In 1625 Christoph Besold stated that the law of nature is to have a free conscience and to believe what one wants.Footnote 1 This article contextualizes that claim and considers Besold's defence of it. Christoph Besold, a major legal authority of Protestant Germany during the 1620s and 1630s and seven-time rector of the Lutheran university of Tübingen, was well known even beyond the empire. His distinction between real majesty – owned by the state as a legal corporate person – and personal majesty – exercised by magistrates – as well as his taxonomy of the constitutional situation in various European countries, was referred to both inside and outside Germany. While his defence of the mixed constitution and of constitutional constraints binding the prince has thus attracted comment since the seventeenth century,Footnote 2 the fact that his constitutional approach came hand in hand with striking claims for freedom of conscience has rarely been noted. Nor has the passage quoted above received detailed treatment.Footnote 3
Since the early Reformation, claims for freedom of conscience for conscience's sake were raised both in England and Germany. They mainly addressed the need not to force consciences because of the nature of Christ's kingdom. None of these, though, were arguing a principled right to be left unmolested in private worship, let alone a natural right for freedom of conscience.Footnote 4 Rather, religious minorities emphasized that neither civil nor ecclesiastical authorities should intervene in the relation of the believer to God in order to protect their diversion from established churches and their rites. To established churches, whether in Geneva or Rome, to civil magistrates, and to most scholars, toleration meant temporarily to restrict the prosecution of impious and unlawful practices, not a right to heresy. Under the specific circumstances of the northern Netherlands, with its critique of the persecution of Protestants under Philip II and its strong Catholic minority, toleration of Catholic and other minorities could take spectacular forms, as in Amsterdam during the seventeenth century, but was continually assailed by members of the reformed church and never established as legal right. Some adherents of Arminius even had to leave the country in the wake of the religious controversies culminating in 1618/19.Footnote 5 Religious peace accords in France, Poland, and Germany were justified in terms of prudence and necessity and were meant to give way to the speedy reunification of all subjects into the true church. With the exception of Germany, most of these accords only held for limited periods.Footnote 6 In England, the toleration of Protestant dissent by the Act for the Relief of Peaceable People (1650) did emphatically not include Catholics but only Presbyterians, Congregationalists, and other groups still belonging to a Protestant camp broadly defined, and even this limited toleration was fiercely attacked by many Presbyterians. It was entirely revoked with the Restoration.Footnote 7 The idea that a group or a person could decide autonomously about their own faith was addressed as autonomia and remained highly controversial, for all confessional churches insisted on the enforcement of the one single true faith and its rites as a command of God.Footnote 8
Civil magistrates also considered the functional need of religious uniformity in any commonwealth. In book vii of his Politics, Aristotle had considered what is indispensable for any state to exist. After enumerating food, crafts, arms, and a certain material wealth, he had added as most important the common cult. Aristotle's teaching remained influential right into the seventeenth century.Footnote 9 As William Cecil put it in 1563 to a minister complaining about the demands of uniformity, ‘I will not argue with you, for my part is much stronger … neither you nor any one born under this kingdom may be permitted to break the bond of obedience.’Footnote 10 Right into the later seventeenth century, most clergy, including Puritan clergy, and laity in England held that subjects were bound to matters indifferent once ordered by established magistrates. Arguments denying that human laws bind the conscience in matters concerning worship were rooted in a specific religious preference and the defence of its way of worship against alleged civil interference against God's will, as for instance Samuel Rutherford's Divine right of church government (1646).Footnote 11 Ultimately, they rested on Acts 5, 29 (obey God more than men), the supreme duty to obey God as supreme lawgiver, not on a right against state and society.
Only from the later seventeenth century onwards did claims for toleration in a new and modern sense, as an outgrowth of a right, gain recognition among some philosophers. A new term for failure to grant this right, ‘intolerance’, was subsequently coined.Footnote 12 But as recent research has emphasized, even the new secular law of nature
was not deeply individualistic and dominated by the idea of subjective rights … few thinkers embraced, or even understood, the idea that moral agency, or personhood, might consist in asserting claims against the rest of the surrounding world with no other guidance than one's own lights … According to most natural lawyers in the seventeenth and eighteenth century, moral agency consisted in being subject to natural law and carrying out the duties imposed by such law, whereas rights were derivative, being means to the fulfilment of duties.Footnote 13
Natural law did thus rarely defend individual rights against society.
