Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T11:11:47.517Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

THE ESSENCE OF EU CITIZENSHIP EMERGING FROM THE LAST TEN YEARS OF ACADEMIC DEBATE: BEYOND THE CHERRY BLOSSOMS AND THE MOON?1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2013

Dimitry Kochenov*
Affiliation:
Chair in EU Constitutional Law, University of Groningen, d.kochenov@gmail.com.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article scrutinizes the last ten years of the academic debate on EU citizenship law taking nine fundamental disagreements among scholars as starting points. It explores EU citizenship's relationship with three groups of issues of fundamental importance, including the place of this concept within the fabric of EU law, the influence of this concept on the essence of the Union as a system of multi-level governance, and its impact on the lives of ordinary Europeans. A large number of key works which influenced the Court and the legislator in the recent years is assessed to outline the likely direction of future research, as well as EU citizenship's future development. Although the literature on the subject is overwhelmingly rich and diverse, this article aspires to provide a representative sample of issues of interest for the framing of the concept at issue from a supranational perspective, necessarily leaving national literatures aside.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © British Institute of International and Comparative Law 2013

I. Introduction

More than half a billion Europeans holding a nationality of one of the 27 Member States of the European Union (EU) are EU citizens. Citizenship beyond the State, deemed impossible by Raymond Aron,Footnote 2 is here, and its importance in shaping the legal position of individuals is rising very rapidly, as it takes over a number of vital aspects of Member States' nationalities, shifts the jurisdictional boundary between national law and EU law, plays a pivotal role in the construction of jurisdiction by the Court of Justice of the EU (ECJ), influences our perceptions of identity, culture and social solidarity, and potentially changes the nature of States in Europe as well as the essence of the Union. With the recent EU citizenship case-law in mind,Footnote 3 it is clear that much more is to come. A ‘federal European citizenship’Footnote 4 is emerging. At this stage Member State nationalities and EU citizenship simply cannot be understood or studied separately anymore: the key starting point of EU citizenship analysis, to agree with Jo Shaw, is ‘to avoid thinking about [the two] as two separate and unrelated phenomena’.Footnote 5 The EU is turning into ‘a laboratory for differentiated citizenship’,Footnote 6 with all the positive and negative consequences of being at the avant-garde of an important transformation.

Analysing the development of EU citizenship law during the last ten years through the prism of the approaches to it adopted in the academic literature,Footnote 7 this paper recognizes the foundational role played by the scholars in the total make-over of the Union under the direct influence of EU citizenship. Upon the inclusion in the Treaties,Footnote 8 EU citizenship has been pushed forward mostly by a trio of factors: the ground-breaking work of the Judges of the ECJ and its Advocates General;Footnote 9 the academic commentary by those who saw important potential behind evasive formulations in the Treaties; and the legislators at both national and supranational level, as they started the on-going process of the Union's adaptation to the new reality of citizens' Europe.Footnote 10 All the three are profoundly interconnected. While case law and legislative developments receive a lot of attention in the literature, the evolution of the academic debate which largely informs the two,Footnote 11 has been somewhat ignored as of itself.Footnote 12

The most influential academic commentators in this field, such as Gareth Davies, Dora Kostakopoulou, Niamh Nic Shuibhne, Jo Shaw, Eleanor Spaventa, or Joseph Weiler, to name just a few, were never confined in their analyses to merely following the Court and the legislators, as they actively co-shaped the Union and its citizenship hand in hand with other actors. This is the key aspect of the academic legal profession in Europe. To agree with Jo Shaw, ‘the study of governance in the EU … is a constructive, rather than a deductive process’.Footnote 13 We are not dealing with those who are ‘right’ and those who are ‘wrong’. The evolving status quo would be better described by stating that one group was more successful in shaping socio-legal reality,Footnote 14 compared with the other, whose adherents advanced the arguments which were either less convincing or simply too timid, to deploy EU citizenship to its full potential.Footnote 15

II. Structure of the study: Nine disagreements in three groups

Lately there has been a true flood of EU citizenship literature in law and social sciencesFootnote 16 and the need for an overview of the key issues discussed by the leading scholars working in the field is now apparent. This paper approaches the myriad relevant sources by taking paradigmatic differences of opinion as starting points. This study is thus fundamentally different in structure from the leading preceding overview of EU citizenship literature by Dora Kostakopoulou, by which it is informed and inspired.Footnote 17 Dora Kostakopoulou's overview was organized around sketching five theoretical approaches to citizenship in the literature, and then to embrace one.Footnote 18 That the present analysis is in some way more patchy is partly informed by the consideration that EU citizenship is too multifaceted and, at the same time, too atypical in a number of ways, to reduce an approach to it to one overarching theory. While theoretically feasible, such ordering does not arise from the literature in its current state and risks turning a blind eye to an array of issues of fundamental importance. It is possible, however, to draw on the most important scholarly disagreements analysed individually, to come up with a tentative quilt-like and diverse picture of the whole. Emphasis on the key points of difference creates a better view of the richness of legal analysis surrounding the concept of EU citizenship and its likely development, allowing the detailed mapping of the multifaceted reality shaped by this concept, while minimizing, at the same time, the negative influences of the dogmatic normative standpoints embraced by some commentators.

Picking up the debate where Professor Kostakopoulou left it—ie at the scholarly discussion of the important judgments of the beginning of this centuryFootnote 19—the main body of this paper provides a critical overview of the last decade of evolution of legal thinking about European citizenship. These were ten overwhelmingly important years, where EU citizenship has definitely moved from a mere activator of other provisions in the Treaty—such as non-discrimination on the basis of nationalityFootnote 20—to combating non-discriminatory restrictions,Footnote 21 and, finally, acquiring the capacity to shape the material scope of EU law.Footnote 22 Crucially for its whole federal architecture,Footnote 23 the EU has acquired a possibility to defend its citizens from their own Member State of nationality in a number of situations previously deemed as wholly internal, ranging from defending the possession of the legal status of EU citizenship when it is likely to be lost with a nationality of a Member StateFootnote 24 to the protection of their ability to enjoy key rights associated with this status.Footnote 25 Yet, unable to supply a compellingly clear understanding of the scope of such rights,Footnote 26 let alone substantive understanding of justice and other essential principles on which the Union rests,Footnote 27 recent developments can also be viewed as making EU citizenship more vulnerable and problematic: ‘sour grapes’.Footnote 28

Notwithstanding the central place EU citizenship has come to occupy within the body of EU law, a huge number of issues at the core of this status remain open to contestation, fuelling scholarly debate. In fact, from the academic commentary it might seem that virtually nothing is yet settled in the EU citizenship field: the essential starting points of thinking about EU citizenship remain contested well into its adult age. Probably more importantly, however, EU citizenship analysis is at times informed by profoundly doctrinal starting points, forcing scholars not to see what they actually see, preferring purely dogmatic approaches to actual engagement with the new developments. Such Begriffjurisprudenz, permitting interpreting away the reality which does not suit particular doctrinal standpoints embraced by the author, is an important obstacle in the development of EU law and has implications stretching far beyond the EU citizenship law field.Footnote 29

Nine interrelated essential points of contestation will be presented in what follows (Sections III, IV and V), to prepare the ground for an attempt to come up with a coherent picture of EU citizenship arising from such key disagreements (Section VI). The nine essential points of contestation outlined roughly divide into three interrelated themes, namely, the legal meaning of EU citizenship; EU citizenship's role in the context of the Union's federal structure; and, last but not least, EU citizenship's role in the context of people's lives. Each of the three, in turn, divides into three sub-parts. So the first theme, the legal meaning of EU citizenship, covers the nature of this concept, its underlying logic and its place within the body of EU law (Section III). The second theme, revolving around the EU citizenship's legal effects within the context of the EU's federal structure, includes EU citizenship's relationship with Member State nationalities, its influence on the scope of EU law and the role it plays in framing the ECJ's jurisdiction (Section IV). The third theme, which, if not the most important, is no doubt the cause of the most heated disagreements, is confined to the analysis of the scholarly disagreements on the assessment of EU citizenship's effects in the context of people's lives, and covers EU citizenship's social side, the relationship of this concept with the identity politics of the Member States and EU citizenship's role for the citizens themselves, ultimately ending up with a question whether it is a ‘good thing’ or a ‘bad thing’: does it corrupt, or liberate the individual? (Section V).The final part (Section VI) makes an attempt to unite the main conclusions reached from the preceding discussion of academic disagreements about the nature of EU citizenship. As a result of this exercise, EU citizenship emerges out of the disagreements as an independent legal status profoundly affecting EU economic freedoms, the ECJ's jurisdiction and also the distribution of powers between the EU and the Member States, particularly in the field of the regulation of Member State nationalities. Its strongest points relate to the toning down of the Member States' grip on their nationals coupled with a serious broadening of the citizens' horizon of opportunities, thus actively promoting freedom. At the same time, a number of painful questions emerge, most fundamentally in relation to the lack of a conceptual basis for supranational citizenship, its failure to adhere to the ideals of democracy, justice, or equality and the likely negative effects of its core consequence, which is the undermining of the authority of the states without offering a way to fill an emerging gap (Section VI). The conclusion, besides underlining the imperfection of our current knowledge, argues for a more critical academic engagement with the topic (Section VII).

III. The legal meaning of EU citizenship

First, debate regarding the nature of EU citizenship is considered—how much is citizenship affected by the derivative mode of its acquisition? Secondly, the underlying logic behind the essence and operation of EU citizenship is contested—is it essentially a continuation of the classical market-oriented freedoms informing the European integration project from its very inception, or something else? If it is indeed a move away from the market, than what is EU citizenship's essential foundation? Thirdly, and flowing from the above, what should be the place of EU citizenship in relation to the specific economic freedoms? That is, what is its role within the body of EU law?

A. EU Citizenship's Nature

The story of scholarly disagreements about EU citizenship is incredibly rich and full of radically different assessments of the same law and identical facts. The legal meaning of EU citizenship is profoundly contested. According to Articles 9 EU and 20 TFEU, EU citizenship is derivative from the nationalities of the Member States in that one presumably cannot exist without another. The starting question is whether or not to make a distinction between the acquisition of EU citizenship (which is purely derivative) and its essence, which is potentially not, in that it accompanies the EU-level legal status and is not in any way based on the national law of the Member States. Here is where a cleavage in the literature emerges. While one camp of commentators, including Dora Kostakopoulou, Miguel Poiares Maduro and others,Footnote 30 submits that derivation is merely a determinant of access to the status, unrelated to the EU citizenship rights, other scholars, including Giuseppe Tesauro and Leonard Besselink, seem to believe that derivative acquisition profoundly affects the very essence of EU citizenship, hindering it from acquiring legal importance on its own, especially in terms of rights it would grant. In the words of Tesauro, ‘non esiste, né potrebbe allo stato ippotizzarsi, una nozione communitaria di cittadinanza, sì che le norme che ne prescrivono il possesso come presupposto soggettivo per la loro applicazione in realtà rinviano alla legge nazionale dello Stato la cui cittadinanza viene posta a fondamento del diritto invocato’.Footnote 31 In a co-written EuConst editorial Besselink goes even further in submitting that also ‘the kind of rights which the EU citizens resident in another Member State enjoys [sic] depend primarily on the law of the Member State’Footnote 32 and ‘the nexus of rights as granted by the Member States remains intimate’.Footnote 33

It seems that doubting the legal importance of European citizenship based on the fact that access to it is derivative is logically unsound: if ius soli citizenship is not better or worse that ius sanguinis citizenshipFootnote 34—there is no reason to claim that the same should not be valid for ius tractum (ie derivative) citizenship:Footnote 35 particular rules of access to the status have nothing to do with the existence of the status as such, let alone the rights associated therewith. Scholars disagreeing with those colleagues who overemphasize the derivative aspect in EU citizenship make a clear distinction between access to a legal status and its essence and contenu. This position was outlined with clarity by AG Poiares Maduro, as he then was, who indicated that ‘la citoyenneté de l'Union suppose la nationalité d'un État membre mais c'est aussi un concept juridique et politique autonome par rapport à celui de nationalité’.Footnote 36 Virtually all the ECJ case law on citizenship is a confirmation of the fact that access to the status of EU citizenship is always provided via the nationality of a Member State does not diminish the importance of the former status or the rights it brings.

In fact, derivation functions practically in such a way that not only does EU citizenship follow Member State nationalities, but the opposite is also possible. Crucially, EU citizens whose Member State nationality from which the status of EU citizenship is derived is put into question can potentially rely on EU citizenship in order to retain their Member State nationality. The ECJ ruled in Rottmann that the EU principle of proportionality applies in the situations ‘capable of causing [EU citizens] to lose the status conferred by Article 17 EC and the rights attaching thereto’,Footnote 37 which comes down to a possibility to force the states to confer/not to withdraw their nationality in certain cases where EU citizenship status is in danger.Footnote 38 This would never be possible, should the perspective adopted by Tesauro et al be accurate. Moreover, even where rights associated with EU citizenship and particular Member State nationalities seem to overlap this is not to be taken at face value: in terms of scale, EU citizenship provides for rights in the territory of the Union,Footnote 39 which is 27 times more than one jurisdiction, where Member State rights operate.Footnote 40 As Gianluigi Palombella observes, ‘this enables each of us to reconceive the horizon of our zeal capabilities (to recall Sen) beyond the limits of national citizenship and territory’.Footnote 41 Add to this the possibility to turn EU citizenship rights against one's own Member State of nationality (including when decisions on that very nationality are taken) and the story is complete. The fundamental distinction made between the legal essence of EU citizenship and that of the nationalities of the Member States—anticipated by Dora Kostakopoulou in her studyFootnote 42—provides a key for the understanding of the dynamics of EU citizenship evolution and the place of this concept in European law, as well as its interrelation with Member State nationalities.Footnote 43 In practice, EU citizenship no longer operates as a simple guarantor of the home country rule for those residing in a different Member State compared with their Member State of nationality, but adds, in the words of Besson and Utzinger, ‘a European dimension to each national demos’,Footnote 44 which certainly makes the perspective adopted by Besselink much less convincing. Ius tractum access does not mean ius tractum nature. The consequences of this are very far-reaching indeed. Drawing on an illuminating account provided by Gianluigi Palombella, this amounts to endowing the Union with direct legitimacy, which ‘becomes primary and no longer dependent of the legitimacy of states’.Footnote 45

Needless to say, the very rules on derivative access contained in the Treaties have met with scholarly opposition. Clear arguments have been made in favour of decoupling access to EU citizenship and Member State nationalities in the future. Positions adopted by Ulli Jessurun d'Oliveira and Dora Kostakopoulou are particularly enlightening in this respect.Footnote 46 In fact, it is more or less accepted in the literature that EU citizenship is incomplete unless it takes third-country nationals onboard in some form, thus moving beyond the confines of Member States' nationalities.Footnote 47

Now that the ECJ has clarified beyond any reasonable doubt that although the two are naturally fused together, EU citizenship is different in principle from the nationalities of the Member States, any mode of accessing this status can be chosen. Besides diminishing the harshness of apartheid européen,Footnote 48 this would do justice to EU citizenship which de facto seems to have outgrown its initial framework.Footnote 49 Analysis of the history of European integration also seems to point in this direction: third-country nationals legally present in the EEC theoretically could become the beneficiaries of free movement of workers provisions.Footnote 50 It certainly makes little sense to divide the territory of the Union with borders exclusively for the third-country nationals, recreating for this vulnerable categoryFootnote 51 all the problems which free movement of persons was intended to solve.Footnote 52 Moreover, EU citizenship does not even cover all Member State nationals.Footnote 53 Now that Member States nationalities and EU citizenship have started, conceptually, to part ways,Footnote 54 the logical arguments for the automatic exclusion of third-country nationals from the latter status becomes much less convincing.

