prohibition. It is merely day-to-day wearing of the burqa which is forbidden under the Act. Nonetheless, the reasoning adopted by the European Court in Ahmet Arslan against the Turkish prohibition could easily be transposed to the French ban. Just like the Turkish prohibition, the French Act problematically affects ‘ordinary citizens’ in ‘ordinary public places’. By analogy, the French ban on the burqa is therefore likelyFootnote 133 to be regarded as a disproportionate reaction to a minority practice which no evidence connects to any security threats or social unrest, except for a feeling of social discomfort. If the Strasbourg Court has been more lenient towards state interferences where these were opposed to groups—such as Islamist political parties in Turkey—that threatened the political liberal order,Footnote 134 the lack of evidence linking the wearing of the full veil to a political agenda of its wearers/promoters makes it very unlikely that the Strasbourg Court will show the same leniency towards the French 2010 ban.

Moreover, the stigmatization of the Islamic faith—which the less overt title finallyFootnote 135 chosen for the 2010 law cannot hide—may give rise to a violation of Article 9 combined with Article 14 of the Convention. The 2004 ban was also clearly inspired by headscarf affairs and thus clearly targeted at Islam. But the prohibition against ostentatious religious signs at school could objectively apply to symbols of other religions. Other religions on the other hand will escape the 2010 ban. As for other non-religious instances where someone may be arrested for covering his/her face in public places, it is likely that the list of exceptions provided for in Article 2Footnote 136 would then apply. In effect, the ban is not likely therefore to be applicable in any other instances but the wearing of the burqa. Despite its neutral language, the 2010 ban inescapably qualifies as a piece of legislation restricting a particular type of religious practice. This religious dimension was implicitly acknowledged in the Conseil constitutionnel's decision which ruled that the ban was compatible with the French Constitution provided that the prohibition was not enforced in places of worships or their vicinity.Footnote 137 As such, the legislation may be regarded as discriminatory towards Islam and consequently may constitute a violation of Article 14 which provides for anti-discrimination protection in respect of convention articles (in the present case: Article 9). The argument that only extreme unacceptable forms of IslamFootnote 138 would fall under the prohibition could not prevail since the ECtHR has asserted many times that it is not up to Member States to assess the legitimacy of particular religious beliefs.Footnote 139 Indeed, religious freedom would be seriously hampered if only moderate forms of beliefs and practices acceptable to the State were covered. Similarly, the argument that the wearing of the burqa would not be a ‘religious’ manifestation since there is no clear religious requirement to cover one's face under Islam is bound to fail. Regardless of the controversies in their interpretation, the wearing of the burqa originates in scriptural authorities in the Qur'an Footnote 140 and is subjectively strongly felt by the women who wear it as carrying a religious meaning. It is therefore likely that legal challenge to the 2010 ban as violating Article 9 (and also possibly Article 14) ECHR would succeed before the ECtHR.

Nevertheless, proponents of the ban do not consider criticisms of it—and even the possibility of an adverse ruling by the ECtHR—as a reason for abandoning it.Footnote 141 Departing from a European consensus (itself possibly emerging with Belgium and possibly The Netherlands now following suit) or from national tradition is not—the argument goes—a flaw in itself. Otherwise, no legal changes could ever be implemented. But lack of grounding in traditional legal concepts may be less an indication of innovation than of imperfection when in the absence of this legal tradition, the very necessity of the ban cannot be justified. Indeed that is why the promoters of the ban have shown endless energy in seeking to root the new law into previous texts and concepts. Anne Levade, whilst defending the innovative approach of the new legislation and undermining the importance of respect for tradition, thus seeks to anchor the new law into the 1789 Declaration on the Rights of Man and the Citizen:

the terms of the Declaration could support this (innovative) notion of ‘social ordre public’ in so far as the authors of the Declaration were striving to establish a framework for the relationships between Man/the Citizen on the one hand and a constituted society on the other.Footnote 142

The social dimension in place in 1789 seems to me a tenuous argument for linking the new concept of ‘social ordre public’ to an established French tradition of civil liberties. But these efforts to demonstrate legal continuity are interesting; they reveal a legitimate desire to look beyond political majority for justifying the ban. Coherence within the legal system is a quality required for the ‘morality of law’.Footnote 143 Political majority alone cannot legitimate infringements of minority rights.