Against this background, Besold's claims were both highly original and surprising. They need to be understood both against the debate within the Holy Roman Empire as to what the legal specifications of the Peace of Augsburg of 1555 actually granted and against the changing use of references to the law of nature within legal discourse. In what follows, the debate with respect to the Peace of Augsburg is sketched before Besold's claims and contemporary arguments on personal rights are considered.
I
The Peace of Augsburg stipulated the civil estates recognizing no lord in jurisdiction and over their fiefs but the emperor could effectively choose between adherence to the Augsburg confession and allegiance to the Church of Rome. Continually attacked by the Lutherans, but seen as valid law by the Catholic estates and the emperor, ecclesiastical princes were meant to lose their titles, lands, and subjects in case of a conversion to Protestantism. Conversely, the declaratio ferdinandei that had granted that citizens and lower nobility of any Catholic prince could adhere to Lutheranism was never accepted by the Catholic estates.Footnote 14 Despite the fact that at least since the conversion of the Cologne Archbishop Gebhard Truchsess von Waldburg in 1582 these fundamental disagreements had sparked military strife within the empire, the Peace of Augsburg remained the commonly accepted basis for both Protestants and Catholics to deal with the problem of two different confessional churches and thus became the battleground for competing interpretations. In particular the ius emigrandi, whereby subjects could migrate to the jurisdiction of a neighbouring prince, with the religious allegiance as their own, became a beacon of Lutheran attempts to turn this provision into a right to private worship. This provision had originally been included into the treaty to allow territorial princes to get rid of heretic religious groups that might pose a threat to internal order or might encourage further heresy.Footnote 15 But until the 1620s, the substantial Lutheran groups among citizens and nobility in the Austrian Habsburg lands in particular defended their ‘right’ to Lutheran worship not least with respect to such interpretations.Footnote 16 In Brandenburg, the elector Sigismund von Hohenzollern had converted to the reformed faith in 1613, thereby weakening his constitutional position, while the Lutheran church and estates there even secured their confessional privileges as laws of the land.Footnote 17 Right into the 1620s, to Lutherans, legal and constitutional argument based on their interpretation of the Augsburg peace accord appeared a high-road to securing their faith.
By the 1580s, however, Emperor Rudolf II (1576–1611) had abandoned the more conciliatory approach of his predecessor Maximilian II. More than that, in particular Wilhelm II duke of Bavaria, educated by the Jesuits, pursued arguably the most active Counter-Reformation politics in the empire. He secured for his brother Ernst the Cologne archbishopric after the conversion of Truchsess von Waldburg. A major signal of this change of religious climate toward Counter-Reformation politics was the publication of Andreas Ernstberger's De autonomia in 1580.Footnote 18 It provided on 1,400 pages, reprinted in 1593 and 1602, one of the most uncompromising attacks against any interpretation of the Augsburg peace accord as favouring an extension of Protestant worship. Ernstberger attacked heretics by identifying their argument for toleration with the idea of autonomia. His publication heralded Catholic attempts at least to confine the toleration of heretics to as narrow an interpretation of what had been granted in 1555 as possible.Footnote 19
Ernstberger's treatise was an example of the Catholic politica, arguing that the church was a civitas, a political body of its own, with, as its members, civil magistrates obligated to obey its regulations.Footnote 20 Furthermore, the philosophical core of Lutheran heresy focused upon the ius emigrandi, with a view to granting private or even public Lutheran worship within Catholic jurisdictions. But to Ernstberger, what they promoted was libertas or licentia credendi, where individual subjects chose what to believe, independent of their civil states.Footnote 21 Ernstberger attacked in particular libertas est potestas vivendi ut velis, that liberty was the power to live as one wants, for liberty was only to be found in faith in God. That faith, however, was only to be found within the church and its teachings. Conscience had to be understood in relation to the ability of fallen men to produce rational and moral judgement. But most men were incapable of doing so on their own. Consciences had to be raised, shaped, and formed by the appropriate institutions of the church. Any respublica, imperium, or indeed any polity, in particular among Christians, could thus only exist within a church providing Christians with such good doctrine.Footnote 22 The toleration of heretics, though to be accepted for reasons of prudence and necessity for a time, always endangered both other believers and the polity as a whole. Along this argument, the Catholic estates in France fought off any royal attempt at religious compromise from the 1560s to 1580s.Footnote 23 For polemical reasons, Ernstberger had charged the Lutheran heresy as a whole with relieving men from the proper bounds of instruction. But in fact, most Lutheran churchmen broadly agreed with this line of reasoning, too.