B. The Underlying Logic of EU Citizenship

Once it is clear that EU citizenship is not affected in its essence by the derivative mode of its acquisition, the citizenship of the Union has to be placed within a broader context of the dynamic development of EU law. Notwithstanding numerous nods in the direction of the fédération européenne, as envisaged in the Schuman DeclarationFootnote 55 and the establishment of an ever closer union among the peoples of the Member States,Footnote 56 the maturing of EU law has been largely associated with the establishment of the Internal Market.Footnote 57 What then is the relationship between EU citizenship and the market? And if EU citizenship is a break away from purely economic considerations, a potentially more important issue arises, namely, what is its rationale then? The very essence of the Union is in this question.

While connecting EU citizenship with the market in the most direct way was a popular approach at the initial phase of EU citizenship evolution,Footnote 58 at this stage, the ECJ has made it absolutely clear that EU citizenship does not per se have market-oriented aims and also plays an important role in the lives of those who are not economically active in the context of the Internal Market. The mainstream approach in the literature, which is fully supported by ECJ case law and secondary EU law instruments consists in characterizing EU citizenship as a Grundfreiheit ohne Markt,Footnote 59 or lying ‘outwith the immediate confines of the single market’.Footnote 60 Among the proponents of this approach are Ferdinand Wollenschläger, Dora Kostakopoulou and numerous others. A concurrent reading, which emphasizes the important role of the Internal Market behind the framing of EU citizenship is promoted, inter alia, by Niamh Nic Shuibhne, who argues, essentially, that EU citizenship remains largely a market citizenship.Footnote 61 Although the now classical distinction between Marktbürger and citoyen in EU law is not challenged,Footnote 62 Niamh Nic Shuibhne looks for what could actually inform EU citizenship's development and returns to the economic roots of European integration in answering this question. She submits that ‘[n]o polity, constitutional or otherwise, exists just for the sake of existence. “What” is grounded in constitutionalism is the substantive point. And what the EU constitutionalizes is a framework within which functions, primarily, a market’.Footnote 63

It is absolutely true that a set of underlying values and principles is indispensable for a polity to function. Yet, would the market alone, even if it is a ‘constitutional market’Footnote 64 provide a sufficient base for the supranational citizenship? Among a myriad of ideal citizenship models formulated by lawyers and political scientists,Footnote 65 the presumption has always been that pure considerations of prosperity provide too thin a foundation for the development of what could aspire to becoming a ‘real’ citizenship. Should we believe, following Wollenschläger, Kostakopoulou et al, that EU citizenship is indeed a citizenship beyond the market—and the ECJ certainly pushes us in this direction—it is necessary to find an alternative basis for it, rather than prosperity and economic freedom: it cannot be left suspended in thin air. To be sure, the moral starting point of the European market integration—that of avoiding yet another war, and dealing with the heritage of the cataclysms of the first half of the last century which lay behind the market at its inception is gone, removed by the ‘paradox of success’.Footnote 66 To concur with Joseph Weiler, the market is now alone, with no ‘moral imperative’ and no ‘mantle of ideals’.Footnote 67 An ideal of justice among other substantive principles seems to be required to build a sound European citizenship upon.

In the quest for the likely foundations—if not justificationFootnote 68—of European integration which could provide EU citizenship with an indispensable core, at least three concepts are discussed in the literature. The idea of justice, focused on by Andrew Williams in his recent ground-breaking work;Footnote 69 political representation, in the work of Joseph Weiler;Footnote 70 and the idea of equality, analysed elsewhere in detail.Footnote 71 All three concepts—especially, an organic combination of the three—could in theory provide a sound foundation for a supranational citizenship stretching beyond the market. In practice, however, they do not.Footnote 72

The picture that emerges out of these studies is discomforting. As Andrew Williams has brilliantly demonstrated, the problems plaguing the key principles of law in the Union could have much deeper roots than one would expect,Footnote 73 going as far as the flaws in the foundational philosophy of the European integration exercise,Footnote 74 leading to an impoverished idea of justice,Footnote 75 and a highly proceduralized vision of the principles of law, threatening to strip the latter of even its most essential substance.Footnote 76 Looking behind the façade of purely rhetorical values, scholars find a worrying void. According to Weiler, ‘oggi, noi accumuliamo la retorica dei valori anche se, nelle parte operative dei trattati, vi diamo poca importanza o lasciamo prevalere ambiguità’.Footnote 77 Williams concurs: ‘[t]he principles which the ECJ proceeded to develop through its case-law have not been based on fundamental values that have any coherence, even though the consistent use of the rhetoric of certain values might suggest otherwise.’Footnote 78 The values and virtues problem in the EU is apparent.Footnote 79

When the underlying philosophy is ‘based on a theory of interpretation (of original political will) rather than a theory of justice’,Footnote 80 all the fundamental principles of law are in danger. In the citizenship context, a glance at the principle of equality is particularly informative, since equality is one of citizenship's key elements.Footnote 81 Drawing on the work by Gareth Davies,Footnote 82 Gráinne de BúrcaFootnote 83 and numerous other commentators, in a recent study dedicated to the functioning of the principle of equality in the context of EU citizenship, the present author was bound to conclude that equality in the EU is not safeguarded, as any substantive understanding of the principle is lacking.Footnote 84

The situation is identical in the context of another major facet of citizenship—that of political representation—which seems to be equally undermined. The citizen, as Joseph Weiler demonstrated, ‘è ridotto a un consumatore di resultati politici’.Footnote 85 The possibility of active participation in politics at the European level proper is minimal—quite an obvious reality which no window-dressing in the form of non-binding citizens' initiative can hide.Footnote 86 Moreover, the ECJ does not even treat electoral rights as EU fundamental rights, as the case law abundantly demonstrates.Footnote 87 It thus seems right to claim that electoral provisions found in Part II TFEU are merely non-discrimination rights.Footnote 88

Citizenship thus came under attack at all the fundamental levels outlined, where one could most legitimately expect this status to play a fundamental role: justice, equality, and democracy. Key values of citizenship remain ignored in the Union. Worse still: no agenda exist to date to remedy the key deficiencies outlined. Having stepped into the citizenship world, the EU is still unable to cope with its birth defect, ie the strong market bias, which is logically inexplicable in the new situation, where citizenship and the Internal Market conceptually parted ways.Footnote 89 The analysis of the recent EU citizenship case-law of the ECJ entirely confirms Weiler's view that ‘[l]'aspetto problematico di questa giurisprudenza è che precisamente omette di compiere la transizione concettuale da una libera circolazione basata sul mercato ad una libertà basata sulla cittadinanza.’Footnote 90 Nic Shuibhne can thus be absolutely right in turning to the market in her search for the conceptual foundation of EU citizenship: neither justice, nor political participation, nor equality, can pass a reality check: in the future they could possibly gain in importance, but currently they fail to provide a sound basis for EU citizenship. Consequently, to refer to Andrew Williams once again, the EU is building on an ‘institutional ethos that lacks reasonable coherence and moral purpose’.Footnote 91 This is problematic well beyond the level of rhetoric, threatening to cause numerous problems in the future.

To say that EU citizenship has an underlying cornerstone supplied by the market, as Niamh Nic Shuibhne does, although factually correct in the sense that other perspectives are proven wrong, does not actually solve the conceptual problem of lacking moral purpose which is of no small importance, should citizenship be taken seriously. Or is it true, as submitted elsewhere that ‘EU citizenship, frankly, is hardly worthy of this glorifying term’?Footnote 92 Although it seems undisputable that the EU is a ‘citizenship-capable polity’,Footnote 93 a different perspective seems to be necessary. What is clear at this point is that although EU citizenship and the Internal Market have parted ways, which created ‘a fundamental freedom beyond the market’, this parting of ways has not, as of yet, been accompanied by the formulation of any fundamental principle of law, which would supply a moral essence or a durable principled foundation for EU citizenship.

C. EU Citizenship's Role within EU Law

The day-to-day functioning of EU citizenship does not seem to be much affected in the short term by the conceptual deficiencies it suffers from. The Court regards it as ‘the fundamental status of the nationals of the Member States’,Footnote 94 creatively applying the provisions of Part II TFEU and clearly recognizing EU citizenship's far-reaching potential. Unsurprisingly, EU citizenship started influencing the application of the market freedoms sensu stricto by affecting them through the scope ratione personae of EU law. With the entry into force of the Treaty of Maastricht the scope ratione personae of EU legal order was enlarged from less than 2.3 per cent of Member States nationalsFootnote 95 to 100 per cent. It follows that, as outlined with admirable clarity by Eleanor Spaventa, ‘any Union citizen now falls within the [personal] scope of the Treaty, without having to establish cross-border credentials’.Footnote 96 Consequently, the rhetoric of the ECJ claiming that the notion of EU citizenship was not designed to enlarge the scope of EU law,Footnote 97 when applied to the scope ratione personae, is, with all respect, simply nonsensical.Footnote 98 Here is where another important cleavage in the literature emerges. While a number of scholars, including Eleanor Spaventa and Oxana Golynker, welcomed the new interpretation of the scope of EU law in the light of EU citizenship also in the context of the economic freedoms—and not only in EU citizenship cases sensu stricto,Footnote 99—others maintain, in essence, that the economic freedoms should not be ‘contaminated’ by the new approach formulated in the context of the citizenship provisions, criticizing the Court for abandoning its pre-citizenship ratione personae testFootnote 100 to the effect of enlarging the number of economically active persons able to benefit from EU law.

After Maastricht, those workers who moved residence, not jobs, ended up covered by economic free-movement provisions—just as all other economically active EU citizens in cross-border situations.Footnote 101 The Court's new approach treats all economic activities with a cross-border element present differently from all non-economic activities within the scope ratione materiae of EU law. Charlotte O'BrienFootnote 102 and Alina TryfonidouFootnote 103 criticize the Court for updating its approach following the entry into force of the Treaty of Maastricht. O'Brien goes as far as to state that ‘the more appropriate assessment of a migrant whose State of work remains unchanged is arguably under [Article 21 TFEU]’.Footnote 104 Scholars in this camp find bringing workers who work and reside in different Member States within the scope of economic provisions ‘counterintuitive’,Footnote 105 craving to see more citizens and fewer worker-citizens to whom EU law would apply. This approach is profoundly problematic for a number of reasons, not least because it comes down to arguing for two different tests of the scope of the law to apply to EU citizens not depending on whether they are economically active or not in a cross-border situation (which is the current approach),Footnote 106 but whether their intentions are directly enough connected to the Internal Market.Footnote 107

According to Oxana Golynker and other commentatorsFootnote 108 who regard the Court's approach approvingly, the Court merely moved away from exercising an ultra vires activity of reading citizens' minds towards assessing the facts.Footnote 109 Golynker submits in this context that ‘it seems appropriate to classify Union citizens who exercised their right to free movement under Art. 18 EC but remained employed or took up employment elsewhere in the Community as Community workers’.Footnote 110 It is incontestable that de facto it is impossible to change the economic nature of someone's activity by swapping the places of employment and residence and that the direction of movement should not matter in the context of the Internal Market, which takes an area without internal frontiers as a starting point.Footnote 111

The dogmatic opposition to the Court's citizenship case law by those unwilling to see economic freedoms applied to EU citizens with ‘wrong intentions’ fails to convince. Upon the introduction of EU citizenship and the enlargement of the personal scope of supranational law to cover virtually everyone, the intentions-based reading of the Internal Market is no longer acceptable. EU citizenship became lex generalis covering the situations not caught by the economic free movement provisions.Footnote 112 Moreover, it is moving fast to play the same lex generalis role where the existence of a cross-border situation is not clearly articulated, ie when either someone's intentions, or the market-considerations as such, cannot possibly play any role, as we have seen in Ruiz Zambrano, for instance.Footnote 113 When Internal Market considerations still play a role, however, clearly it is not intentions but rather economic activity, which matters in deciding which provisions are to apply.

There is another side to the coin of EU citizenship affecting the scope of EU fundamental freedoms, however, which is, regrettably, frequently overlooked. EU citizenship not only enlarges the scope of such freedoms, but also potentially limits them. This is owing to, relative considerations, such as the ‘real links’ with the host Member State test first formulated in the EU citizenship case law for non-economically active citizens,Footnote 114 come to limit the scope of economic free-movement provisions. This is arguably what happened in Geven Footnote 115 and Hartmann,Footnote 116 where the grant of social advantages to economic migrants was subjected to a test of ‘real links’ with the society of the Member State in question.Footnote 117 In this context Síofra O'Leary is very convincing in deciphering the signs of ‘cross-pollenisation’ of EU citizenship and economic free movement of persons case-law, expressing a concern with the unwanted consequences of EU citizenship case-law for economic free movement provisions.Footnote 118 Drawing a clear dividing line between EU citizenship and economic free-movement case law, thus sticking to the ‘old-fashioned classification’Footnote 119 is problematic at this point. The two are much interconnected and are likely increasingly to influence each other's scope in the years to come.

IV. EU citizenship in the context of the EU's federal structure

There are three key academic debates addressing the role played by EU citizenship in the context of the relationship between the national and supranational legal orders in the EU, debates which are necessarily interrelated with the discussion above of the legal meaning of EU citizenship. The first focuses on the EU citizenship's relationship with the nationalities of the Member States. Are they in harmony or in competition—ie does the growing importance of EU citizenship affect the Member States' competence in the sphere of regulation of their nationalities and the contents of the latter? Asking the same question in a more general way, secondly, potentially brings the whole body of the law in Europe into a new perspective: what is the effect of EU citizenship on the delimitation of the scope of the law of the EU and of the Member States? How does it affect the regulatory autonomy of the Member States and, especially, does it solve the problem of reverse discrimination? Thirdly, scholars disagree on which test of jurisdiction is to be applied by the ECJ in citizenship cases. If being an EU citizen is not enough to fall within the scope of the law, what combination of other factors should one be looking for?