In any case, censorship by the ECtHR, as explained above, would actually not be incurred because of the arguably illegitimate aims sought by the law but because of the way these aims are being implemented. More likely than not, it is the lack of proportionality between the infringements caused and the aims sought by the prohibition that would lead to a condemnation of France in Strasbourg. And this requirement of proportionality, despite its complexity, should in my view be embraced. It is an opportunity to balance conflicting interests and take into account a diversity of viewpoints. It is the best protection against logics of antagonism and the best vehicle for ensuring that multiculturalism/secularism models foster reconciliation rather than generate confrontation.

VI. CONCLUSION

Why then don't the French like the burqa?

As in 2004, the prohibition of a certain type of religious symbols was seen as the answer to force integration of minority groups. As such, the 2010 ban may tie in with current debates on multiculturalism and integration across Europe, including in the UK. But this political timeliness is not enough to ground the law in the traditions of secularism and feminism. The absolute scope of the law which covers the whole of the public space betrays both secularist and feminist tradition by leaving no scope for the expression of difference within the public sphere and by leaving no room for subjective views of dignity by veiled women. None of the arguments invoking the concepts of laïcité, equality, dignity or ‘social ordre public’ as evidence of a unique French manifestation of secularism and feminism are convincing.

The 2010 ban falls outside of the boundaries of the notion of laïcité. Even the most virulent forms of laïcité cannot stretch beyond public services or public agents and be applied to places and people who in no way emanate from the State. If they did, laïcité would no longer be a mode of Church/State relationship which leaves room for the manifestation of individual beliefs but would become a vehicle for State indoctrination. Nor is the 2010 ban about protecting women's dignity and equality. Such paternalistic views of dignity cannot be enforced where no conclusive empirical evidence suggests that the full veil is in most cases worn as a result of coercion. If they were, individual autonomy and liberty in the public sphere would simply be denied. Finally, the 2010 ban cannot rely on the notion of ‘social ordre public’. While the 2010 law is indeed about promoting common values and fostering a way of ‘living together’, ‘un vivre ensemble’, in a legal system committed to human rights, this goal cannot be enforced at the cost of civil liberties. Proportionate interferences with religious freedoms may be justifiable but the absolute negation of individual rights—be it in respect of a garment that appears so alien and extreme—cannot in law be upheld. Despite the recent approval bestowed by the French Constitutional council, it is predicted that the law will fall foul of European Convention requirements. Even if —given the wide margin of appreciation that the European Court grants to Member States in these areas—laïcité may well (but wrongly in my view as argued above) qualify as a legitimate goal pursued by the ban, the 2010 ban is bound to fail for want of proportionality between the aim sought and the absolute and unqualifiedFootnote 144 restriction on religious freedom it carries.

Secularism, laïcité and multiculturalism as it has been saidFootnote 145 are all tools designed to manage diversity. As such, they can never endorse measures which aim at erasing differences altogether. For the sake of laïcité and multiculturalism as well as for human rights, it is to be hoped that the 2010 ban will not become the new model for Europe.

References

2 Fadel, MH, ‘Public Reason as a Strategy for Principled Reconciliation: The Case for Islamic Law and International Human Rights Law’ (2008) 8 ChiJIntlL 1Google Scholar.

4 See Willaime, J-P, ‘Le Voile intégral: approches européennes et réactions nord-américaines’, in La Laïcité à l’épreuve du voile intégral, La Documentation française (2010) 5365Google Scholar.

5 For a comparative analysis of burqa bans in France, Belgium and concept legislation in The Netherlands, see van der Schyff, G and Overbeeke, A, ‘Exercising Religious Freedom in the Public Space: a Comparative and European Convention Analysis of General Burqa Bans’ (2011) 7 EuConst 424–52Google Scholar.