In terms of their insistence on unity of state and church, Lutherans in general hardly differed from their Catholic counterparts. But they had to deal with the theological foundation of their church embedded in scripture and the early statements made by Luther on the issue of consciences. It remained undisputed that civil magistrates were under divine obligation to present the true gospel to their subjects. But right into 1523, responding to the pressure of Rome to prosecute him and his followers, Luther had insisted that force must not be used to implement any faith. His insistence on freedom of conscience and on the true nature of the Christian church, incompatible with such outward force, had rested on his persuasion that God will give faith independent of any human performance. Thus, in his 1523 On civil authority Luther had stated that belief is a ‘free work’ that should not be enforced, and that civil magistrates should leave subjects to believe as they ‘can and will’. The limits of what any hierarchy, civil or ecclesiastical, could or should enforce with regard to faith was the central point of this treatise.Footnote 24
Martin Heckel and Martin Honecker demonstrated how Lutheran theologians until the 1620s managed to combine their Lutheran tenets with the enforcement of ecclesiastical conformity.Footnote 25 Major Lutheran theologians like Johann Gerhard understood the church as a visible and an invisible one. To the visible church within each territory the need to give it some tangible structure applied, and here two further means came at hand. One was the major role of the prince, in terms of legal and material resources. Second, the idea that the church was made up of three estates: clergy, magistrates (i.e. princes), and laity. In descriptions of their relation to each other, the role of the laity was reduced to almost only listening; the clergy reserved successfully their role of defining the faith; and the princes had to defend the true church. In actual practice, the consistory courts of the Lutheran church were run by the leading clergymen and princely lawyers of the respective territory, in close association with professors of theology of Lutheran universities. A case in point is Johann Gerhard, the ‘father’ of Lutheran orthodoxy during the 1610s and 1620s. He advised princes to take responsibility for the faith of their subjects and to eject heretical subjects. The honour of God, the divine office of the prince, the salvation of men, the welfare of the country, and the unity of the church all demanded the prosecution of heretics. Gerhard clearly understood it to be the duty of the prince to promote the true faith among his subjects, due to the ‘officium magistratus in promovenda subditorum pietate’. Examples from the Old Testament, from Moses and Joshua, characterize his argument and show how important the idea of the unity of faith and state remained.Footnote 26 Given this state of debate, how did Besold, the leading jurist of the Lutheran university of Tübingen, seek to defend his claim?
II
Born 1577 as a lawyer's son, Besold graduated in 1591 from the philosophy faculty at Tübingen university. While there, he came in contact with Johannes Kepler and they came to write to one another actively. In 1599, Besold took his doctorate in both laws (Roman and Canon), became advocate to the Württemberg Hofgericht – the main territorial court of law – and was elected professor of Roman law, primarily Pandecten, in 1610. From 1614 to 1635, he served as rector of the university seven times. By the mid-1620s he had become the towering legal authority of Lutheran Germany.Footnote 27 His standing in the profession was not diminished by the fact that he was challenged twice by the Tübingen Lutheran ecclesiastical authorities, in 1622 for chiliastic interests and in 1626 for alleged Catholic leanings. By then, he had published his Prae-cognita philosophiae (preliminary thoughts on philosophy) in which he had praised the spiritual experience of Christ and had cited authors suspected by Lutheran orthodoxy for their heterodox spiritualism, among them Johannes Arndt (1555–1621), Master Eckhard (c. 1260 – c. 1328), and Valentin Weigel (1533–88).Footnote 28 Also in his letters to Kepler, he began to praise the simplicity of the early church and to ridicule confessional strife.Footnote 29 Besold survived both investigations and swore on the Lutheran book of Concord again in 1628. But in 1629, he spectacularly supported the Catholic point of view that the Württemberg church lands had been illegally alienated from the Church of Rome after 1552 in violation of the accords of Passau (1552) and Augsburg. In 1630, Besold secretly converted to Catholicism. In 1635, the conversion became public and he accepted a call to the Jesuit university of Ingolstadt. He also became an Imperial councillor and a councillor to the Catholic house of Wittelsbach.Footnote 30 His 1625 argument was neither consistent with his earlier 1614 criticism against using reason of state arguments with respect to issues of the church, nor with his later publications, revised according to a Catholic point of view after 1635.Footnote 31 Besold defended entirely different principles at different points in time. What we can discern from his publications is what seemed to be the best strategy to defend any one of them at any time toward the reading public of the empire.