A. EU Citizenship's Relationship with Member States' Nationalities

EU citizenship went far beyond affecting the scope of EU law provisions. It started reshaping the federal status quo in Europe, with direct implications for the division of powers between the EU and the Member States. The starting point of this important process was marked by the profound change which the maturing of EU citizenship introduced into the relationship between EU law and the nationalities of the Member States.Footnote 120

An old academic debate, exemplified by the positions adopted by Gerard-René de Groot and Andrew EvansFootnote 121 on the one side and Ulli Jessurun d'Oliveira on the otherFootnote 122 came to a resolution in 2010 when the Court unreservedly embraced de Groot's position that Member States are not absolutely free in framing their nationalities as they see fit. The Court thus explicitly dismissed Jessurun d'Oliveira's approach, which was based on an assumption that the regulation of nationalities belongs to a reserved domain of national law of the Member States, where the Union is not in the position to intervene. The ECJ answered Jessurun d'Oliveira's question ‘is Union citizenship the crowbar that will break open the nationality law of the Member States?’Footnote 123 in the affirmative and ruled in Rottmann that EU law has to be taken into account when a decision on nationality taken by a Member State is bound to have implications for the EU citizenship status of a person.Footnote 124 Consequently, virtually any instance of loss (and, necessarily, also acquisitionFootnote 125) of a Member State nationality is potentially covered by EU law, thus making the ECJ, in the words of Gareth Davies, ‘the final arbiter’ in citizenship cases.Footnote 126 To suggest that this development was not in the making for a long time does not take the development of EU citizenship seriously. Indeed, Rottmann has been generally regarded in the literature as a predictable and logical development,Footnote 127 especially when viewed in the light of the earlier Micheletti ruling,Footnote 128 which concerned the necessity to take EU law into account in the cases of recognition of each other's nationality by the Member States.Footnote 129 The similarity with conferral and withdrawal of nationalities is obvious in this context.Footnote 130 To deny the Union any possibility to protect EU citizenship status from the encroachments of the Member States would be to leave it entirely to the Member States to decide who EU citizens are, even when such decisions are taken in breach of the core principles of EU law—a flawed construct whose underlying logic is bound to be criticized whatever the relationship between EU citizenship and Member State nationalities established by the Treaties.Footnote 131 Arguments against such approach go back as far as the 1970s, when Sir Richard Plender convincingly argued against the legality under European law of the British DeclarationsFootnote 132 on UK nationality for the purposes of EEC law.Footnote 133 It took the Court 30 long years and a dubious decision in Kaur Footnote 134 to start checking the nationality decisions of the Member States against EU law, accomplished for the first time, albeit indirectly, in Rottmann.Footnote 135 In the meanwhile, the literature, and especially the analysis provided by Andrew EvansFootnote 136 and Gerard-René de Groot,Footnote 137 warned of the numerous situations where nationality decisions would be incompatible with EU law long before Rottmann was decided. The Court thus made a small predictable revolution in following the mainstream literature on the subject and confirming that the reserved domains which Jessurun d'Oliveira argued for are unknown to the system of EU law.Footnote 138 EU citizenship came out of this seriously reinforced, since although the Member States remain free to decide who their nationals are, in doing this they are bound to take EU law fully into account.

The Rottmann decision merely reveals a small part of the full story of the influence of EU citizenship on the nationalities of the Member States. It only focuses on the direct role played by EU law in the sphere of the acquisition and loss of Member State nationalities, but the indirect influence is arguably by far more important. Although there is not much research done in this area,Footnote 139 the literature raises several important points.

First, since all the nationalities of the Member States provide access to the same single status of EU citizenship from which a constantly growing number of rights is then derived, including the right not to be discriminated against on the basis of nationality, the possibility for one Member State to have a ‘better nationality’ within the EU is non-existent, legally speaking at least.Footnote 140 This is especially evident once one takes into account the importance of residence, a ‘place to hang [one's] hat’,Footnote 141 to which the majority of practically usable rights are connected in any Member State, as well as the fact that such residence can be established with the use of EU citizenship status.Footnote 142

Secondly, EU citizenship de facto amounts to the possession of a quasi-nationality of the Member State of residence of which the citizen is not a national,Footnote 143 as well as a ‘relativisation’,Footnote 144 if not ‘abolition’Footnote 145 of the Member State nationalities through Article 18 TFEU. Clearly, EU citizens cannot be equated with foreigners (ie third-country nationals) anywhere in the Union any more.Footnote 146 Consequently, the lack of any coordination between the Member States in terms of access to their nationality was bound to result in the mutation of the accessibility of the legal status of nationality even without any formal intervention of the EU.Footnote 147 The only detailed study of this matter to dateFootnote 148 distinguishes between two ways of such accommodation: formally, where the nationality laws of the Member States are changed to treat EU citizens differently from third-country nationals on the issues of loss and acquisition of nationality; and informally, with de facto preferential treatment for EU citizens when compared with the third-country nationals in terms of access to the nationality of the Member State of residence, since they are not subject to immigration control and derive residence rights from EU law.Footnote 149 Consequently, while, following Rottmann, EU law now plays a role in the framing of Member State nationalities, at the Member State level, EU citizens get preferential access to local nationalities compared with third-country nationals both at the formal and informal levels even without any direct involvement of EU law in this matter. These developments taken together provide yet another illustration of how much EU citizenship and the Member States nationalities are interconnected in practice. The circle is thus ‘rounded up’Footnote 150—a derivative status of EU citizenship comes to affect the Member State nationalities from which it is derived.

Finally, it can also be argued that the formalization of the preferential treatment of EU citizens in naturalization issues in a number of Member States amounts to the establishment of separate modes of acquisition of EU citizenship:Footnote 151 those not in possession of the supranational status have a much harder time acquiring Member State nationality since it comes in tandem with EU citizenship in their case. This is unlike those who are already EU citizens and can usually naturalize in their Member State of residence more easily than third-country nationals.

Although Member States are formally in charge of their nationalities, all decisions on nationality issues are subject to the scrutiny of the ECJ and can always be framed in the context of EU law, whether or not the EU is generally competent to act in the field. The very federal context of the European integration project is responsible for the adaptation of the Member States to the new reality of EU citizenship.

B. EU Citizenship's Influence on the Vertical Delimitation of the Scopes of the Law

EU citizenship plays a global role in shaping the borderline between national and EU law beyond influencing the scope of Member States' nationalities. This is due to three factors, two of which have been presented above. First, EU citizenship has overwhelmingly enlarged the scope ratione personae of EU law.Footnote 152 Secondly, the introduction of EU citizenship has also enlarged the scope of the economic freedoms in the Treaties.Footnote 153 Thirdly, and probably most importantly, the introduction of EU citizenship pushed the Court towards a profound reassessment of the concept of purely internal situations, by moving more situations, however artificially, within the scope of EU law. This process has been brilliantly documented by Alina Tryfonidou,Footnote 154 Niamh Nic Shuibhne,Footnote 155 and Peter Van Elsuwege and Stanislas Adam,Footnote 156 among other commentators.Footnote 157 The classical approach to purely internal situations espoused by such authorities as LA Geelhoed, or Lord SlynnFootnote 158 is not supported by the latest developments in the law.Footnote 159 EU citizenship exposed reverse discrimination in purely internal situations to much more convincing criticism compared with the arguments advanced in the pre-citizenship (market-oriented) era of development of EU law, since EU citizenship as such is not necessarily a market conceptFootnote 160 and reverse discrimination targets mostly those who are viewed as not contributing to the market.Footnote 161 Moreover, the general equality considerations necessarily connected to the concept of citizenship provide an equally important starting point for criticism of the current state of the law.Footnote 162

It is now settled case law that ‘the situation of a national of a Member State who … has not made use of the right to freedom of movement cannot, for that reason alone, be assimilated to a purely internal situation’.Footnote 163 This signifies a potentially infinite enlargement of EU law's scope. Eleanor Spaventa is undoubtedly correct, submitting that ‘no national rule falls a priori outside the scope of the Treaty, since movement is enough to bring the situation within its scope’.Footnote 164 Such movement need not be connected with any physical travel in space or economic activity of the mover.Footnote 165

Consequently, any economic engagement within the Internal Market does not necessarily play a role in shaping the material scope of EU law: EU citizenship does the trick. The meaning of the notion ‘cross border situation’ came to be so technical that it now has virtually nothing to do with borders.Footnote 166 The Court stretches ratione materiae of EU law to cover virtually hypothetical cross-border situations, eg those depending on cross-border birth,Footnote 167 wives’ movements,Footnote 168 or potential movements in the future.Footnote 169 While entitling the growing numbers of individuals to the protections of EU law, such developments stand to be seriously criticized, since they do not actually solve the problem of poor foundations informing the divide between the scopes of national and EU law, and may even exacerbate it, as they risk turning the determination of which law is to apply into a game of chance, simultaneously ensuring that the principle of equality ‘undergoes something of an ideological battering’.Footnote 170 Numerous lawyers, including Niamh Nic Shuibhne and, most importantly, AG Sharpston,Footnote 171 argue for a gradual total overhaul of the approach to purely internal situations. As AG Sharpston aptly observes, there is ‘something deeply paradoxical about [the toleration of reverse discrimination by the EU] although the last 50 years have been spent abolishing barriers to freedom of movement between … Member States’.Footnote 172 Dominique HanfFootnote 173 and AG KokottFootnote 174 are more traditional, viewing reverse discrimination as a necessary evil within the context of multi-level EU constitutionalism.

Even if Nic Shuibhne, Sharpston and others provide convincing arguments that it is ‘time to move on’,Footnote 175 away from reverse discrimination, it is difficult to see on what fundamental basis this could be done, without leaving the omnipresent market paradigm, however deficient. This challenge might be too much for the Union to take on at this stage.Footnote 176 One thing is clear, however: EU citizenship resulted in an exponential growth of the scope of EU law, notwithstanding the (textually unsubstantiated) claims that this was not the intention of the drafters.Footnote 177 Moreover, this growth brought about a serious diminishing in clarity concerning the vertical delimitation of powers between the two legal orders in the Union.Footnote 178

C. EU Citizenship and the Choice of a Jurisdiction Test

In the most recent line of case law,Footnote 179 the Court attempted to remedy the much criticized deficiencies of its cross-border situation approach by formulating a new jurisdiction test in EU citizenship cases which would be entirely removed from Internal Market considerations and where Member State borders within the Union or economic activity would not play any role. Welcomed elsewhere,Footnote 180 this approach has been criticized by Niamh Nic Shuibhne,Footnote 181 Daniel Thym and Kay Hailbronner.Footnote 182 Yet, their criticism mostly concerns the extent of the Court's reasoning, rather than its underlying logic and the outcome. Academics seem to agree that the new vision of jurisdiction, which can now be derived from EU citizenship alone, is a ground-breaking innovation in EU law. Eleanor Spaventa regretted that ‘orthodox thinking led us to believe that, in order to fall within the scope of the Treaty, the migration paradigm had to be satisfied for Union citizens to acquire rights in Community law’.Footnote 183 The ECJ ultimately concurred and embarked on purifying its case law of the unwelcome orthodoxy, which in fact amounted to the discovery of the actual text of Part II TFEU, which contains no references whatsoever to an internal market rationale or the Court's maxim that EU citizenship was not meant to enlarge the material scope of EU law.Footnote 184

The Court ruled that any measures ‘which have the effect of depriving citizens of the Union of the genuine enjoyment of the substance of the rights conferred by virtue of their status as citizens of the Union’Footnote 185 are within the ambit of EU law. In other words, since 2011 there are two tests of jurisdiction in the Court's arsenal: a familiar cross-border situation test and a new degree of interference with EU citizenship rights test.Footnote 186 The two are already being used side-by-side,Footnote 187 even if further clarification concerning their practical functioning will be required. This new development is one of the most far-reaching evolutions in the case law in decades. EU citizenship is finally taken seriously.Footnote 188

The new jurisdiction test comes down to a yet another decisive extension of the scope of EU law, since the number of situations which can produce the ‘effect of depriving Union citizens of the genuine enjoyment of the substance of [their EU citizenship] rights’Footnote 189 is potentially quite considerable. As advocated by the majority of scholars working in the field,Footnote 190 it has been established for the first time by the Court that EU citizenship alone can trigger the application of EU law in a number of situations, with all its accompanying and inestimable consequences. Important though this recognition is, there remain unresolved a considerable number of key questions of fundamental importance. The Court's approach failed to provide clarity concerning the rights of EU citizenship which would be capable of activating EU law in wholly internal situations beyond the problematic right not to be pushed to leave the territory of the Union but not of your Member State of nationality, a right which these cases introduced. Moreover, it is unclear to what extent such rights must be breached to have such effect; what the sources of such rights are; who will decide that such breaches have indeed occurred—national courts, or the ECJ?—and numerous other questions.Footnote 191

V. EU citizenship and the individual

EU citizenship has direct implications for the daily lives of Europeans. Academic debate focuses on an array of issues in this context. The first to be discussed here concerns social solidarity. What are the effects of EU citizenship on the social side of the nationalities of the Member States, including access to different kinds of benefits and other elements of the social security network? The second focuses on identity politics: if it exists at all, what does the identity side of EU citizenship look like? Finally, drawing on much of the above, is EU citizenship empowering, or is it degrading for EU citizens, ie is it a good or a bad thing? Given the lack of underlying substantive principles in which the supranational status could be rooted, as discussed above,Footnote 192 it is only logical that divergent views on this issue are presented in the literature.

A. EU Citizenship and Social Solidarity

Michael Dougan and Eleanor Spaventa are absolutely right, ‘the idea of social solidarity can no longer be treated as a national or local monopoly’.Footnote 193 While they claim that the Union lacks ‘any clear organizing concept of social solidarity’,Footnote 194 Catherine Barnard disagrees in part, finding that ‘[t]he principle of “solidarity” is taking root as a guiding principle of European Community law’.Footnote 195 Her compelling analysis of the case law makes a convincing point that the ECJ used this purely non-economic principle to establish EU citizenship.Footnote 196

But is solidarity confined to citizens—or is it broader in scope? Addressing this question, Sandrine Maillard formulates an all-encompassing approach to social citizenship in Europe, not only connecting the concept with workers’ rights before the incorporation of EU citizenship into the acquis,Footnote 197 but also, simultaneously, attempting to detach it from EU citizenship sensu stricto.Footnote 198 In fact, this approach seems to be working well, as the majority of social rights, at a closer inspection, are not in fact granted exclusively on the basis of nationality or EU citizenship. So long term resident third-country nationals usually enjoy social rights too, notwithstanding the fact that problems with the application of Article 18 TFEU to them abound.Footnote 199 Consequently, social citizenship emerges as a parallel layer of citizenship in Europe, which is largely residence-based, situating the whole debate on the European social model within a much larger context—what Maillard is masterfully doing in her study, which demonstrates the fading away in importance of nationality as such in the context of modern social law. The link between a Member State nationality or EU citizenship and social solidarity appears not at all necessaryFootnote 200 in the context of the emergence, following Sandrine Maillard, of ‘solidarité au-delà de la nationalité’,Footnote 201 which is independent of nationality.Footnote 202 In this context the potential influence of EU citizenship on social solidarity emerges as a much inflated topic. Daniel Thym is absolutely right in this context to state that the ‘long-term implications of the social benefits case-law are, from today's viewpoint, less revolutionary than initial analyses suggested.’Footnote 203

Alongside the links between social solidarity and citizenship, and between social solidarity and the State, the presumption of ‘social dumping’ in the EU is questioned in the literature. It has been generally assumed that EU citizenship, particularly in the context of enlargement, can lead to a much feared erosion of solidarity or a ‘race to the bottom’ between the providers of social services at the national and local level. Empirical evidence to support this is missing entirely, as Michael Keating compellingly demonstrates.Footnote 204

In one example, Michael Dougan sounded several warnings along such lines in the wake of the EU's enlargement: ‘Enlargement might lead to large-scale benefit migration towards western countries which have established generous welfare systems; that a massive influx of workers from the CEEC would seriously disrupt labor markets in the EU-15; that difference between wages and other compliances costs might lead to social dumping in favor of undertakings from the CEEC.’Footnote 205 Needless to say, none of this has materialized in reality.Footnote 206 Endemic in the whole discussion of the dangers of EU citizenship for the social sphere is unfortunately one feature, namely that it tends to ignore the facts, which are quite simple: ‘[c]ontrary to the “race to the bottom” hypothesis, European governments have not dismantled their welfare systems in the face of market competition and, indeed, have retained a variety of distinct models’.Footnote 207

Moreover, it appears that a nation state is not a necessary platform for a system of social solidarity, which numerous sub-national social security systems demonstrate.Footnote 208 The consequences of such dissociations are twofold. First, it does not matter whether a social citizen is in possession of a legal status of nationality of the Member State of residence or EU citizenship. Secondly, nationality of a Member State or EU citizenship would not necessarily guarantee preferential treatment when decoupled from residence.Footnote 209 In this context, the relevance of Member State nationality or EU citizenship in the social plane is only determined by the extent to which the two permit access to residence durable enough to endow individuals with social rights: ‘residence is new nationality’.Footnote 210 In the context of cross-pollenization of EU citizenship and economic freedoms in the Treaties outlined by Síofra O'Leary,Footnote 211 a danger also exists that workers’ access to social citizenship (in terms of Maillard) could be constrained. This could be done with the use of the tools developed in the context of non-economically active EU citizens, aimed at delaying the full application of Article 18 TFEU in the Geist of the secondary legislation and the case law aiming to prevent the so-called ‘benefits shopping’. Notwithstanding the Court's occasional willingness to help,Footnote 212 its general approach to the issueFootnote 213 is much criticized in the literature.Footnote 214

All in all, while scholars too numerous to be mentioned aim to ‘shield’ national-level solidarity from EU interference, a contrasting approach, exemplified by Gareth Davies’ enlightening scholarship, points to the benefits of exposing state-run monopolistic social solidarity systems to competition with a view to increasing efficiency and improving lives.Footnote 215 After all, a claim that the ‘shielded’ national solidarity systems are per se better than any possible alternative is absurd and cannot be taken seriously.Footnote 216 But since Member State nationalities can be cherished by their holders because of the trust they put in the social services provided by their States, being vocal about the actual detachment of citizenship and ‘social citizenship’ as well as allowing for open competition between what States actually provide can result in the ‘hollowing of national citizenship’.Footnote 217 Consequently, crusades to defend national solidarity against EU encroachments seem to come down to an ideological stance, not grounded in reality.