6 Loi no 2010–1192 interdisant la dissimulation du visage dans l'espace public of 11 October 2010, JO 12 October 2010.

7 Loi visant à interdire le port de tout vêtement cachant totalement ou de manière principale le visage of 1 June 2011, JO Le Moniteur 13 July 2011.

9 See <http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/10316696> accessed 13 September 2011.

10 <http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/8464124.stm> accessed 4 June 2012.

11 Bhandar, B, ‘The Ties that Bind Multiculturalism and Secularism Reconsidered’ (2009) 36 Journal of Law and Society 325CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

12 See Gaudreault-DesBiens, J-F and Karazivan, N, ‘The “Public” and The “Private” in the Common Law and Civil Law Traditions. Legal Traditions as Reasoning Templates for the Regulation of Religion’ (2011) Law and Religion e-JournalGoogle Scholar, available at <http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1905138>.

13 The term ‘burqa’ will be used throughout this article in a broad sense to include any forms of Islamic veils covering the face that is burqa in a strict sense as well as niqab.

14 Loi no 2004–228 of 15 March 2004, JO 17 March 2004, 5190.

15 ECHR 4 December 2008 Kervanci v France 31645/04 and Dogru v France 27058/05, RTD civ (2009) 1049–52.

16 See Report of July 2005 by Mme Hanifa Chérifi, quoted in the Report on the full Islamic veil, infra (n 25) 91.

17 Loi no 2010–1192, JO 12 October 2010, 18344.

18 Conseil Constitutionnel 7 October 2010, JO 12 October 2010, 18345.

19 Cf A Chrisafis, ‘Nicolas Sarkozy says Islamic veils are not welcome in France’ The Guardian 23 June 2009 available at <http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2009/jun/22/islamic-veils-sarkozy-speech-france> accessed 27 September 2011.

21 M Parris, ‘Never Mind What the Woman Thinks. Wearing the Veil is Offensive to Me’ The Times 27 August 2005, available at <http://newsgroups.derkeiler.com/Archive/Soc/soc.culture.african.american/2005–08/msg00663.html> accessed 30 June 2012.

22 On this issue of whether resort to law is the proper response, see Tariq Ramadan, in conversation with members of the Pew Research Forum in the United States: ‘The answer is not to come with law to prevent people … It's not the way forward … Speak more about education, psychology … we have to be very cautious not to translate every sensitive issue into a legal issue. We are wrong by doing this’, available at <http://pewforum.org/Politics-and-elections/A-conversation-With-Tariq-Ramadan.aspx> accessed 4 June 2012, quoted in R Grillo and P Shah, ‘Reasons to Ban? The Anti-Burqa Movement in Western Europe’, Max Planck Working Papers 12-05, <http://www.mmg.mpg.de/publications/working-papers/2012/wp_12-05/> accessed 30 June 2012.

23 Rapport sur les solutions juridiques d'interdiction du port du voile intégral 25 March 2010, JCP 2010, act 406, comments by A Levade.

24 Conseil d'Etat, Report (n 23) 35.

25 Mission d'information sur la pratique du port du voile intégral sur le territoire national, Report submitted to the President of the National Assembly 26 January 2010, JCP 2010, act 142, comments by A Levade.

26 Conseil d'Etat, Report (n 23) 29.

27 A similar proposal had already been submitted by the party UMP 5 February 2010 (proposition de loi AN no 2283).

28 The Law was voted by an overwhelming 335/1 majority before the Lower House of the French Parliament and a 246/1 majority before the Upper House.

29 Conseil Constitutionnel 7 October 2010, (n 18).

30 See J Rivero, ‘La notion juridique de laïcité’ (Recueil Dalloz 1949) 137.

31 JO 11 December 1905; On the origins of the Act, see Foyer, J, ‘La Genèse de la loi de séparation’ in La Laïcité (2005) Archives de Philosophie du droit vol 48, 7583Google Scholar.