Besold's treatise on the rights of majesty of civil magistrates over the church was the second part of his larger ‘On the rights of majesty in general’. Part one provided an overview of rights of majesty; part two concentrated on the rights over the church; part three focused on the rights within the polity; and part four considered mixed polities. The whole work contained 250 pages and was primarily a textbook for students looking for authoritative oversight from a major legal authority. Looking at the eight chapters in part two these considered the legal basis of the rights over the church as part of any right to govern: that atheists had to be prosecuted as part of the responsibilities of civil magistrates (i); the nature of the rights of civil magistrates (ii and iii); the relation of prince and clergy (iv); the issue of councils and synods (v); whether to fight heresy (vi) – here we find the argument in question; the administration of the goods and lands of the church (vii); finally, what estates and subjects should do in case of a change of confession of the prince (viii).
Besold attempted to bridge the discrepancy between his ideas and the legal and practical realities of ecclesiastical government in Germany from three vantage points. Theologically he quoted the early Luther that faith must not be forced by any government, civil or ecclesiastical. The arguments developed in the meantime on the distinction of the invisible and visible church and on the distribution of offices and responsibilities within the visible particular church were ignored. Legally he distinguished public and private worship. While the civil magistrate remained under obligation to enforce public worship according to the regulations of the Augsburg accords, private worship had to be left alone. In terms of political prudence he cited the example of Moscow and of the Dutch Republic that allegedly had good experiences of letting heretics pursue their faith unmolested. These arguments can be explored a little.
Besold stressed that civil magistrates did have responsibility for the church, as the early Luther had insisted. However, he was then quick to point out the allegedly abstruse nature of divergences of opinion among the confessional churches. Their clergy quarrelled among each other about ‘my pope, your pope, my Luther, your Luther’.Footnote 32 Indeed, in his letters to Kepler, he had ridiculed the debates among the confessional clergy in Germany and had insisted on the simplicity of the early church.Footnote 33 In his 1625 argument he proceeded to state that the office to preach was not an office to rule (‘ministerium non imperium constitutum’). The responsibility of the civil magistrate as a Christian member of the community was to promote faith by promoting the gospel, including provisions for church buildings, the clergy, and so forth. It did not mean to force consciences. For this, Besold fell back on the early Luther. He quoted in length from Luther's Against the papists, where Luther insisted that while Christian magistrates should promote the true faith, they must not enforce anything with the sword, for this was contrary to the spirit of Christ.Footnote 34
This qualification of the duties of magistrates with regard to the church – promotion of the gospel, not enforcement of consciences – was adapted by Besold to legal procedure by distinguishing public and private worship. Public heresy had to be prosecuted.Footnote 35 The quiet heretic had to be left alone. Already during the second half of the sixteenth century, the distinction between public and private worship had been used to negotiate the fact of two confessions within the empire, with their mutually exclusive claims and the need of unity and uniformity. An example for the strategic use of this distinction is provided by the negotiations about the Hungarian coronation ceremony of Maximilian, the eldest son of Emperor Ferdinand I. Maximilian had serious reservations about taking the Eucharist under the Catholic rite. In March 1561, the negotiations with the Hungarian estates to arrange for Maximilian's coronation as king of Hungary had collapsed over his demand to receive the Eucharist according to his Lutheran leanings sub utraque species. Emissaries from Vienna were sent to Pope Pius IV to gain Maximilian a dispensation. But Pope Pius wanted both to prevent Maximilian from converting entirely to Lutheranism and to support his German allies in their struggle to root out any compromise with the heretics. A public dispensation sat uneasily with those aims. Eventually, Pius resolved to grant Ferdinand papal authority to administer the Eucharist sub utraque specie to his son privately and secretly, with Maximilian required explicitly to admit the validity of the Catholic rite sub una specie.Footnote 36 What could not be granted publicly could be granted privately. Another example is the interpretation of the ius emigrandi by the Lutherans as allegedly granting at least private worship. There was, however, little willingness to grant Catholics in Protestant territories the same privilege.Footnote 37 In both examples, the distinction between private and public worship helped to negotiate the contradiction between the need to compromise with political partners whose faith one had to condemn as heretical and the principle of defence of the one true faith.