B. EU Citizenship and Identity

Nations—and nationalities—are conceived by ‘creating or elaborating an “ideological” myth of origins and descent’.Footnote 218 In Mythologies Roland Barthes explains that myths are not important for the story they tell, but for what they do.Footnote 219 The identity side of citizenship works in the same way. Although the myth itself is usually so naïf that it does not even pretend to be true ‘nationality is to a greater or lesser degree a manufactured item’Footnote 220—‘l'oublie et l'erreur historique’Footnote 221—identity's perceived true nature is not thereby undermined, ensuring that people are ready to sacrifice it all; mourir pour la Patrie.Footnote 222 The related debate is well known. ‘If national allegiances can be based on false beliefs, how is it possible for a purportedly rational institution such as morality to accommodate them?’Footnote 223 While philosophers are occupied, European political scientists and legal scholars observe EU citizenship and are expectedly divided around its identitarian contenue. What if the Union is creating a community of people on different principles? Or is it, again, about identities and myths?Footnote 224

The prevalent perspective in the literature, as outlined, for instance, in the authoritative study by Elsmore and Starup, claims that ‘[i]n an EU context citizenship focuses on the legal aspect. It lacks the cultural … angle’.Footnote 225 Taking this as a starting point, scholars entirely disagree with regard to its implications for the future of EU citizenship. While for some commentators, such as Richard Bellamy, the likely ‘transfer of allegiance to the EU’Footnote 226 is the key way to measure EU citizenship's success or failure, others, like Joseph WeilerFootnote 227 and Gianluigi Palombella,Footnote 228 see the lack of this aspect precisely as a strong point.Footnote 229 After all, there is no reason to believe that Habermasean ‘constitutional patriotism’ is anything else but ‘the last refuge of a scoundrel’Footnote 230—which removes ground from under the feet of the analysts viewing EU citizenship from Bellamy's perspective. The general framework of constitutionalism as such—‘an empire of uniformity’Footnote 231—is also unlikely to be helpful, as James Tully masterfully demonstrated.Footnote 232 What would be the reason to embark on a European project if it were to result in a grand-scale replication of the Member State-level nationalistic mythology? Gianluigi Palombella seems right that ‘Europe does not need to abandon dēmoi in order to make it e pluribus unum’.Footnote 233 Serious problems with such a line of thinking arise, however, when classical democratic representation at the EU level, implying the existence of a dēmos is advocated: we come back to Bellamy's vision.Footnote 234 How does one create such a dēmos and should one? A ‘Constitution’, to agree with Joseph Weiler is unlikely to be a helpful tool.Footnote 235 Just accepting dēmoicracy could be an option.Footnote 236

Speaking of identity in purely theoretical termsFootnote 237—which plagues much of legal and political works in on EU citizenship—does not seem sufficient. In this respect the analysis by Jürgen Gerhards, employing sociological data is of fundamental importance.Footnote 238 Although this is obviously not to advocate ‘government by public opinion’,Footnote 239 social reality has to be taken into account, especially by those seeking ‘thick’ European identity. The results of Gerhards’ study are fascinating.Footnote 240 They demonstrate that on average only 33.9 per cent of EU citizens support the idea of non-discrimination on the basis of nationality, on which EU citizenship rests. Numbers vary greatly across countries. The acceptance of non-discrimination is the highest in Sweden,Footnote 241 Benelux, France and Denmark and the lowest in Eastern Europe,Footnote 242 with Poles being most opposed to the idea of non-discrimination,Footnote 243 tightly followed by Lithuanians, Slovenes, Maltese, Hungarians and Czechs. In other words, the main principles of EU citizenship have only become a social reality in North-Western EuropeFootnote 244 and are failing to reflect the ideals of the population of the new Member States with a notable exception of Estonia,Footnote 245 which has its own ugly skeletons in the closet, however.Footnote 246

The whole edifice of European integrationFootnote 247 is not a reflection of popular sentiments among EU citizens: Greeks prefer the Greeks.Footnote 248 Could it be then, that the main identitarian contribution of the EU in general and its citizenship in particular runs contrary to State-doctored myths? If so, European citizenship is a potent tool to be deployed against the ‘suffocating bonds’.Footnote 249 Gianluigi Palombella, Gareth Davies and Will KymlickaFootnote 250 all point in this direction, the latter going as far as connecting the failure to recognize the EU's ability to ‘tame and diffuse liberal nationhood’Footnote 251 with ‘moral blindness’.Footnote 252 Joseph Weiler is more cautious: if States are the only seat of classical democratic legitimacy, how far can the Union be successful in undermining them?Footnote 253

All in all, while the mainstream literature sees EU citizenship as a legalistic creation with no implications for identity, spilling ink analysing whether it is a problem—an alternative, negative reading, consists of emphasizing EU citizenship as a liberal check protecting its holders against any state-mandated ‘culture’ and ‘identity’ impositionsFootnote 254 in the State of residence.Footnote 255 Non-discrimination on the basis of nationality blocks any moves of the Member States to ‘integrate’ EU citizens into their societies by imposing parochial culture and language tests,Footnote 256 which are gaining in popularity in the context of third-country national migrants.Footnote 257 This unquestionably liberates EU citizens—although Joseph WeilerFootnote 258 and Ulli Jessurun d'OliveiraFootnote 259 disagree.Footnote 260 While the ECJ and its AGs seem to fully recognize the EU citizenship's liberating function in this respect,Footnote 261 the ‘genuine links’ jurisprudence of the Court is in direct tension with the liberal essence of EU citizenship. It is to be seen how it will evolve, but there is certainly a danger in allowing the ‘genuine links’ to become a push for the acceptance of State-level mythology.

C. EU Citizenship's Worth

In the long term, should the negative vision of the identity side of EU citizenship be correct, residence comes to the fore as the main distinction between those who are in and those who are out, as opposed to myths and ideologies.Footnote 262 Following Gareth Davies, ‘the new Belgians are those who choose Belgium’.Footnote 263 The element of choice is fundamentally important here, since a classical relationship between an individual and a State does not presuppose anything like this. A citizen can try to change her State through democratic or violent means, but no State outside of the EU can empower her to swap States. Under 2 per cent of the world's population changes nationality in the course of their lives.Footnote 264 Scholars applaud EU citizenship for offering individuals this possibility of choosing where to live their lives, which ultimately amounts to choosing friends, foes, and the law, by voting with their feet.Footnote 265 The Union offers a much broader playground of opportunities than any individual State would, enabling EU citizens to live their lives as they, as opposed to a State where they were born and of which they are nationals see fit, from work to marriage,Footnote 266 from healthcareFootnote 267 to education.Footnote 268 Through the EU, Member States act as facilitators of personal choices not limited by their own borders or particular ideologies. This approach is in line with federalist thinking connecting the choice of jurisdiction and liberty.Footnote 269 As Stine Jørgensen observes, ‘in the eyes of the citizens, welfare benefits, freedom of movement and the principle of non-discrimination all support and supplement the legal position of the individual’.Footnote 270 Catching the essential core of this vision, Davies brings it to apotheosis, claiming that the constitutional tactic of the EU amounts to ‘humiliating the State’.Footnote 271

The opposing view is espoused by Joseph Weiler, who takes the democratic-legitimating core of a modern State as the starting point.Footnote 272 Lacking functional democratic mechanisms apart from the negative freedom inherent in it, EU citizenship is said to corrupt individuals,Footnote 273 since political involvement—let alone justice, equality, etcFootnote 274—is simply not part of its package. Humiliating the State, the main added value of EU citizenship in the view of some, becomes the main reason why it is a ‘bad thing’ in the view of others.

Gianluigi Palombella offers a possible way to resolve the conflict between the two perspectives through dissociating State and popular sovereignty, which diminishes the importance of the State, and, simultaneously, tackles the problematic individualismFootnote 275 of the ‘humiliating the State’ vision. He argues that ‘it is evident that popular sovereignty can withstand the passage of time, as an expression of our trust in democracy, and it can do so independently of the fate of the state as a form of the organization of power’.Footnote 276 Consequently, it is fundamental not to confuse the decline of the sovereignty of the State—a ‘concept founded on the reduction of law to the will of the state as an autonomous macro-person’Footnote 277—and the decline of the sovereignty of the citizens.Footnote 278 The sovereignty of the people is presumably reinforced by an ability to choose the community, as opposed to an obligation to be faithful to the one which you possibly find unbearable.Footnote 279 Consequently, Weiler's and Davies’ perspectives on the essence of the Union and its citizenship can theoretically be reconciled. However, how important is seeking this reconciliation at this stage? Even the most optimistic accounts of EU citizenship would not present it as a real and imminent danger to Member States and their nationalities.

Can it be that both Davies with his ‘humiliation of the State’ and Weiler with his ‘corrupting the individual’ accounts of the Union are guilty of exaggerating its imminent positive or negative effects? Could this cleavage be resolved through a simple toning down of the claims? Presently, the majority of EU citizens are not even aware of possessing this status. What is clear, however—and in this Joseph Weiler's work goes against the flood of literature embracing a purely individualistic approach to EU citizenship's potential as overwhelmingly important—is that the EU is unquestionably not mature enough to offer citizenship grounded in substantive values independent of ‘humiliating the State’. This is its main problem which is unlikely to be solved any time soon and of which all those working in the field of EU citizenship should be acutely aware. Individualism has clear limits.

VI. A sketch of the bigger picture: Key outcomes of the analysis

All in all, the brief overview of scholarly disagreements presented above permits a broad sketch of EU citizenship's essence as it emerges from the literature. This sketch leaves no doubt that the legal importance of EU citizenship is on the rise and notwithstanding the numerous outstanding problems affecting the development of this legal status, its potential to play a more prominent role in EU law is obvious. This has to do with three profoundly interrelated key aspects of EU citizenship, which are most evident in the scholarship, namely: EU citizenship's legal nature; its place within the EU's federal structure; and its impact on individual lives. In all three aspects outlined above, and in their tripartite subdivisions, important developments have been observed during the last ten years. So what do the discords in the academic literature teach us about EU citizenship and the evolution of EU law as such?

A. Legal Nature: Three Main Conclusions

Concerning the legal nature of EU citizenship, the literature allows distilling three main points. First, EU citizenship (its derivativeFootnote 280ius tractum acquisition notwithstandingFootnote 281) has unquestionably outgrown the act of derivation, turning into an autonomous legal status,Footnote 282 which is essentially independent from the nationalities of the Member States as far as the role it plays and the rights it brings. This development necessarily results in a marked diminution of the role of Member States’ nationalities in the context of EU law. Given the autonomous nature of EU citizenship, the exclusion of those who are long-term EU residents but are not in possession of one of the Member States’ nationalities is logically more and more difficult to justify. Consequently, the legal situation of third country nationals residing in the Union, who are now essentially excluded from all the key benefits which EU law has to offer in terms of creating a single territory of opportunity for all to enjoy,Footnote 283 will remain an important frontier of EU citizenship law. Such apartheid européen will need to be dealt with sooner or later.Footnote 284

Secondly, the foundations of such an independent status are actually quite feeble. Pointing towards the Internal Market as an underlying value supporting supranational citizenship, however legitimate,Footnote 285 seems profoundly insufficient. It is vital to ground the new independent legal status in something more than mere economic interactions. In fact, EU citizenship has already outgrown its market rationale in many respects.Footnote 286 The literature offers a trio of potentially useful starting points to consider in this regard: democracy,Footnote 287 equalityFootnote 288 and justice.Footnote 289 As of now, however, all of them unquestionably fail the reality check in the EU context. Consequently, EU citizenship is clearly threatened, if not undermined, by the questionable foundations of this status, partly balancing in thin air, rather than firmly sitting on the conceptual ground. It is thus unavoidable that the issue of EU citizenship's foundations will have to be dealt with by the Court and the legislator: nods in the direction of the ‘market’ are insufficient in the contemporary context, when the legal importance of this status is growing at an astonishing pace.

Thirdly, EU citizenship now affects the interpretation of pre-citizenship economic freedoms too. In this it does not show any signs of being practically undermined by the conceptual deficiencies described above. During the last decade it clearly came to play the essential role in framing EU law's development, becoming ‘the fundamental status of the nationals of the Member States’,Footnote 290 promised as long ago as in Grzelczyk.Footnote 291 The scope of the fundamental economic freedoms is now profoundly affected by the citizenship concept.Footnote 292 The main problem, which can arise in this context, is the potential spread of at times less generous rules of access to non-discrimination on the basis of nationality from the context of EU citizenship law covering non-economically-active citizens to the economic free-movement law.Footnote 293 A firewall will need to be put in place to protect the EU's fundamental freedoms.

B. Influencing the EU's Federal Structure: Three Main Conclusions

The second most popular topic addressed in EU citizenship literature concerns the possible influence of such citizenship on the vertical delimitation of the two legal orders in the EU. First, it is indisputable that EU citizenship moved beyond mere autonomy from the nationalities of the Member States and came to profoundly affect the essence of such nationalities, as the ECJ acquired jurisdiction to check the legality of the decisions on granting and withdrawing EU citizenship (and, consequently, the very nationalities of the Member StatesFootnote 294) by the national authorities.Footnote 295 This reaffirmed once again that nationality is not a reserved domain where EU law cannot intervene,Footnote 296 thus definitely clarifying the division of powers between the two legal orders in Europe. At the informal level the legal importance of Member States’ nationalities has also been diminishing, ending up ‘relativised’,Footnote 297 if not, in many respects ‘abolished’.Footnote 298 This led to a conceptual reframing of the balance between the two statuses. A number of Member States went as far as to establish de facto separate rules on the acquisition of EU citizenship,Footnote 299 compared with the acquisition of nationalities only. The main problem arising in this context is the poor coordination of nationality matters between the Member States, some of them still lost in the sovereignty mythology and unwilling to take full account of the reality where without such coordination they actually regulate little.