32 Under the 1959 Debré Law. See Poucet, B (ed), La loi Debré, paradoxes de l'Etat éducateur? (CRDP 2001)Google Scholar.

33 Naturally, the dichotomy between ‘religious parents’ and ‘non-religious’ parents is too crude. There are various degrees of religiosity and many parents with strong religious convictions choose the state school system whereas many parents with a vague religious commitment choose to send their children to Catholic schools. See B Chélini-Pont, ‘The French Model: Tensions between Laïc and Religious Allegiances in French State and Catholic Schools’, chap 7 in Myriam Hunter-Henin (ed), Religious Freedoms and Education in Europe (Ashgate 2012) 153–69.

34 See n 32.

35 See n 96.

36 Troper, M, ‘French Secularism or Laïcité’ (1999–2000) 21 Cardozo Law Review 1272–3Google Scholar.

37 Cf suggesting a bank holiday dedicated to Laïcité on 9 December, date of the 1905 Act on the separation of Church and State, Vitel, PMP from the party UMP (Var), Question to the Prime Minister no 68744, JO 19 January 2010, 443Google Scholar.

38 See Report, (n 25) 95–122. See also, Report by the Conseil d'Etat, (n 23) 17.

39 See Willaime, J-P, Le Retour du religieux dans la sphère publique. Vers une laïcité de reconnaissance et de dialogue (Editions Olivetan 2008)Google Scholar.

40 See A Ferrari, ‘De la politique à la technique: laïcité narrative et laïcité du droit. Pour une comparaison France/Italie’ in B Basdevant-Gaudemet and F Jankowiak (eds), Le Droit ecclésiatique en Europe et à ses marges XVIIIe–XXe siècles (2009) 333–45.

41 In the case of Lautsi v Italy (App no 30814/06), the Grand Chamber, overruling the first Chamber's decision of 3 November 2009, held on 18 March 2011 that the presence of crucifixes in the classrooms of Italian state schools was acceptable despite the principle of laïcité contained in the Italian Constitution.

42 ibid para 70.

43 ibid paras 72 and 73.

44 ibid para 74.

45 See Part IV.

46 See leading to the same conclusion the comparison between the French and the Italian notions of laïcité (n 40).

47 On the Canadian context, see the Bouchard/Taylor Committee Report on reasonable accommodations, esp chap 7 (Bibliothèque et Archives nationales du Québec 2008) available at <http://archive.wikiwix.com/cache/?url=http://://www.accommodements.qc.ca/documentation/rapports/rapport-final-integral-fr.pdf&title=Rapport%20final%20int%C3%A9gral> accessed 30 June 2012.

48 ibid chap 6 on ‘Interculturalism’.

49 On the liberal historical origins of laïcité, see Weil, P, ‘Why French Laïcité is Liberal’ (2009) 30 Cardozo Law Review 2699Google Scholar. See also note 36.

50 See n 37.

51 See CE avis 3 May 2000 Mlle Marteaux, RFDA 2001, 141, Conclusions R Schwartz.

52 For further illustration of the divide, see the contrasting views of D Schnapper, La Démocratie providentielle. Essai sur l’égalité contemporaine (2000) and J-P Willaime (n 39).

53 Cf CE 27 November 1989 Avis, RFDA 1990, 1, J Rivero; AJDA 1990, 39–42; Bell, J, ‘Religious Observance in Secular Schools: A French Solution’ (1990) 2 Education and the Law 121–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

54 See for example, X Darcos' comments reported in MP Clément, Rapport n 1381, JOAN, Doc Session 2004, 9 and 10. Contra, Durand-Pringorgne, C, ‘Le Port des signes extérieurs de convictions religieuses à l’école : une jurisprudence affirmée…, une jurisprudence contestée’ (1997) RFDA, 151–72Google Scholar.

55 Cf emphasizing the need to take into account the circumstances of the case, CE 27 November 1996 (3 cases) JCP 1997 II 22 808, B Seiller.

56 Rapport de la Commission présidée par M. Bernard Stasi de réflexion sur l'application du principe de laïcité dans la République submitted 11 December 2003, La Documentation française (2004).