Besold also mentioned the ius emigrandi, but went much further with his claim of a natural right to free conscience. What had been a tool to negotiate such problems in exceptional circumstances was now turned into a provision that was going to provide a space of free choice to believe what one wanted protected by natural law. The two stepping stones toward his claim of a natural right, his reference to Luther and his distinction between private and public worship, were not new, but were turned into an entirely different context by using them as explanation and as providing a legal space for the exercise of a natural right.Footnote 38 Besold then attacked Ernstberger and argued that territorial estates could hire their own preachers.Footnote 39 Here, he remained in line with Lutheran claims, particularly as developed in Austrian lands where sizeable Lutheran groups had considerable influence on the territorial estates.Footnote 40 He finally concluded by citing the Dutch Republic and Moscow and their political success in tolerating all sorts of heretics, not only Christians.Footnote 41 In making this point, he plainly contradicted most contemporary political advice on this issue.
Besold combined theological, legal, and political points of view. Theologically, there was nothing that any civil or ecclesiastical magistrate should do concerning religion other than making the true gospel publicly available. Magistrates must not intervene in the relation of God and man's conscience. The early Luther provided Besold with ample material in support of this point. In making this argument, it was crucial to ignore the developments of the preceding century distinguishing between the visible and invisible church in order to transfer Luther's faith in the power of the divine word into the early seventeenth century. Second, Besold's distinction of private and public worship allowed submitting to the public responsibilities of all magistrates in the empire, while magistrates left private worship unmolested. Far beyond the almost conventional Lutheran claim to allow private worship as allegedly granted by the ius emigrandi of the Augsburg peace accord, he insisted on a right by law of nature. His conclusion from the early Luther's insistence on the limits of the use of the magistrate's sword to such a right provided arguably the most drastic reception of Luther's thoughts at that time. In effect, he transferred Luther's claim based on the reformer's trust in the work of the divine word into a juridical claim for subjects against their civil and ecclesiastical magistrates. Since there was no positive stipulation anywhere on which such a claim could be based, Besold chose to cover his argument with the claim that the law of nature provided such freedom. Third and finally, examples from prudence suggest that magistrates serve their own interest and that of the polity best by not prosecuting heretics.