Secondly, EU citizenship led to an exponential growth of the scope of EU law, notwithstanding the unconvincing ECJ claims to the contrary. The analyses in the literature put it straight: EU citizenship is responsible for an overwhelming enlargement of the scope ratione personae and, also, of the material scope too, as the two are directly connected.Footnote 300 Consequently, the Court is now discovering a new paradigm of EU integration,Footnote 301 where EU citizenship logic can potentially replace, at least in some cases, the ideology of cross-border effects, undermining the dogmatism of cross-border situation thinking. In other words, EU citizenship plays a fundamental role in the framing of the scope of EU law. This, however, caused a number of problems, as legal certainty is not always taken absolutely seriously in the process:Footnote 302 many questions concerning the vertical delimitation of powers in the Union remain.

These can theoretically be addressed via a reform of the ECJ's jurisdiction tests. This is the third most important aspect of EU citizenship's influence on the federal nature of the Union. EU citizenship came to play a role as an activator of EU law even in the context where no cross-border situation is invoked, as we have seen in Rottmann and Ruiz Zambrano.Footnote 303 This, notwithstanding the apparent limitations of this approach in Dereci, means a dawn of a new Union, where not the economic cross-border considerations, but the respect of fundamental rights plays a crucial role in the activation of the supranational law.Footnote 304 The new approach has been rightly criticized for its vagueness,Footnote 305 however, as it seemingly poses more questions than it provides answers.Footnote 306

C. EU Citizenship and Ordinary Lives: Three Main Conclusions

Most importantly, however, EU citizenship directly affects all the holders of this status, as it offers Europeans a radically broadened horizon of opportunities and in this sense seriously contributes to liberty in the Union through empowering individuals. Literature analysis of EU citizenship's influence on ordinary lives allows, first, dismissing the claims that it negatively affects social solidarity within the national contexts of the Member States, as social rights build on the idea of social citizenship which is not directly connected to the status of Member State nationality as such.Footnote 307 This finding is further reinforced by the fact that a direct link between social solidarity and the State is not obvious either.Footnote 308 Moreover, any ‘shielding’ of national social solidarity systems from EU citizenship's influence exacerbates the unequal distribution of wealth around the Union, thus benefiting only the richest Member StatesFootnote 309 and is based on a bluntly unsound presumption that what is being shielded is better than any possible alternative, undermining possible reforms which can benefit all.Footnote 310 Given that no ‘race to the bottom’ is actually observable in the EU,Footnote 311 much of the literature on the negative effects of EU citizenship on social solidarity seems largely conceptually empty.

Secondly, literature analysis allows dispelling the myth that EU citizenship is merely a legalistic status that does not affect the identity of the nationals of the Member States. Of course it does, and it does so by releasing them from the ‘suffocating bonds’Footnote 312 by protecting them from the Member StatesFootnote 313—an approach which is particularly clear in the light of the new vision of the activation of EU law, where cross-border situations are not required and the protection of rights plays a key role. In this sense, the EU is to be praised for not trying to emulate nation-states.Footnote 314

This leads us, thirdly, to a more fundamental question: if the EU citizenship's main strength is to undermine the Member States’ grip on their nationals, thus de facto undermining the states as such, is it capable of supplying something positive to compensate for shattering the national foundations, which are also generally perceived as the foundations of democracy, equality and justice?Footnote 315 This is where the main drawback of EU citizenship, ie the absence of a value basis and conceptual foundation comes again to the fore. Although to state that Member States would perish under its pressure would be stretching it too far, thus toning down the immediate relevance of the question posed, it will be necessary to deal with the fundamental conceptual void at the basis of EU citizenship sooner, rather than later. As EU citizenship develops, however, this drawback can also solve itself in the process: let us wait and see.

VII. Final remarks

As Williams correctly observes, ‘the ECJ's future challenges are both administrative and philosophical in nature.’Footnote 316 The same applies to legal scholarship. While philosophical challenges present a truly fundamental challenge, the majority of the literature, strangely, focuses on the administrative ones. To realize EU citizenship's full potential this will have to change. As this overview has demonstrated, plenty of scholars are engaged with EU citizenship, yet, the most important problems underlying its essence are only tackled by very few commentators, led by, inter alia, Dora Kostakopoulou, Gareth Davies and Joseph Weiler. The constructive potential of EU citizenship is unlikely to be fully realized without a shift in the register of scholarly engagement with this important area of law. To be successful in shaping the Union in the years to come such commentary will have to be less ideological and less distracted by day-to-day events. Lastly, drawing inspiration only from the negative features of EU citizenship, opposing it to a State, is potentially dangerous—a more balanced account of the concept has to be formulated. Although the tradition of renku-writing would have it otherwise, this overview has hopefully demonstrated that there are plenty of other interesting topics worthy of discussion when the myriad legal problems surrounding EU citizenship is addressed: time to move beyond the cherry blossoms and the Moon.

Footnotes

1

‘Of an infinite number of permissible subjects, cherry blossoms and the moon are traditionally held to be the most interesting.’ Makoto Ueda, Matsuo Bashō 74 (Tokyo: Kodansha International, 1970).

References

2 Aron, R, ‘Is Multinational Citizenship Possible?’ (1974) 41 Social Research 638Google Scholar. For a very informative analysis of the connection existing between the concepts of citizenship and the nation-state, see Preuß, UK, ‘Problems of a Concept of European Citizenship’ (1995) 1 ELJ 271–3Google Scholar.

3 eg Case C–135/08, Janko Rottmann v Freistaat Bayern [2010] ECR I–1449; Case C–34/09, Gerardo Ruiz Zambrano Office national de l'emploi [2011] ECR I–0000; Case C–127/08] Metock and Others [2008] ECR I–6241; Case C–192/05 Tas-Hagen and Tas [2006] ECR I–10451; Case C–200/02 Zhu and Chen [2004] ECR I–9925; Case C–256/11 Murat Dereçi, Vishaka Heiml, Alban Kokollari, Izunna Emmanuel Maduike & Dragica Stević v Bundesminister für Inneres [2011] ECR I–0000. Several important cases to clarify the legal nature of EU citizenship further are currently pending in front of the Court. See eg Case C–356/11 O, S, OJ C 269/74 (2011); Case C–357/11 L., OJ C 269/75 (2011).

4 Schönberger, C, ‘European Citizenship as Federal Citizenship: Some Citizenship Lessons of Comparative Federalism’ (2007) 19 Revue européenne de droit public 61Google Scholar. See also Shaw, J, ‘Political Rights and Multilevel Citizenship in Europe’ in Guild, E, Groenendijk, K and Carrera, S (eds), Illiberal Liberal States: Immigration, Citizenship and Integration in the EU (Ashgate 2009) 29Google Scholar.

5 Shaw, J, ‘Citizenship: Contrasting Dynamics at the Interface of Integration and Constitutionalism’ in Craig, P and de Búrca, G (eds), Evolution of EU Law (OUP 2011 2nd ed) 578Google Scholar.

6 Bauböck, R and Guiraudon, V, ‘Introduction: Realignments of Citizenship: Reassessing Rights in the Age of Plural Memberships and Multi–Level Governance’ (2009) 13 Citizenship Studies 440CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 While the limitations of such an exercise are obvious, given the sheer amount of the publications engaged with this topic in all the 23 languages of the Union, it is nevertheless possible to outline the most influential trends in the academic thought on EU citizenship during the last ten years.

8 The pivotal role played by EU citizenship in the Union today is not connected to the recent revisions of the Treaties. In fact, virtually all the recent developments in this vein have been rather inconsequential, if not a disappointment: Schrauwen, A, ‘European Citizenship in the Treaty of Lisbon: Any Change at All?’ (2008) 15 Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 55CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kostakopoulou, D, ‘Ideas, Norms and European Citizenship: Explaining Institutional Change’ (2005) 68 ModLRev 261–2Google Scholar.

9 eg Opinion of AG Jacobs in Case C–168/91 Kostantinidis [1993] ECR I–1191; Opinion of AG Léger in Case C–214/94 Boukhalfa [1996] ECR I–2253; Opinion of AG Jacobs in Case C–224/02 Heikki Antero Pusa [2004] ECR I–5763; Opinon of AG Jacobs in Case C–96/04 Standesamt Stadt Niebüll [2006] ECR I–3561; Opinion of AG Sharpston in Case C–212/06 Government of the French Community and Walloon Government v Flemish Government [2008] ECR I–1683; Opinion of AG Sharpston in Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000. Also the extrajudicial writings of the members of the Court play an important role in the academic debate. See, inter alia, Lenaerts, K, ‘“Civis europaeus sum”: From the Cross-Border Link to the Status of Citizen of the Union’ (2011) 3 Electronic Journal of the Free Movement of Workers in the European Community 6Google Scholar; J Kokott, ‘EU Citizenship—citoyens sans frontières?’ (2005) Durham European Law Institute, European Law Lecture, available at <http://www.dur.ac.uk/resources/deli/annuallecture/2005_DELI_Lecture.pdf> (accessed 20 August 2012).

10 At the EU level see Directive 2004/38, OJ L 158/77, 2004; Carrera, S, ‘What Does Free Movement Mean in Theory and Practice in an Enlarged EU?11 ELJ (2005) 711–18Google Scholar; Soriao, C, ‘Libre circulation et séjour dans l'UE: La directive 2004/38 au regard des droits de l'Homme’ (2005) 121 Journal des tribunaux, Droit européen 200Google Scholar; Elsmore, MJ and Starup, P, ‘Union Citizenship—Background, Jurisprudence, and Perspective: The Past, Present, and Future of Law and Policy’ (2007) 26 Yearbook of European Law 96100CrossRefGoogle Scholar. At the national level, see the country reports of the EUDO citizenship observatory of the European University Institute <http://eudo-citizenship.eu > .

11 The notion of European citizenship is older than the Maastricht Treaty: Kochenov, D and Plender, R, ‘EU Citizenship: From an Incipient Form to an Incipient Substance? The Discovery of the Treaty Text’ (2012) 37 ELR 369 (and the literature cited therein)Google Scholar.

12 Notable exceptions are Kostakopoulou (n 8); Shaw (n 5) 575–84.

13 Shaw, J, ‘Constitutional Settlements and the Citizen after the Treaty of Amsterdam’ in Neunreither, K and Wiener, A (eds), European Integration after Amsterdam: Institutional Dynamics and Prospects for Democracy (OUP 2000) 297Google Scholar.

14 cf JR Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (Simon and Schuster 1997).

15 A fair amount of short-sightedness played a role here too, however. To agree with Dora Kostakopoulou, ‘It is … unfortunate that much of the relevant literature in the 1990s did not recognize that the value of European citizenship existed not so much in what it was, but in what it ought to be’: Kostakopoulou (n 8) 263.

16 See the references throughout this article and also, inter alia; Sánchez, S Iglesias, ‘¿Hacia una nueva relación entre la nationalidad estatal y la ciudadanía europea?’ (2010) 37 Revista de Derecho Comunitario Europeo 933Google Scholar; Marguery, T, ‘La citoyénneté européenne joue-t-elle un role dans l’éspace penal de liberté, de sécurité et de justice?’ (2010) CDE 387Google Scholar; Shaw, J, ‘The Constitutional Development of Citizenship in the EU Context: With or without the Treaty of Lisbon’ in Pernice, I and Tanchev, E (eds), Ceci n'est pas une Constitution – Constitutionalism without a Constitution? (Nomos 2009) 104Google Scholar; Groussot, X, ‘“Principled Citizenship” and Process of European Constitutionalisation – From a Pie in the Sky to a Sky with Diamonds’ in Bernitz, U et al (eds), General Principles of EC Law in a Process of Development (Kluwer 2008) 315Google Scholar; Somek, A, ‘Solidarity Decomposed: Being and Time in European Citizenship’ (2007) 32 ELR 787Google Scholar; Bauböck, R, ‘Why European Citizenship? Normative Approaches to Supranational Union’ (2007) 8 Theoretical Inquiries in Law 452CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dougan, M, ‘The Constitutional Dimension to the Case Law on Union Citizenship’ (2006) 31 ELR 613Google Scholar; Kadelbach, S, ‘Union Citizenship’ in A von Bogdandy and Bast, J (eds), Principles of European Constitutional Law (Hart 2006) 453Google Scholar.

17 Kostakopoulou (n 8).

18 These included ‘Market citizenship’; ‘Civic republican European citizenship’; ‘Deliberative European citizenship’; ‘Corrective European citizenship’; and ‘Constructive European citizenship’: Kostakopoulou ibid 238–43. Many more theoretical approaches to citizenship are available, which could potentially be utilized also in the context of EU citizenship analysis. See eg L Bosniak, ‘Citizenship Denationalised’ (2000) 7 IndJGlobalLegalStud 477; K Rubinstein and D Adler, ‘International Citizenship: The Future of Nationality in a Globalised World’ (2000) 7 IndJGlobalLegalStud 522. For the analysis of the different approaches in the context of EU citizenship see eg P Mindus, ‘Europeanisation of Citizenship within the EU: Perspectives and Ambiguities’ (2008) Università degli Studi di Trento Working Paper WP SS, No 2.

19 eg Case C–184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I–6193; Case C–224/98 D'Hoop [2002] ECR I–6191; Case C–413/99 Baumbast and R. [2002] ECR I–7091; Case C–224/02 Pusa [2004] ECR I–5763.

20 Case C–85/96 Martínez Sala [1998] ECR I–2691; Case C–184/99 Grzelczyk [2001] ECR I–6193; Case C–413/99; Case C–456/02 Trojani [2004] ECR I–7573. See, in general, Davies, G, Nationality Discrimination in the European Internal Market (Kluwer 2003)Google Scholar; K Lenaerts, ‘Union Citizenship and the Principle of Non-Discrimination on the Grounds of Nationality’ in Festskrift til Claus Gulmann (Thomson 2006).

21 Case C–192/05 Tas-Hagen and Tas [2006] ECR I–10451; Opinion of AG Jacobs in Case C–224/02 Pusa [2004] ECR I–5763; Jacobs, F, ‘Citizenship of the European Union – A Legal Analysis’ (2007) 13 ELJ 591CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kochenov, D, ‘Free Movement and Participation in the Parliamentary Elections in the Member State of Nationality: An Ignored Link?’ (2009) 16 Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 197CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

22 Case C–135/08, Janko Rottmann v Freistaat Bayern [2010] ECR I–1449; Case C–34/09, Gerardo Ruiz Zambrano v Office national de l'emploi [2011] ECR I–0000; Case C–256/11 Dereci [2011] ECR I–0000; Lenaerts (n 9); Kochenov, D, ‘A Real European Citizenship; A New Jurisdiction Test; A Novel Chapter in the Development of the Union in Europe’ (2011) 18 ColumJEurL 55Google Scholar; Van Elsuwege, P, ‘Shifting the Boundaries? European Union Citizenship and the Scope of Application of EU Law’ (2011) 38 LIEI 263Google Scholar.

23 On the legitimacy of the use of federal terminology in the legal context of the EU see inter alia Schütze, R, ‘On “Federal” Ground: The European Union as an (Inter)National Phenomenon’ (2009) 46 CMLRev 1069Google Scholar.

24 Case C–135/08, Janko Rottmann v Freistaat Bayern [2010] ECR I–1449; G-R de Groot, ‘Overwegingen over de Janko Rottmann-beslissing van het Europese Hof van Justitie’ Asiel & migrantenrecht (2010) 293; Kochenov, D, ‘Annotation of Case C–135/08 Rottmann’ (2010) 47 CMLRev 1831Google Scholar; J Shaw (ed), ‘Has the European Court of Justice Challenged the Member State Sovereignty in Nationality Law?’ (2011) EUI Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies Paper No 62.