57 Loi no 2004–228 of 15 March 2004 (n 14).

58 Cf JAN Condorcet, Cinq mémoires sur l'instruction publique (1791), eds C Coutel and C Kintzler (Flammarion 1994).

59 Cf Barnard, HC, Education and the French Revolution (Cambridge University Press 1969)Google Scholar. The presence of documentation relating to the Ferry Laws on the official site of the French Senate illustrates the importance of the Ferry laws in the French psyche: available at <http://www.senat.fr/evenement/archives/D42/index.html> accessed 18 March 2012.

60 Baubérot, J, quoted by D McGoldrick, Human Rights and Religion. The Islamic Headscarf Debate in Europe (Hart Publishing 2006) 76Google Scholar.

61 See Williams, K, ‘Religious Worldviews and the Common School. The French Dilemma’ (2007) 41 Journal of Philosophy of Education 675–92CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

62 Debray, R, Ce que nous voile le voile. La République et le sacré (Gallimard, Paris, 2004) 32Google Scholar.

63 G Bachelard, ‘Valeur morale de la culture scientifique’ in Didier Gil (ed), Bachelard et la Culture Scientifique (Presses Universitaires de France 1993) (author's translation).

64 Schwartz, R, Interview published in La Laïcité à l’épreuve du voile intégral, La Documentation française no 364 (2010) 17Google Scholar (author's translation).

65 For a comparable distinction but in respect of pluralism/plurality, see Beckford, J, Social Theory of Religion (Cambridge University Press 2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Report (n 25) 95–122.

67 J-P Sueur, JO Sénat CR 15 September 2010, 6755 (author's translation).

68 Stasi Report (n 56) section 3.3.1, p 57; section 4.2.2.1, p 99 and ff.

69 See Liogier, R, Une Laïcité légitime. La France et ses religions d'Etat (Médicis Entrelacs 2006)Google Scholar.

70 Arguably, the prohibition should then even extend to the private sphere. The restriction to the public sphere however broadly construed stands in contradiction with the announced goal to protect women's dignity. This restriction suggests that the prohibition is less about protecting dignity than it is about protecting ‘Republican values’ under an inflated conception of public policy (see Part III).

71 But the 2004 prohibition applies to pupils over 18 who are still in secondary schools whether before or after Baccalauréat (A levels). This uniform application of the 2004 ban throughout state schools suggests that the prohibition of religious symbols is less about protecting dignity than it is about enforcing laïcité throughout the public school sector (see Part I).

72 Interview of Sami Amghar before the ‘Committee on the full veil’ Report (n 25) 467 (author's translation).

73 See de Béchillon, D, ‘Voile intégral: éloge du Conseil d'Etat en théoricien des droits fondamentaux’ (2010) RFDA 467–8Google Scholar.

74 See on this crucial question of empirical evidence, <http://www.ugent.be/re/publiekrecht/en/news/faceveil.htm> accessed 20 March 2012.

75 See Nancy, J-L, ‘Church, State, Resistance’ (2007) 34 Journal of Law and Society 7CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Also on the tensions between ‘piety’ and ‘polity’, Motha, S, ‘Veiled Women and the Affect of Religion in Democracy’ (2007) 34 Journal of Law and Society 139–62CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

76 E Lévinas, Ethique et Infini (Fayard 1982).

77 CE Ass 27 October 1995 Commune de Morsang-sur-Orge, also known as ‘l'affaire du lancer de nains’, Grands arrêts de la jurisprudence administrative, 17th ed, n 98. Comments by O Cayla, ‘Le Coup d'Etat de droit’ (1998) Le Débat 108.

78 See M Hunter-Henin, ‘Surrogacy. Is There a Room for a New Liberty between the French prohibitive Position and the English Ambivalence’ in M Freeman (ed), Law and Bioethics (OUP 2008) 329–57.

79 See Part IV.

80 Conseil d'Etat, Report (n 23) 20.

81 See for example, CEDH 17 February 2005 KA and AD v Belgium, no 42758/98. For a theoretical perspective, Dworkin, R, Taking Rights Seriously (Harvard University Press 1977) 272–3Google Scholar.

82 Liogier, R, ‘Laïcité on the Edge in France: Between the Theory of Church-State Separation and the Praxis of State-Church Confusion’ (2009) 9 Macquarie Law Journal 40Google Scholar.