In the other parts of his treatise, Besold's main strategy rested on limiting the room for manoeuvre of the prince by constitutional constraints embedded in the laws of the empire and territories. For example, in chapter viii on a prince changing his confession Besold argued in favour of the legitimate defence of the laws of a territory against that prince.Footnote 42 The Augsburg treaty had allegedly guaranteed the influence of the estates.Footnote 43 Any prince owed his rights over the church to his role as its prime member (‘praecipuum ecclesiae membrum’) rather than lord over the church. He had thus to administer with the consensus of the church (‘ac ecclesiae consensu’). He could thus only use those means given to Christ and the apostles, persuasion and faith, not force (‘debent adhibere media, quae Christu et Apostoli praescripserunt’).Footnote 44
These arguments were embedded in his treatise on the Rights of majesty. There he insisted on the scattered nature of these rights and the subsequent limitations on princely rule. Besold distinguished between real majesty – owed by the state as a legal person itself – and personal majesty, handled by the prince and then again between his ordinary and his extraordinary powers.Footnote 45 He stressed the need for any law or measure to be in accordance with the law of nature.Footnote 46 Magistrates were thus obliged to leave consciences unmolested. Besold also insisted on the limitations of princely rule by the Imperial laws.Footnote 47 Within the empire, the territories also had specific fundamental laws.Footnote 48 Any respublica was a ‘coetus’, a bond of men, based on the consensus of the political community.Footnote 49 The community of the empire rested on its fundamental laws and the agreements at the Imperial diet.Footnote 50 His praise for the dukes of Württemberg did not qualify this approach to limited princely rule.Footnote 51 Princely power had to be exercised within strict legal confines.Footnote 52 The description of royal rule in 1 Samuel 8, the basis of claims to absolutism as made by James VI and I of Scotland and England in his True law of free monarchies,Footnote 53 was understood by Besold to be plain tyranny. Besold referred to other Lutheran legal scholars who had claimed, arguing from a feudal basis, that territorial estates had a right to defend the value of their holdings against a prince threatening them with measures beyond his legitimate authority. In defence of these holdings, vassals could resist their prince. During the 1620s, the estates in Württemberg and Hesse-Cassel did just that.Footnote 54 Also in other publications, the diverse nature of lordship was emphasized and the scattered nature of territorial rule analysed.Footnote 55 The failed second reformation in Brandenburg is only one example of this state of relations among princes and estates in Lutheran Germany that made Besold's account feasible as a basic introduction for students to become servants and advisers to princes in their later career. What about his claim on the law of nature?
III
During the later middle ages, there was an academic debate about the right to self-defence by law of nature against illegal actions of servants of a court of law. Such a possibility was rarely perceived to be an option in conflicts between a lord and his subjects.Footnote 56 The law of nature that Aquinas had introduced as part of his introduction of Aristotle into theology and philosophy addressed the presence of divine law in the limited reason of men. It was not a clear-cut system of norms to be applied in practice.Footnote 57 Only in some respects, for instance on the validity of an unwritten contract as natural obligation (obligatio naturalis), it provided clear guidelines.Footnote 58 But although the view remained agreed that all laws and all government must submit to divine law and the law of nature, jurists remained highly sceptical about any direct recourse to natural law, because it did not provide a clear cut and consistent summary of applicable rules.Footnote 59
The discourse of the Protestant Reformation in the empire did not only include the idiom of the law of nature, but, by beginning to distinguish between the divine law of nature and human natural law, began to work toward a more systematic applicability of natural law.Footnote 60 For Melanchthon and for many Lutheran jurists, as we know from the recent work of Christoph Strohm, the idiom of natural law became a term to summarize their search for guiding ethical principles necessary to understand, teach, and apply Roman and any other law. The teachings of the Stoics became a guideline to formulate these ethical principles.Footnote 61 As Roman law became historicized, the search for such ethical golden rules intensified. Lutheran and reformed jurisprudence increasingly referred to the law of nature, citing Roman law for a definition of natural law.Footnote 62 By the early seventeenth century, the deliberations of Spanish scholars such as Fernando Vasquez and Luis Molina were quoted by legal scholars in the empire such as Althusius and Besold. Vasquez, for example, attempted to define ‘each man's dominium’ as ‘a free faculty in suo’ for the sake of keeping justice among all.Footnote 63
Against this background, the reformed jurist Hugo Donellus had started to speak of specific rights inseparable from any person, including life, body, liberty, and reputation.Footnote 64 He defined the rights of persons as those they could legitimately claim.Footnote 65 In his legal encyclopaedia, the Dicaeologica, Johannes Althusius referred to these developments. In book i, part ii, he defined liberty as a right to dominate, consisting of a right to rule and a need to obey or be ruled (‘dominatio cum iure imperandi & necessitate obtemperandi’). Our control over our own body and soul is exercised within the framework of what is just (ch. 25) and is thus described as right and authority to do according to one's will what is licit (‘est jus & auctoritas licita faciendi pro arbitrio’, book I, ch. 25, n. 5). Althusius then addressed the right of liberty in one's own person and its rights (‘jus libertatis in ipsam personam liberam et res ipsius’, n. 9). He defined it as the right of liberty on one's own person concerning the right to have oneself and to release oneself (‘jus libertatis personam concernens est jus habendi & dimittendi sui ipsius’, ch. 25, n. 10).Footnote 66 The exercise of this liberty, however, hinges on what is just. While body, life, limbs, and reputation are described as protected under normal circumstances,Footnote 67 the end of government remains the enforcement of justice in the commonwealth, including the enforcement of true religion. Both Althusius and Donellus advocated the duty and right of civil magistrates to enforce the true faith. Both took it for granted that the community has as its prime rationale the enforcement of a life following certain precepts, and that subjective rights come second to these.Footnote 68 Hence civil magistrates had a right to censure consciences.Footnote 69 The concept of liberty as dominium, and of certain liberties as inalienable dominium, did in no way preclude the enforcement of the true faith and the prosecution of heresy. Besold did know Althusius's works, but he could not have taken his claim for a natural right to a free conscience from either Donellus or Althusius.