25 Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000; van der Mei, AP, van den Bogaert, SCG, and de Groot, G-R, ‘De arresten Ruiz Zambrano en McCarthy’ (2011) 4 NTER 187Google Scholar; Ankersmit, L and Geursen, W, ‘Ruiz Zambrano: De interne situatie voorbij’ (2011) 4 Asiel & migrantenrecht 156Google Scholar; P Van Elsuwege (n 22); Sánchez, S Iglesias, ‘El assunto Ruiz Zambrano: Una nueva aproximación del Tribunal de Justicia de la Unión europea a la ciudadanía de la Unión’ (2011) 24 Revista general de derecho europeo 382Google Scholar.

26 For an analysis see Kochenov, D, ‘The Right to Have What Rights? EU Citizenship in Need of Clarification18 ELJ (2013 forthcoming)Google Scholar.

27 Williams, A, ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (2009) 20 OJLS 549CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Williams, A, The Ethos of Europe (CUP 2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For an informative perspective, see Neyer, J, ‘Justice, Not Democracy in the European Union’ (2010) 48 JComMarSt 903Google Scholar; Neyer, J, ‘Who Is Afraid of Justice? A Rejoinder to Danny Nicol’ (2012) 50 JComMarSt 523Google Scholar.

28 Weiler, JHH, ‘Individual and Rights: The Sour Grapes (Editorial)’ (2010) 21 EJILGoogle Scholar. See also Weiler, JHH, ‘Europa: “Nous coalisons des Etats nous n'unissons pas des hommes”’ in Cartabia, M and Simoncini, A (eds), La Sostenibilità della democrazia nel XXI secolo (Il Mulino 2009) 51Google Scholar.

29 See Schütze, R, From Dual to Cooperative Federalism (OUP 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar (which is a compelling plea against this approach).

30 eg Kochenov, D, ‘Ius Tractum of Many Faces: European Citizenship and the Difficult Relationship between Status and Rights’ (2009) 15 ColumJEurL 181–93Google Scholar.

31 G Tesauro, Diritto comunitario (5th edn, CEDAM; Wolters Kluwer Italia 2008) 480 [author's translation: ‘At the moment the Community notion of citizenship does not exist, not even hypothetically, given that the norms requiring its possession as a subjective condition for their application in reality refer to the national law of the State whose nationality turns into the basis of the invoked right.’]

32 Besselink, L and Reestman, JH, ‘Dynamics of European and National Citizenship: Inclusive or Exclusive? (Editorial)’ (2007) 3 EuConst 2Google Scholar.

33 Ibid. See, similarly, Richard Bellamy: ‘[EU citizenship] facilitates cooperation between citizens of the member states and their access to citizenship of another member state, but does very little to create a distinctive attachment to the EU itself’: Bellamy, R, ‘Evaluating Union Citizenship: Belonging, Rights and Participation within the EU’ (2008) 12 Citizenship Studies 598CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

34 The ECJ traditionally disallows making any distinctions between Member State nationalities on the ground of how they were acquired: Case 136/78 Ministère public v Auer [1979] ECR 437, para 28; Case C–369/90 Micheletti [1992] ECR I–4239, para 10; Case C–200/02 Zhu and Chen [2004] ECR I–9925; Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000.

35 Kochenov (n 30) 181; P Dollat, ‘La citoyenneté européenne: Théorie et statuts’ (Bruylant 2008) 95–104.

36 Opinion of AG Poiares Maduro in Case C–135/08, Rottmann [2010] ECR I–1449, para 23 (emphasis added) [author's translation: ‘Union citizenship assumes nationality of a Member State but it is also a legal and political concept independent of that of nationality.’].

37 Case C–135/08, Rottmann [2010] ECR I–1449, para 42.

38 Kochenov (n 24) 1833; Davies, G, ‘The Entirely Conventional Supremacy of Union Citizenship and Rights’ in Shaw, J (ed), Has the European Court of Justice Challenged the Member State Sovereignty in Nationality Law? (EUI Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies Paper No 62 (2011))Google Scholar; Kostakopoulou, D, ‘European Union Citizenship and Member State Nationality: Updating or Upgrading the Link’ in Shaw, J (ed), Has the European Court of Justice Challenged the Member State Sovereignty in Nationality Law? (EUI Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies Paper No 62 (2011))Google Scholar.

39 Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000, para 44; Kochenov (n 22); L Azoulai, ‘La citoyenneté européenne, un statut d'intégration sociale’ in Mélanges Jean Paul Jacqué: Chemins d'Europe (Dalloz 2010); Golynker, O, ‘European Union as a Single Working-Living Space: EU Law and New Forms of Intra-Community Migration’ in Halpin, A and Roeben, V (eds), Theorising the Global Legal Order (Hart 2009) 145Google Scholar;

40 D Kochenov, ‘Rounding up the Circle: The Mutation of Member States’ Nationalities under Pressure from EU Citizenship’ EUI Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies Paper No 23/2010. For a meticulous analysis of EU citizenship rights, including those functioning in parallel with the rights granted by Member State nationalities see Dollat (n 35) 249–300.

41 Palombella, G, ‘Whose Europe? After the Constitution: A Goal-Based Citizenship’ (2005) 3 Int'l J. Const. L. 377Google Scholar (also referring to Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (Knopf 1999)).

42 Kostakopoulou (n 8) 243.

43 Section IVA infra.

44 Besson, S and Utzinger, A, ‘Towards European Citizenship’ (2008) 39 Journal of Social Philosophy 196CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

45 Palombella (n 41) 367. Expectedly, there is a ‘but’. Palombella submits that ‘rather, [legitimacy] is to depend on the public autonomy of a sovereign that is coextensive with the constitutional text's range of influence’ ibid.

46 Kostakopoulou (n 38); Jessurun d'Oliveira, HU, ‘Ontkoppeling van nationaliteit en Unieburgerschap?,’ Nederlandsch Juristenblad (2010) 785Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 30) 182.

47 This can happen either through granting such persons the formal status of EU citizenship in the future, or through providing them with a set of rights comparable to those enjoyed by EU citizens: Lansbergen, A and Shaw, J, ‘National Membership Models in a Multilevel Europe’ (2010) 8 International Journal of Constitutional Law 50CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Maas, W, ‘Migrants, States, and EU Citizenship's Unfulfilled Promise’ (2008) 12 Citizenship Studies 583CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kochenov (n 40) 29–33; Kostakopoulou, D, Citizenship, Identity and Immigration in the European Union: Between Past and Future (Manchester University Press 2001) 79Google Scholar; Kostakopoulou, DEU Citizenship: Writing the Future’ (2007) 13 ELJ 623CrossRefGoogle Scholar. For a magisterial account of the legal migration into the EU see A Wiesbrock, Legal Migration to the European Union (Martinus Nijhoff 2010).

48 Balibar, É, Nous, citoyens d'Europe: Les frontières, l’État, le peuple (La Découverte 2001) 190–1CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

49 Kochenov and Plender (n 11): the codification of the pre-existing informal status by the Treaty of Maastricht failed to seriously affect the legal edifice of the Union for roughly 20 years—it is only with Rottmann and Ruiz Zambrano that the Court seems to be starting to discover the far-reaching potential of EU citizenship.

50 Kochenov, D, ‘The Impact of European Citizenship on the Association of the Overseas Countries and Territories with the European Community’ (2009) 36 LIEI 239Google Scholar; Bohring, WR, ‘The Scope of the EEC System of Free Movement of Workers: A Rejoinder’ (1973) 10 CMLRev 82Google Scholar.

51 See Kochenov, D, ‘European Union's Minority Protection’, in Kymlicka, W and Boulden, J (eds), International Approaches to Governing Ethnic Diversity (OUP 2013, forthcoming)Google Scholar.

52 For an illuminating historical account see W Maas, Creating European Citizens (Rowman & Littlefield 2007). Limited free movement rights granted to third-country nationals who are long-term residents by Directive 2003/109 (OJ L 16/44, 2004) do not solve any outstanding problems: Wiesbrock, A, ‘Free Movement of Third-Country Nationals in the European Union: The Illusion of Exclusion’ (2010) 35 ELR 455Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 30) 286; Skordas, A, ‘Immigration and the Market: The Long-Term Residents Directive’ (2006) 13 ColumJEurL 201Google Scholar.

53 See for an analysis Kochenov (n 30) 186–90.

54 This issue will be further assessed in Section IVA below.

55 See also Petit, I, ‘Dispelling a Myth? The Fathers of Europe and the Construction of Euro-Identity’ (2006) 12 ELJ 661CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

56 TFEU Preamble, recital 1.

57 See Kapteyn, P, The Stateless Market: The European Dilemma of Integration and Civilization (Routledge 1995)Google Scholar.

58 Kostakopoulou (n 8) 244–6.

59 Wollenschläger, F, ‘A New Fundamental Freedom beyond Market Integration: Union Citizenship and Its Dynamics for Shifting the Economic Paradigm of European Integration’ (2011) 17 ELJ 34Google Scholar.

60 Shaw (n 5) 575.

61 Shuibhne, N Nic, ‘The Resilience of EU Market Citizenship’ (2010) 47 CMLRev 1597Google Scholar.

62 On this distinction see Reich, N and Harbacevica, S, ‘Citizenship and Family on Trial: A Fairly Optimistic Overview of Recent Court Practice with Regard to Free Movement of Persons’ (2003) 40 CMLRev 628Google Scholar; Dollat (n 35) 249ff.

63 Nic Shuibhne (n 61) 1605.

64 ibid 1608.

65 For a meticulous overview, see Kymlicka, W and Wayne, N, ‘Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory’ (1994) 104 Ethics 352CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Weiler, JHH, ‘Bread and Circus: The State of the European Union’ (1998) 4 ColumJEurL 231Google Scholar.

67 ibid.

68 Morgan, G, ‘European Political Integration and the Need for Justification’ (2007) 14 Constellations 332CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

69 Williams, The Ethos of Europe (n 27); Willams, ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (n 27).

70 Weiler, JHH, ‘Europa: “Nous coalisons des Etats nous n'unissons pas des hommes”’ in Cartabia, M and Simoncini, A (eds), La Sostenibilità della democrazia nel XXI secolo (Il Mulino 2009) 51Google Scholar.

71 Kochenov, D, ‘Citizenship without Respect: The EU's Troubled Equality Ideal’ (2010) Jean Monnet Working Paper (NYU Law School) 08/10, 7484Google Scholar.

72 The same seems to hold for the concept of liberty, scrutinized by Richard Bellamy: R Bellamy, ‘The Liberty of the Post-Moderns?: Market and Civic Freedom within the EU’ (2009) LSE ‘Europe in Question’ Discussion Paper No 01/2009.

73 Williams, ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (n 27); Williams, The Ethos of Europe (n 27).

74 Williams claims that the EU is based more on the founders’ intent, than on a substantive idea of justice: Williams, ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (n 27) 549.

75 ibid; Williams, The Ethos of Europe (n 27).

76 Williams (2009) ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (n 27) 568–9. For more examples see Kochenov (n 71); Arnull, A, ‘The Rule of Law in the European Union’ in Arnull, A and Wincott, D (eds), Accountability and Legitimacy in the European Union (OUP 2002) 241Google Scholar; de Búrca, G, ‘The Role of Equality in European Community Law’ in Dashwood, A and O'Leary, S (eds), The Principle of Equal Treatment in EC Law (Sweet & Maxwell 1997) 13Google Scholar.

77 Weiler (n 70) 54 [author's translation: ‘today we accumulate the rhetoric of values, at the same time either giving them little importance in the operating parts of the Treaties, or allowing ambiguity prevail’].

78 Williams, ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (n 27) 560–1.

79 ibid 558–70. See also Joseph Weiler's unpublished paper on the subject ‘On the Distinction between Values and Virtues in the Process of European Integration’. For the particular citizenship context see Kuisma, M, ‘Rights of Privileges? The Challenge of Globalisation to the Values of Citizenship’ (2008) 12 Citizenship Studies 613CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

80 Williams, ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (n 27) 549.

81 Kochenov (n 71) 12–27.

82 G Davies, ‘Services, Citizenship, and the Country of Origin Principle’, Mitchell Working Paper (Edinburgh) No 2/2007.

83 De Búrca (n 76).

84 Kochenov (n 71).

85 Weiler (n 70) 64 [author's translation: ‘is reduced to a consumer of political results’].

86 Dollat (n 35) 561–5; Ferro, MS, ‘Popular Legislative Initiative in the EU: Alea Iacta Est’, (2007) 26 Oxford Yearbook of European Law 355CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

87 Most recently, in Case C–300/04 Eman and Sevinger v College van burgemeester en wethouders van Den Haag [2006] ECR I–8055. See Besselink's, ‘Annotation’ in 45 CMLRev 806–8 (2008); Kochenov, D, ‘The Puzzle of Citizenship and Territory in the EU: On European Rights Overseas’ (2010) 17 Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 230CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

88 Kochenov (n 30) 197. In general see Shaw, J, The Transformation of Citizenship in the European Union: Electoral Rights and the Restructuring of Political Space (CUP 2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zincone, G and Ardovino, S, ‘I diritti elettorali dei migranti nello spazio politico e giuridico europeo’, (2004) 5 Le Istituzioni del Federalismo 741Google Scholar; Shaw, J, ‘Alien Suffrage in the European Union’ (2003) 12 The Good Society 29CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

89 Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

90 Weiler (n 70) 82 [author's translation: ‘the problematic aspect of this case law is precisely that it avoids making a conceptual transition from the free movement based on economic considerations to a freedom based on citizenship’]. Weiler comes to this conclusion based on the analysis of the political side of the essence of citizenship, but the same holds, as has been demonstrated above, also for the analysis evolving around the principle of equality. See also Maduro, MP, ‘Europe's Social Self: “The Sickness unto Death”’, in Shaw, J (ed), Social Law and Policy in an Evolving European Union (Hart 2000) 340Google Scholar.

91 Williams, The Ethos of Europe (n 27) 18 (emphasis in the original).

92 Kochenov (n 71) 9.

93 Shuibhne, N Nic, ‘The Outer Limits of EU Citizenship; Displacing Economic Free Movement Rights?’ in Barnard, C and Odudu, O (eds), The Outer Limits of European Union Law (Hart 2009) 168Google Scholar.

94 Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000, para 41.

95 This is the amount of EU citizens currently residing in the Member State other than their Member State of nationality. This amount includes economic and non-economic migrants. In pre-citizenship times not all these persons would be covered by EU law. The data is from: Vasileva, K, ‘Population and Social Conditions’ (2009) Eurostat Statistics in Focus 94/2009, 3Google Scholar.

96 Spaventa, E, ‘Seeing the Wood Despite the Trees? On the Scope of Union Citizenship and its Constitutional Effects’ (2008) 45 CMLRev 13Google Scholar.

97 eg Joined cases C–64/96 & C–65/96 Uecker and Jacquet [1997] ECR I–3171, para 23; Case C–148/02 Garcia Avello [2003] ECR I–11613, para 26. For a critical assessment of this approach in the light of Rottmann see Kochenov (n 24).

98 Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

99 If such context can at all be distilled.

100 For an analysis, see Tryfonidou, A, ‘In Search of the Aim of the EC Free Movement of Persons Provisions: Has the Court of Justice Missed the Point?’ (2009) 46 CMLRev 1592–5)Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 22).