85 Recommendation and Resolution no 1743 both entitled ‘Islam, Islamism and Islamophobia in Europe’ of 23 June 2010 available at <http://assembly.coe.int/Main.asp?link=/Documents/AdoptedText/ta10/EREC1927.htm> accessed 4 June2012 and <http://assembly.coe.int/Main.asp?link=/Documents/AdoptedText/ta10/ERES1743.htm> accessed 4 June 2012.

86 Admittedly, one does so to prohibit for example the display of nudity in public spaces but I will argue that the ban on the burqa goes much further. See Part III.

87 Koussens, D, ‘Sous l'affaire de la burqa… quel visage de la laïcité française?’ (2009) 41 Sociologie et Sociétés 328CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

88 See French MP Lionel Luca, Parliamentary debates of 19 May 2010, National Assembly.

89 See n 96.

90 See J Rawls' idea of an ‘overlapping consensus’ in Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press 1993) 150–4.

91 See Lévy, B-H, Le Testament de Dieu (Bernard Grasset 1979)Google Scholar.

92 Beydoun, KA, ‘Laïcité, Liberalism and the Headscarf’ (2008) 10 Journal of Islamic Law and Culture 191CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

93 For a distinction between laïcité as a narrative and laïcité as a legal concept, see A Ferrari (n 40). And more generally, Cover, R, ‘Foreword: Nomos and Narrative’ (1983) 97 HarvLRev 4–5Google Scholar.

94 On the importance for human rights to study people's motivation in depth, see Vakulenko, A, ‘Islamic Headscarves and the European Convention on Human Rights: an Intersectional Perspective’ (2007) 16 Social and Legal Studies 183–99CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

95 Lamine, A-S, ‘Les Formes actuelles du retour du religieux’ in La Laïcité à l’épreuve du voile, La Documentation française no 364 (2010) 32Google Scholar.

96 Amghar, S, ‘Le Salafisme en France: de la révolution islamique à la révolution conservatrice’ (2008) 3 Critique internationale 95113CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

97 See Foessel, M, Etat de vigilance. Critique de la banalité sécuritaire (Broché 2010)Google Scholar.

98 See D de Béchillon (n 73) 470.

99 Conseil constitutionnel of 7 October 2010 (n 18), considérant 3.

100 See n 14.

101 CE 3 May 2000 avis Mlle Marteaux (n 51).

102 Décret no 2009-724 of 19 June 2009.

103 For a full list see the Conseil d'Etat's Report (n 23).

104 The Conseil constitutionnel made a merely symbolic reference to art 4 which states that ‘Liberty is the right to do everything that does not cause harm to others. Thus, each and every human being enjoys natural liberties that know of no other bounds but the very same rights and liberties enjoyed by other members of society. These boundaries must be determined by the legislator.’ (author's translation)

105 See Levade, A, ‘Le Conseil d'Etat aux prises avec le voile intégralJCP 2010, 754Google Scholar.

106 See Decision of the Conseil constitutionnel no 93-325 DC of 13 August 1993.

107 Loi no 97-1027 of 24 August 1993 (loi relative à la maîtrise de l'immigration et aux conditions d'entrée, d'accueil et de séjour des étrangers en France) JO 29 August 1993.

108 CE 27 June 2008 Mme Machbour, no 286798.

109 Contra, Mullally, S, ‘Civic Integration, Migrant Women and the Veil: at the Limits of Rights’ (2011) 74 MLR 27–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

110 See ‘Citizenship Tests in a Post-National Era’ (2008) 10(1) International Journal of Multicultural Societies Special Issue.

111 Integration models of each country may thus not be so far apart as one sometimes thinks. But the emphasis on ‘common values’ may be more characteristic of the French Republican tradition, see Bowen (n 10) 11.

112 T Asad, ‘Trying to Understand French Secularism’ in H de Vries and LE Sullivan (eds) Political Theologies: Public Religions in a Post-Secular World (Fordham University Press 2006) 495.