IV
In general, there were three reasons not to prosecute heretics, despite the arguments from classic reason of state and the demands from the confessional churches. One, plain necessity and expediency could suggest allowing the toleration of heretics for as long as necessary. That was essentially the argument of the Augsburg Peace. Second, one could attempt to deny the fact of the divisions within the Christian faith by either arguing adiaphora or irenic points of view, in any case emphasizing common points of Christianity.Footnote 70 Third, one could argue that the state had really nothing to do with the churches and could and should protect various religious communities as long as public peace was not endangered.
This latter position developed arguably from the time of Pufendorf, though within the confines of what the territorial princes were obliged to do according to the treaties of Augsburg (1555) and Westphalia (1648). Both obliged them to privilege certain confessions. Only from the disestablishment of the empire onwards in 1806 could the now sovereign princes treat the churches as private associations that had no specific claim to public privileges over each other. Before the later eighteenth century and the intellectual breakthrough of the claim that ‘society [should be] denied the right to subordinate a natural entelechy to a social objective’,Footnote 71 what was perceived to be the common good, in particular as defined by divine and natural law, had to break private selfishness and private concerns. This was to be found in later medieval debate just as in most accounts of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century natural law. Thus, natural law hardly delivered rights against the rest of society or against accepted views of what the divine law was. Even to Locke, the alleged threat from the Church of Rome severely limited the room for manoeuvre he was willing to grant Roman Catholics. Luther's early insistence that consciences must not be forced did have forerunners in late medieval debate, all emphasizing, like Luther himself, that Christ's kingdom was not of this world.Footnote 72 This attitude, however, did not in any principled way deny the right of civil or ecclesiastical authorities to prevent heresy spreading and to enforce God's word among subjects. No matter how carefully the issue of consciences was considered, this care did not translate into any principled claim that subjects had a right to believe what they want. Later, Christian Thomasius, who wished to protect himself and other subjects from the demands of the confessional churches, did thus submit the church as fully as possible to princely control and argued in favour of a state church everyone had to attend, no matter what consciences demanded.Footnote 73
Given this state of affairs, Besold faced two challenges. First, he had to formulate his claim about the law of nature as a subjective right unaffected by society's perception of the common good and true belief. Second, he had to couch this formulation in terms acceptable to his readers among civil and ecclesiastical magistrates, who, as he had already experienced in Tübingen, had no hesitation in using their administrative and legal authority to check whether he was still fit for his office.
Besold combined a threefold strategy. As with Luther, he argued that consciences must never be forced, marginalizing here Protestant ecclesiastical authority developed over the previous century. Under cover of protection from Luther, he emphasized the specific nature of consciences and belief. His distinction between public and private worship allowed him to suggest to civil magistrates that they could be fully dutiful to the church by concentrating entirely on the provision of public worship and the defence of public peace, but leaving private subjects alone in their private worship. Here, he added his extra proviso on the natural right to believe what one wants, carefully embedded in more conventional claims, though turning them into an entirely new context. Thus, he exploited the idiom of natural law in order to transfer Luther's vision, based on the reformer's trust in the work of the divine word, into a juridical claim for subjects against their civil and ecclesiastical magistrates. Finally, Besold replaced the classic argument about the functional need for unity of church and state with the pragmatic advantages of toleration as shown by the Netherlands and Moscow.