101 eg Case C–152/03 Ritter-Coulais [2006] ECR I–1711. See also Case C–227/03 AJ van Pommeren-Bourgondiën [2005] ECR I–6101; Case C–287/05 Hendrix [2007] ECR I–6909; Case C–213/05 Geven [2007] ECR I–6347; Case C–212/05 Hartmann [2007] ECR I–6303.

102 C O'Brian, ‘Annotation of Case C–212/05 Hartmann, Case C–213/05 Geven, Case C–287/05 Hendrix’ (2008) 45 CMLRev 499.

103 Tryfonidou (n 100).

104 O'Brien (n 102) 505. This position is very similar to the one expressed by AG Geelhoed in Cases C–212/05 Hartmann [2007] ECR I–6303 and C–213/05 Geven [2007] ECR I–6347.

105 O'Brien, C, ‘Real Links, Abstract Rights and False Alarms: The Relationship between the ECJ's “Real Link” Case Law and National Solidarity’ (2008) 33 ELR 654Google Scholar.

106 For more on the ECJ's approach to jurisdiction in the context of EU citizenship see Section IVC below.

107 The Tryfonidou/O'Brien vision seems to be based on too narrow a vision of the Internal Market: Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

108 Golynker (n 39) 151; Kochenov (n 22).

109 For a compelling analysis of ultra vires engagements of the ECJ and the national courts see Craig, Paul, ‘The ECJ and Ultra Vires Action: A Conceptual Analysis’ (2011) 48 CMLRev 395Google Scholar.

110 Golynker (n 39) 151. See also Opinion of AG Kokott in Case C–287/05 DPW Hendrix v Raad van Bestuur van het Iutvoeringsinstituut Werknemersverzekeringen [2007] ECR I–6909.

111 Art. 26(2) TFEU.

112 Davies (n 20) 189; Kochenov (n 71) 52–4. But see Wollenschläger (n 59) 30–1.

113 Lenaerts (n 9); Kochenov (n 22).

114 eg Case C–209/03 Bidar [2005] ECR I–211.

115 Case C–213/05 Geven [2007] ECR I–6347.

116 Case C–212/05 Hartmann [2007] ECR I–6303.

117 See also Section VB below.

118 S O'Leary, ‘Developing an Ever Closer Union between the Peoples of Europe?’(2008) Mitchell Working Paper (Edinburgh) 6/2008, 15–24. See also Golynker (n 39) 153–6.

119 Golynker (n 39) 151.

120 This issue is directly related to the interpretation of the derivative nature of the EU citizenship concept discussed above.

121 Evans, A, ‘Nationality Law and European Integration’ (1991) 16 ELR 190Google Scholar; de Groot, G-R, ‘Towards a European Nationality Law’ (2004) 8 Electronic Journal of Comparative LawGoogle Scholar.

122 HU Jessurun d'Oliveira (2010) Ontkoppeling van nationaliteit 785; HU Jessurun d'Oliveira, ‘Nationaliteit en de Europese Unie’ in Ongebogen recht: Opstellen aangeboden aan Prof. Dr. H. Meijers (Sdu 1998) 80–1.

123 HU Jessurun d'Oliveira, ‘Case Note 1. Decoupling Nationality and Union Citizenship?’ (2011) 7 EuConst 139.

124 Case C–135/08, Rottmann [2010] ECR I–1449, para 59. The case concerned, specifically, the loss of a Member State nationality and, consequently, of EU citizenship.

125 Following Gareth Davies, to separate the rules on loss and acquisition of nationality would be ‘highly illogical and inequitable’: Davies (n 38). Indeed, separating the acquisition from the loss of citizenship in the eyes of EU law would seemingly lead to a paradoxical conclusion that fundamental principles of EU law should only be safeguarded when EU citizenship is lost and not when it is being acquired. Without any doubt we will soon have more case law on this matter.

126 Davies (n 38).

127 ibid; Kochenov (n 24) 1831.

128 Case C–369/90 Micheletti [1992] ECR I–4239.

129 For an interesting perspective on this see Shaw (n 5).

130 Kochenov (n 24) 1831.

131 Kostakopoulou (2011) European Court of Justice; Kochenov (n 30) 182–6 (and the literature cited therein).

132 Declaration by the Government of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland on the Definition of the Term ‘Nationals’, 22 Jan 1972, 1972 OJ (L 73) 196; New Declaration by the Government of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland on the Definition of the Term ‘Nationals’, 28 Jan 1983, 1983 OJ (C23) 1. For analysis see de Groot (n 121) para 4.

133 Plender, R, ‘An Incipient Form of European Citizenship’ in Jacobs, FG (ed) European Law and the Individual (North-Holland 1976) 39Google Scholar.

134 Case C–192/99 Kaur [2001] ECR I–1237; Toner, H, ‘Annotation of Case C–192/99 Kaur’ (2001) 39 CMLRev 881Google Scholar; Kochenov and Plender (n 11) 281–2.

135 Dr. Rottmann lost his German nationality by the decision of the German Federal Administrative Court (BVerwG) that opined that such loss would be in full compliance with the EU principle of proportionality: German Federal Administrative Court, BVerwG 5 C 12.10. For more on the proportionality conditions in this case see eg Cambien, N, ‘Case C–125/08, Janko Rottmann v Freistaat Bayern’, 17 ColumJEurL (2011) 386–91Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 24).

136 Evans (n 121).

137 de Groot (n 121). See also Kochenov (n 30) 190–3 (and the literature cited therein).

138 For an analysis at a meta-level see Bogdandy, A von and Bast, J, ‘The European Union's Vertical Order of Competences: The Current Law and Proposals for Reform’ (2002) 39 CMLRev 227Google Scholar.

139 Evans (n 121); de Groot (n 121); Rostek, K and Davies, G, ‘The Impact of Union Citizenship on National Citizenship Policies’ (2006) 10 European Integration online Papers 1Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 40) (also covering several important exceptions, such as international visa-free travel).

140 Kochenov, D, ‘Double Nationality in the EU: An Argument for Tolerance’ (2011) 17 ELJ 330Google Scholar.

141 Davies, G, ‘“Any Place I Hang My Hat?” or: Residence is the New Nationality’ (2005) 11 ELJ 43CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

142 An important exception, which provides a mild counter-current to the generally observable trend, is the case law on the deportations of EU citizens. In a series of recent cases the ECJ seemingly succeeded in watering down the protections against deportations of long-term resident EU nationals, going against the letter and the spirit of the Directive 2004/38, in particular its art 28. See eg Case C–348/09 P.I. [2012] ECR I–0000, paras 28–29; Case C–145/09 Tsakouridis [2010] ECR I–11979, para 47. For criticism, see annotation by D Kochenov and B Pirker in ColumJEurL (2013, forthcoming).

143 This is so notwithstanding the fact that EU law as it stands does not prohibit the Member States from including EU citizens on foreigners’ registers: Case C–524/06 Huber v Germany [2008] ECR I–9705. Analysed by Hailbronner, K, ‘Are Union Citizens Still Foreigners?’ in Minderhoud, P and Trimikliniotis, N (eds), Rethinking the Free Movement of Workers: The European Challenges Ahead (Wolf Legal Publishers 2009)Google Scholar.

144 Wollenschläger (n 59) 4.

145 Davies (n 141) 55.

146 Kochenov (n 40) 4.

147 There have been several authoritative calls in the literature concerning the necessity to think about granting the EU such power. eg Evans, AC, ‘Nationality Law and the Free Movement of Persons in the EEC: With Special Reference to the British Nationality Act 1981’ (1980) 2 Yearbook of European Law 189Google Scholar; Blumann, C, ‘La citoyenneté de l'Union européenne (bientôt dix ans): Espoir et désillusion’ in Epping, V, Fischer, H and Heintschel, W von Heinegg (eds), Brücken Bauen und Begehen: Festschrift für Knut Ipsen zum 65 Geburtstag (CH Beck 2000) 3Google Scholar.

148 Kochenov (n 40). For a slightly updated short version see also Kochenov, D, ‘Member State Nationalities and the Internal Market: Illusions and Reality’ in Nic, N Shuibhne and Gormley, LW (eds), From Single Market to Economic Union: Essays in Memory of John A Usher (OUP 2012) 245Google Scholar.

149 Evans (n 121) 193.

150 Kochenov (n 40).

151 ibid 28–9.

152 See Section IIIC above.

153 ibid.

154 Tryfonidou, A, ‘Reverse Discrimination in Purely Internal Situations: An Incongruity in a Citizens’ Europe’ (2008) 35 LIEI 43Google Scholar; Tryfonidou, A, Reverse Discrimination in EC Law (Kluwer 2009)Google Scholar.

155 Shuibhne, N Nic, ‘Free Movement of Persons and the Wholly Internal Rule: Time to Move on?’ (2002) 39 CMLRev 731Google Scholar.

156 P Van Elsuwege and S Adam, ‘Situtations purement internes, discriminations à rebours et collectivités autonomes après l'arrêt sur l'Assurances soins flamande’ (2008) Cahiers de droit européen 655.

157 eg Hanf, D, ‘“Reverse Discrimination” in EU Law: Constitutional Aberration, Constitutional Necessity, or Judicial Choice’ (2011) 18 Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 26CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kochenov (n 71) 47–52 (and the literature cited therein).

158 Geelhoed, LA, ‘De vrijheid van personenverkeer en de interne situatie: maatschappelijke dynamiek en juridische rafels’ in Manunza, E and Senden, L (eds), De EU: De interstatelijkheid voorbij? (Wolf Legal Publishers 2006) 49Google Scholar; Slynn, Lord Gordon, Introducing a European Legal Order (Stevens and Sons 1992) 99Google Scholar.

159 For an important new analysis in the vein of the classical approach see eg Hanf (n 157).

160 Section IIIB above.

161 For discussion see Tryfonidou (2009) ‘Reverse Discrimination in EC Law’ (Kluwer 2009) 158.

162 Davies (n 82); Kochenov (n 71).

163 eg Case C–403/03 Egon Schempp v Finanzamt München V [2005] ECR I–6421, para 22.

164 Spaventa (n 96) 14.

165 eg Case C–413/99 Baumbast [2002] ECR I–7091; C–200/02 Zhu and Chen [2004] ECR I–9925; Case C–403/03 Schempp [2005] ECR I–6421, para 22; Case C–287/05 Hendrix [2007] ECR I–6909; Case C–213/05 Geven [2007] ECR I–6347; Case C–212/05 Hartmann [2007] ECR I–6303.

166 Spaventa (n 96) 14; Van Elsuwege and Adam (n 156) 334; Kochenov (n 71) 44.

167 Case C–200/02 Zhu and Chen [2004] ECR I–9925.

168 Case C–403/03 Schempp [2005] ECR I–6421.

169 Case C–148/02 Garcia Avello [2003] ECR I–11613.

170 Shuibhne, N Nic, ‘The European Union and Fundamental Rights: Well in Spirit but Considerably Rumpled in Body?’ in Beaumont, P, Lyons, C, and Walker, N (eds), Convergence and Divergence in European Public Law (Hart 2002) 188Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 71).

171 Opinion of AG Sharpston in Case C–212/06 Government of the French Community and Walloon Government [2008] ECR I–1683; Opinion of AG Sharpston in Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000.

172 Opinion of AG Sharpston in Case C–212/96 Government of the French Community [2008] ECR I–1683, paras 143–144.

173 Hanf (n 157).

174 Opinion of AG Kokott in Case C–434/09, McCarthy [2011] ECR I–0000, para 61.

175 Nic Shuibhne (n 175); Opinion of AG Sharpston in Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000, 139.

176 Section IIIB above.

177 Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

178 Elsuwege, P Van and Kochenov, D, ‘On the Limits of Judicial Intervention: EU Citizenship and Family Reunification Rights’ (2011) 13 European Journal of Migration and Law, 443CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kochenov (n 71) 47–52 (and the literature cited therein).

179 Case C–135/08, Rottmann [2010] ECR I–1449; Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000; Case C– 434/09 McCarthy [2011] ECR I–0000; Case C–256/11 Dereci [2011] ECR I–0000. For analysis, see eg Shuibhne, N Nic, ‘Annotation of Case C–434/09 McCarthy and Case C–256/11 Dereci’ (2012) 49 CMLRev 176Google Scholar; Adam, S and Van Elsuwege, P, ‘Citizenship Rights and the Federal Balance between the European Union and the Member States’ (2012) 37 ELR 176Google Scholar; Wiesbrock, A, ‘Disentangling the “Union Citizenship Puzzle”? The McCarthy Case’ (2011) 36 ELR 861Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 22); Van Elsuwege (n 22); Elsuwege, P Van, ‘European Union Citizenship and the Purely Internal Rule Revisited7 (2011) EuConst 208Google Scholar; Kay Hailbronner and Daniel Thym, ‘Annotation of Case C–34/09 Ruiz Zambrano’ (2011) 48 CMLRev 1253; Kochenov (n 24).

180 Kochenov (n 22); Ankersmit and Geursen (n 25); Van Elsuwege (n 22).

181 Shuibhne, N Nic, ‘Seven Questions for Seven Paragraphs (Editorial)36 EurLRev 161 (2011)Google Scholar.

182 Hailbronner and Thym (n 179).

183 Spaventa (n 96) 17. See also Everson, M, ‘The Legacy of the Market Citizen’ in Shaw, J and More, G (eds), New Legal Dynamics of European Union (OUP 1995) 73Google Scholar.

184 For a detailed analysis see Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

185 Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000, para 42 (emphasis added).

186 Lenaerts (n 9); Kochenov (n 22).

187 Case C– 434/09 McCarthy [2011] ECR I–0000, para 56; Kochenov ibid.

188 Kochenov ibid.

189 Case C–434/09, McCarthy [2011] ECR I–0000, para 53; Case C–135/08, Rottmann [2010] ECR I–1449, para 42; Case C–34/09, Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000, para 42.

190 Starting with S O'Leary, who published the first comprehensive monograph on EU citizenship: S O'Leary, The Evolving Concept of Community Citizenship (1996) 273–8. See also, inter alia, by Nic Shuibhne (n 175) 731; White, RCA., ‘Free Movement, Equal Treatment and Citizenship of the Union’ (2005) 4 ICLQ 885CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Spaventa (n 96) 13; Tryfonidou, A, ‘Reverse Discrimination in Purely Internal Situations: An Incongruity in a Citizens’ Europe’ (2008) 35 LIEI 44Google Scholar; Iliopoulou, A, ‘Libre circulation et non-discrimination, elements du statut de citoyen de l'Union européenne’ (Bruylant, 2008) 267Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 30) 234; Tryfonidou, A, Reverse Discrimination in EC Law (Kluwer 2009) 129Google Scholar; Kochenov (n 71) 80; Van Elsuwege (n 22).

191 D Kochenov (n 26); Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

192 Section IB above.

193 Dougan, M and Spaventa, E, ‘“Wish You Weren't Here …” New Models of Social Solidarity in the European Union’ in Spaventa, E and Dougan, M (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart 2005) 181Google Scholar.

194 ibid 182. See also GS Katrougalos, ‘The (Dim) Perspectives of European Social Citizenship’ (2007) Jean Monnet Working Paper (NYU) 05/08.

195 Barnard, C, ‘EU Citizenship and the Principle of Solidarity’ in Spaventa, E and Dougan, M (eds), Social Welfare and EU Law (Hart 2005) 157Google Scholar. See also R O'Gorman, ‘The Proportionality Principle and Union Citizenship’, (2009) Mitchell Working Paper (Edinburgh) 1/2009 4-11; Wind, M, ‘Post-National Citizenship in Europe: The EU as a “Welfare Rights Generator?”’ (2009) 15 ColumJEurL 239Google Scholar.