113 See p 1.

114 Often described as a true multicultural system, Britain actually also seeks at times a superseding unity: see for example debates on Britishness and British values, S Lee, , ‘Gordon Brown and the “British Way”’ (2006) 77 The Political Quarterly 369–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

115 With the exception of places of worship open to the public, see Conseil Constitutionnel 7 October 2010, considérant 5, (n 18).

116 See A Levade, praising the absolute scope of the law and criticizing by contrast the position recommended by the Conseil d'Etat for its complexity and its cautious approach,: ‘Le Conseil d'Etat aux prises avec le voile intégral’ (n 105); see also, Levade, A, ‘Epilogue d'un débat juridique: l'interdiction de la dissimulation du visage dans l'espace public validée!’, JCP 2010, 19781981Google Scholar.

117 CE 8 October 2004 Union française pour la cohésion nationale, no 269704.

118 Conseil d'Etat Report (n 23) 32.

121 See M Hunter-Henin, ‘France. Horizontal Application of Human Rights in France. The Triumph of the European Convention on Human Rights’ in D Oliver and J Fedtke (eds), Human Rights and the Private Sphere – A Comparative Study (Routledge-Cavendish 2007) 98–124.

122 Indeed, the Cour de cassation has shown in the past that it is audacious enough to challenge new legislative moves when other supreme French national courts have behaved with greater reverence towards Parliament. See M Hunter-Henin, ‘Constitutional Developments and Human Rights in France: One Step Forward, Two Steps Back’ (2011) 60 ICLQ 1–22.

123 See ECHR 17 February 2005 KA and AD v Belgium, no 42758/98 (but in the context of practices carried out in private).

124 ECHR Sahin v Turkey, App no 44774/98 [2004] 299 paras 97–8.

125 See n 135.

126 ECHR 4 December 2008 Kervanci v France, no 31645/04 and Dogru v France, no 27058/05 para 62.

127 See Brems, E, ‘Human Rights: Minimum and Maximum Perspectives’ (2009) 9 HRLRev 359–65Google Scholar.

128 Conseil constitutionnel 7 October 2010, (n 18), considérant 5.

129 See ECHR 23 February 2010 Ahmet Arslan and Others v Turkey, 41135/98, D.2010, 682–4, J-P Marguénaud.

130 See ECHR 26 September 1995 Vogt v Germany, 1996-IV, no 14, 21 EHRR 205; ECHR 20 May 1999 Rekvéni v Hungary, 25390/94.

131 See ECHR 15 February 2001 Dahlab v Switerland, 42393/98; ECHR 24 January 2006 Kurtulmuş v Turkey, 65500/01.

132 See (n 137).

133 Depending of course on the circumstances of the case put forward to Strasbourg as the ECtHR does not examine Acts in abstracto but in relation to their application to a particular case.

134 ECHR Refah Partisi v Turkey, no 41340/98, 41343/88 and 41344/98 [2003] 37 EHRR 1.

135 On the advice of the Conseil d'Etat. See Report, (n 23) 21.

136 Art 2.2 of the 2010 law provides that the ban will not apply to instances where the covering of the face is prescribed by other legislative or regulatory requirements; is mandated by health or professional reasons; or occurs in the context of sporting, artistic or traditional events.

137 Conseil constitutionnel, (n 18), considérant 5.

138 This vision inspired the French parliamentary resolution adopted on 11 May 2010 (Ass Nat XIII législature, TA no 459; JCP 2010, act 551, comments by Anne Levade) in which the full veil is described as a radical practice that is contrary to the values of the French Republic.

139 See for example, ECHR 26 October 2000 Hasan and Chaush v Bulgaria, para. 78.

140 On these Quranic origins, Barlas, A, ‘Believing Women’ in Islam: Unreading Patriarchal Interpretations of the Qur'an (University of Texas Press 2002) 53Google Scholar.

141 A Levade (n 105) 756.

142 ibid.

143 See Fuller, L, The Morality of Law (Yale University Press 1969)Google Scholar.

144 Save for the private sphere where the burqa however won't be felt needed.

145 See Part IV.