Three points can be made to help explain Besold's position. One, surely, is his erratic character or the development of his ideas. As has been mentioned, Besold argued very different points at different times. Second, though there were medieval roots to arguments for freedom of consciences, Luther not only reinforced these but did so with such force that they were taken up by Protestant minorities across Europe. Besold was not the only writer who sought support for unconventional views on the nature of the church from citations of the early Luther. Some English separatists and puritans did the same. Indeed, some of Luther's statements were occasionally even understood to be problematic with respect to the unity of the church. Walter Travers (1548–1635), one of the opponents of Whitgift in the admonition debate and the author of ‘that most radical of Presbyterian texts, the Book of Discipline’,Footnote 74 put Luther beside Calvin as a ‘new apostle’.Footnote 75 William Ames praised Luther along with Zwingli and Wycliffe as among ‘the first restorers of the Gospel’.Footnote 76 The separatist Henry Jacob quoted not only Luther alongside Cyprian, Cartwright, and Calvin, but referred also to the Lutheran theologian Chemnitz to bolster his argument that true ecclesiastical government flows from the people's ‘free consent’.Footnote 77 The Puritan Paul Baynes critically remarked in his Diocesans trall (1621) that the
ordinary power of the execution thereof was not [my italics] given to the community of the church, or to the whole multitude of the faithful, so that they were the immediate and first receptacle, receiving it from Christ, and virtually deriving it to others. This I set down against [my italics] the Divines of Constance and our prime Divines, Luther and Melanchthon.Footnote 78
It is not surprising that those fearing prosecution from the officially established churches, like Besold himself, made an effort to hide their aims behind the celebrated reformer's words, though Luther later amended his views in favour of ecclesiastical government.
Third, in conjunction with Luther's influence, sophisticated juridical debate developed within the empire to solve the problem of two different religious confessions within a single polity. Though doubts had increased as to the nature of this unity since the 1640s,Footnote 79 the peace accords of 1555 and 1648 to regulate the relation between the two (and later de facto three) confessional churches were drawn by contemporaries who remained entirely convinced of the necessity of unity of church and state.Footnote 80 But as they attempted to find a compromise by technical formulae and regulations, they provided an environment where the Lutherans in particular attempted to argue in favour of legal spaces to exercise their faith within Catholic jurisdiction. Thus, the scene was set for attempts to provide toleration by way of providing technical legal provision. This kind of debate was specifically encouraged by the attempt to find legal compromise to solve the fact of religious diversity in the wake of the Augsburg peace accord. The preceding argument stressed how far-reaching the consequences of this debate could be. Although inadequate as an appreciation of the point of view of Lutheran orthodox clergy, it is thus understandable that Catholics such as Ernstberger argued that what lurked behind some of these suggestions was really not a limited toleration but full-scale ‘autonomy’.Footnote 81
It has long been argued that since the later seventeenth century, legal scholars and philosophers increasingly attempted to infuse the existing peace regulations with new philosophical meanings. With Besold in mind, we need to place the beginnings of this process earlier than hitherto thought. His claim for a natural right of free conscience is an important example of how far, and how early, Lutheran jurisprudence in the empire sought to infuse the existing treaties with novel visions of the relation of civil and ecclesiastical authority to ordinary believers. Besold, however, is also important for another reason. The positive evaluation of princely territorial absolutism, characteristic of later Protestant political thought in the empire, stressed by Leonard Krieger in formulating the ‘German idea of freedom’, was precisely not part of Besold's agenda.Footnote 82 In contrast to men like Thomasius or Pufendorf, his prince was squeezed between mighty imperial institutions, such as the Aulic and Imperial chamber courts, the fundamental laws of the empire, and the estates of their own lands. The German politica from the hands of Arnisaeus or Besold of the first half of the seventeenth century was clearly recognized by scholars and politicians in England and France. Besold's arguments were, indeed, more influential than is generally recognized.