196 Barnard ibid; Barnard, C, ‘Social Policy Revisited in the Light of the Constitutional Debate’ in Barnard, C (ed), The Fundamentals of EU Law Revisited: Assessing the Impact of the Constitutional Debate (OUP 2007) 121Google Scholar.

197 S Maillard, ‘L’émergence de la citoyenneté sociale européenne’ (Presses Universitaires d'Aix-Marseille 2008) 65–80.

198 ibid 257ff.

199 While Sandrine Maillard, among numerous other scholars, seems to presume the non-application of the provision to third-country nationals (ibid 333–5), more progressive accounts are also available: P Boeles, ‘Europese burgers en derdelanders: Wat betekent het verbod van discriminatie naar nationaliteit sinds Amsterdam?’ (2005) 12 Sociaal-economische wetgeving 502; Epiney, A, ‘The Scope of Article 12 EC: Some Remarks on the Influence of European Citizenship’ (2007) 13 ELJ 611CrossRefGoogle Scholar; C Hublet, ‘The Scope of Article 12 of the Treaty of the European Communities vis-à-vis Third-Country Nationals: Evolution at Last?’ (2009 15 ELJ 757; Kochenov (n 30) 206–9.

200 An interesting situation, especially concerning posted workers, arose in the field of free movement of services and also in free movement of companies. See eg Belavusau, U, ‘The Case of Laval in the Contest of the Post-Enlargement EC Law Development’ (2008) 9 GLJ 2279CrossRefGoogle Scholar (and the literature cited therein). The issue virtually hijacked scholarly attention for a while.

201 Maillard (n 197) 353ff. [author's translation: ‘solidarity outwith nationality’].

202 ibid 443.

203 Thym, D, ‘Towards “Real” Citizenship? The Judicial Construction of Union Citizenship and its Limits’ in Adams, M et al. (eds), Judging Europe's Judges: The Legitimacy of the Case Law of the European Court of Justice Examined (Hart 2013, forthcoming)Google Scholar.

204 M Keating, ‘Social Citizenship, Solidarity and Welfare in Regionalised and Plurinational States’ (2009) 13 Citizenship Studies 506–10.

205 Dougan, M, ‘A Spectre Is Haunting Europe … Free Movement of Persons and Eastern Enlargement’ in Hillion, C (ed), EU Enlargement: A Legal Approach (Hart 2004) 112Google Scholar.

206 On ‘social dumping’ and enlargement see eg D Kukovec, ‘Whose Social Europe?’ (2011) IGL&P Paper No 3 Harvard Law School; Belavusau (n 200).

207 Keating (n 204). See also Barnard, C, ‘Social Dumping and the Race to the Bottom: Some Lessons for the European Union from Delaware?25 EurLRev 57 (2000)Google Scholar.

208 Keating ibid 506. Looking at the practical functioning of the social assistance systems, Keating thus entirely disagrees with the generally held view, espoused, inter alia by Richard Bellamy, that ‘welfare rights tend to be best protected in unitary, parliamentary systems where a strong and cohesive demos provides the social solidarity needed to allow legislative majority's [sic] to pass redistributive measures’: Bellamy, R, ‘The European Constitution Is Dead, Long Live European Constitutionalism13 Constellations 185 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

209 Davies (n 145).

210 ibid; Maillard (n 197) 410.

211 O'Leary (n 118) 15–24.

212 Case C–209/03 Bidar [2005] ECR I–2119; Golynker, O, ‘Student Loans: The European Concept of Social Justice According to Bidar’ (2006) 31 ELR 390Google Scholar.

213 Case C–158/07, Jacqueline Förster v IB-Groep [2008] ECR I–8507.

214 Mei, AP van der, ‘Union Citizenship and the Legality of Durational Residence Requirements for Entitlement to Student Financial Aid16 Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law (2009) 477Google Scholar; Mataija, M, ‘Case C–158/07, Jacqueline Förster v IB-Groep – Student Aid and Discrimination of Non-Nationals: Clarifying or Emaciating Bidar?’ (2009) 15 ColumJEurL 59Google Scholar.

215 Davies (n 82) 21; Mei, AP Van der, ‘Union Citizenship and the “De-Nationalisation” of the Territorial Welfare State’ (2005) 7 European Journal of Migration and Law 210Google Scholar.

216 Moreover, crucially, such ‘protection’ of the social security systems always works only one way, benefiting exclusively the richer states in the Union (and their residents), while ensuring a strict separation between the richer and poorer parts, as Damjan Kukovec (n 206) has brilliantly demonstrated in the only serious legal paper on the issue to date: Whose Social Europe?

217 Davies (n 82) 21.

218 Smith, AD, The Ethnic Origin of Nations (Blackwell 1986) 147Google Scholar.

219 ‘In a mythical system causality is artificial, false; but it creeps, so to speak through the back door of Nature’ R Barthes, Mythologies (trans Annette Lavers) (Farrar, Starus and Giroux 1972) 131.

220 Miller, D, ‘The Ethical Significance of Nationality’ (1988) 98 Ethics 657CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

221 Renan, Ernst, Qu'est-ce qu'une nation? et autres essais politiques (Agora 1992) [1st edn 1882] 41.

222 See on the patriotic sacrifice eg Walzer, M, ‘Civility and Civic Virtue in Contemporary America’ (1974) 41 Social Research 4Google Scholar.

223 Miller (n 220) 648. See also Chwaszcza, C., ‘The Unity of People, and Immigration in Liberal Theory’ (2009) 13 Citizenship Studies 451CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

224 Sala, V DellaPolitical Myth, Mythology and the European Union’ (2010) 48 JCMS 1Google Scholar.

225 Elsmore and Starup (2007) ‘Union Citizenship’, 61.

226 Bellamy (n 33) 609.

227 Weiler, JHH, ‘In Defence of the Status Quo: Europe's Constitutional Sonderweg’ in Weiler, JHH and Wind, M (eds), European Constitutionalism beyond the State (CUP 2003) 7Google Scholar.

228 Palombella (n 41).

229 See also Kostakopoulou, D, ‘Political Alchemies, Identity Games and the Sovereign Debt Instability: European Identity in Crisis or the Crisis in Identity-Talk?’ (2012) 63 RevIntlAff 97Google Scholar; D. Kochenov, ‘Mevrouw de Jong Gaat Eten: EU Citizenship and the Culture of Prejudice’ (2011) EUI Working Paper RSCAS 20011/06.

230 Weiler (n 227) 18.

231 Tully, J, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity (CUP 1995) 59CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

232 ibid 59–98.

233 Palombella (n 41) 365.

234 Bellamy (n 72).

235 Weiler (n 227).

236 K Nicolaïdes, The New Constitution as European Demoi–cracy? (2003) The Federal Trust for Education and Research No 38/03; Weiler ibid.

237 The term ‘identity’ itself is questioned: Kostakopoulou (n 229).

238 Gerhards, J, ‘Free to Move? The Acceptance of Free Movement of Labour and Non Discrimination among Citizens of Europe’ (2008) 10 European Societies 121CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

239 For the criticism of Bryce's work see eg A Vermeule ‘Government by Public Opinion: Bryce's Theory of the Constitution’ (2011) Harvard Public Law Working Paper No 11-13.

240 For a concise presentation see Gerhards (n 238) 127 (Figure 1).

241 77.8 per cent do not see any reason to discriminate: ibid.

242 Including Greece, where 87.3 per cent do not share the non-discrimination ideal: ibid.

243 96.3 per cent do not embrace non-discrimination: ibid.

244 Around 80 per cent do not share the ideal in Spain, Portugal, Italy, Austria and the former Eastern Germany: ibid.

245 56.1 per cent do not share the ideal: ibid.

246 On the specificity of Estonian case of legalized discrimination of non-citizen minorities see Poleshchuk, V (ed), A Chance to Survive: Minority Rights in Estonia (Foundation for Historical Outlook 2009)Google Scholar.

247 At least as far as it requires ensuring non-discrimination on the basis of nationality.

248 Kochenov (n 71) 74–85.

249 Palombella (n 41) 382. See also EMH Hirsch-Ballin, Burgerrechten (Universiteit van Amsterdam 2011); Kochenov (n 229).

250 Palombella (n 41); Kymlicka, W, ‘Liberal Nationalism and Cosmopolitan Justice’ in Benhabib, SAnother Cosmopolitanism (OUP 2006) 134Google Scholar. See also Davies, GHumiliation of the State as a Constitutional Tactic’ in Amtenbrink, F and Bergh, P van den (eds), The Constitutional Integrity of the European Union (TMC Asser Press 2010)Google Scholar.

251 Kymlicka ibid 134.

252 ibid 135.

253 Weiler, JHH, ‘Fundamental Rights and Fundamental Boundaries: Common Standards and Conflicting Values in the Protection of Human Rights in the European Legal Space’ in Kastoryano, R and Emmanuel, S (eds), An Identity for Europe: The Relevance of Multiculturalism in EU Constitution (Palgrave Macmillan 2009) 78Google Scholar.

254 Christian Joppke makes a compelling case for the finding that ‘the national particularisms, which immigrants and ethnic minorities are asked to accept across European states are but local versions of the universalistic idiom of liberal democracy’: Joppke, C, ‘Immigration and the Identity of Citizenship: The Paradox of Universalism’ (2008) 12 Citizenship Studies 542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

255 Kochenov (n 229) 12–15; Kochenov (n 51).

256 According to AG Poiares Maduro, ‘Citizenship of the Union must encourage Member States to no longer conceive of the legitimate link of integration only within the narrow bonds of the national community, but also within the wider context of the society of peoples of the Union’: Opinion of AG Poiares Maduro in Case C–499/06 Halina Nerkowska v Zakład Ubezpieczeń Społecznych Oddział w Koszalinie [2008] ECR 3993, para 23 (emphasis added).

257 For an overview and analysis, see R Bauböck and C Joppke (eds), ‘How Liberal Are Citizenship Tests?’ (2010) EUI RSCAS Working Paper 2010/41; Oers, R van, Ersbøll, E and Kostakopoulou, D, ‘Mapping the Redefinition of Belonging in Europe’ in Oers, R van, Ersbøll, E and Kostakopoulou, D (eds), A Re-definition of Belonging? (Koninklijke Brill 2010) 307CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Joppke, C, ‘Beyond National Models: Civic Integration Policies for Immigrants in Western Europe’ (2007) 30 West European Politics 1CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

258 Weiler (n 70) 82.

259 Jessurun d'Oliveira (n 122) ‘Nationaliteit en de Europese Unie’.

260 This disagreement might be caused by the idealistic vision of the ‘integration’ systems of the Member States. For a first-hand (critical) account of a Dutch culture test, for instance, see Kochenov (n 229).

261 AG Jacobs explained the mechanics of this function of EU citizenship in his Opinion in Case C–148/02 Garcia Avello [2003] ECR I–11613, at para 63 (footnotes omitted): ‘The concept of “moving and residing freely in the territory of the Member States” is not based on the hypothesis of a single move from one Member State to another, to be followed by integration into the latter. The intention is rather to allow free, and possibly related or even continuous, movement within a single “area of freedom, security and justice”, in which both cultural diversity and freedom from discrimination [are] ensured.’

262 For a meticulous overview of literature on the borders of belonging see Gibney, MJ, ‘The Rights of Non-citizens to Membership’ in Sawyer, C and Blitz, BK (eds), Statelessness in the European Union (Cambridge 2011) 41CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

263 Davies (n 141) 56 (emphasis added). See also Kostakopoulou, D, ‘Citizenship Goes Public: The Institutional Design of Anational Citizenship’ (2009) 17 Journal of Political Philosophy 275CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

264 Shachar, A and Hirschl, R, ‘Citizenship as Inherited Property’ (2007) 35 Political Theory 253CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

265 Kreimer, SF, ‘Federalism and Freedom’ (2001) 574 Annals AAPSS 66CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Hirschman, AO, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty (Harvard University Press 1970)Google Scholar.

266 Kochenov, D, ‘On Options of Citizens and Moral Choices of States: Gays and European Federalism’ (2009) 33 FordhamIntlLJ 156Google Scholar.

267 Flear, ML, ‘Developing Euro-Biocitizens through Migration for Healthcare Services’ (2007) 14 Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 239CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

268 Jørgensen, S, ‘The Right to Cross-Border Education in the European Union’ (2009) 46 CMLRev 1567Google Scholar.

269 eg Kreimer (n 265); Kreimer, SF, ‘Lines in the Sand: The Importance of Borders in American Federalism’ (2002) 150 UPaLRev 980–4Google Scholar; McConnell, M, ‘Review: Federalism: Evaluating the Founders’ Design’ (1987) 54 University of Chicago Law Review 1494CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

270 S Jørgensen (n 268).

271 Davies (n 250).

272 Weiler (n 253) 73.

273 Weiler (n 70) 64.

274 As discussed in Section IIIB above.

275 Weiler (n 253).

276 Palombella (n 41) 365.

277 ibid.

278 ibid.

279 According to Jageskiold, denying of the right to leave is ‘is a source of much unnecessary suffering around the world’: Jagerskiold, S, ‘The Freedom of Movement’ in Lenkin, L (ed), The International Bill of Rights. The Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (Columbia University Press 1981) 167Google Scholar.

280 Arts 9 EU and 20 TFEU.

281 Kochenov (n 30).

282 Opinion of AG Poiares Maduro in Case C–135/08 Rottmann [2010] ECR I–1449, para 23.

283 L Azoulai, ‘Marges de la citoyenneté européenne – Obligations étatiques, équité transnationale, Euro-Bonds’ in B Fauvarque-Cosson et al (eds), La citoyenneté européenne, (Société de la législation compareé 2011).

284 Balibar (n 48) 190.

285 Nic Shuibhne (n 61).

286 Wollenschläger (n 59).

287 Weiler (n 70).

288 Kochenov (n 71).

289 Williams, ‘Taking Values Seriously: Towards a Philosophy of EU Law’ (n 27); Williams (2010) The Ethos of Europe (n 27).

290 Case C–34/09 Ruiz Zambrano [2011] ECR I–0000, para 41.

291 Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

292 Golynker (n 39); O'Leary (n 118).

293 ibid 15.

294 Case C–135/08 Rottmann [2010] ECR I–1449.

295 Kochenov (n 148).

296 de Groot (n 121).

297 Wollenschläger (n 59) 4.

298 Davies (n 141) 55.

299 Kochenov (n 40).

300 Spaventa (n 96); Kochenov (n 71).

301 Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

302 Spaventa (n 96); Nic Shuibhne (n 175); Van Elsuwege and Adam (n 156).

303 Lenaerts (n 9); Kochenov (n 22).

304 Kochenov and Plender (n 11).

305 Van Elsuwege (n 22); Nic Shuibhne (n 181); Adam and Van Elsuwege (n 179).

306 Kochenov (n 26).

307 Maillard (n 197).

308 Keating (n 204).

309 Kukovec (n 206).

310 Davies (n 82).

311 Barnard (n 207); Keating (n 204) 506–10.

312 Palombella (n 41) 382.

313 Davies (n 250); Kochenov (n 229).

314 Weiler (n 235); Palombella (n 41).

315 Weiler (n 70).

316 A Williams, ‘Human Rights and the European Court of Justice: Past and Present Tendencies’ (2011) Legal Studies Research Paper Warwick Law School No 2011-06, 53.