Hostname: page-component-7b9c58cd5d-v2ckm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-16T14:55:36.864Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the stability of norms and norm-following propensity: a cross-cultural panel study with adolescents

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2025

Erik O. Kimbrough*
Affiliation:
Smith Institute for Political Economy and Philosophy, Argyros College of Business and Economics, Chapman University, Orange, USA
Erin L. Krupka
Affiliation:
School of Information, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, USA
Rajnish Kumar
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Queen’s Business School, Queen’s University Belfast, Belfast, UK
Jennifer M. Murray
Affiliation:
Centre for Public Health, Queen’s University Belfast, Belfast, UK
Abhijit Ramalingam
Affiliation:
Department of Economics, Appalachian State University, Boone, USA
Sharon Sánchez-Franco
Affiliation:
School of Medicine, Universidad de los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia
Olga L. Sarmiento
Affiliation:
School of Medicine, Universidad de los Andes, Bogotá, Colombia
Frank Kee
Affiliation:
Centre for Public Health, Queen’s University Belfast, Belfast, UK
Ruth F. Hunter
Affiliation:
Centre for Public Health, Queen’s University Belfast, Belfast, UK
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Norm-based accounts of social behavior in economics typically reflect tradeoffs between maximization of own consumption utility and conformity to social norms. Theories of norm-following tend to assume that there exists a single, stable, commonly known injunctive social norm for a given choice setting and that each person has a stable propensity to follow social norms. We collect panel data on 1468 participants aged 11–15 years in Belfast, Northern Ireland and Bogotá, Colombia in which we measure norms for the dictator game and norm-following propensity twice at 10 weeks apart. We test these basic assumptions and find that norm-following propensity is stable, on average, but reported norms show evidence of change. We find that individual-level variation in reported norms between people and within people across time has interpretable structure using a series of latent transition analyses (LTA) which extend latent class models to a panel setting. The best fitting model includes five latent classes corresponding to five sets of normative beliefs that can be interpreted in terms of what respondents view as “appropriate” (e.g. equality vs. generosity) and how they view deviations (e.g. deontological vs. consequentialist). We also show that a major predictor of changing latent classes over time comes from dissimilarity to others in one’s network. Our application of LTA demonstrates how researchers can engage with heterogeneity in normative perceptions by identifying latent classes of beliefs and deepening understanding of the extent to which norms are shared, stable, and can be predicted to change. Finally, we contribute to the nascent experimental literature on the economic behavior of children and adolescents.

Type
Original Paper
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC-BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s) 2024

1 Introduction

Economists have come to understand that social behavior is, among other things, norm-governed. Norms are often conceptualized as beliefs about and standards of appropriate behavior (Bicchieri, Reference Bicchieri2006; Cialdini & Trost, Reference Cialdini, Trost, Gilbert, Fiske and Lindzey1998); they also coordinate actions and expectations in interactions with multiple equilibria (Binmore & Samuelson, Reference Binmore and Samuelson2006; Gintis, Reference Gintis2009; Sugden, Reference Sugden1995).Footnote 1 Models of norm-driven choice assume that people seek both their own consumption utility and to adhere to commonly known injunctive norms, creating trade-offs when those two objectives conflict, which individuals resolve differently depending on the weight they assign to normative goals.Footnote 2 Thus, to understand how norms shape decisions, both the norms themselves and the individual propensity to follow them have become objects of study and quantification (Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018; Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013).

With measures of norms and/or norm-following propensity in hand, researchers attempt to assess the predictive validity of these models (see e.g., Kranton 2002, 2005, Benjamin, Choi, and Strickland 2010, Chang et al., Reference Chang, Chen and Krupka2019, Eckel et al., 2021, Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, and Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013). This approach depends crucially on a few assumptions that have not been widely tested empirically. First, these models and associated measurement strategies assume what we call “norm uniqueness”, i.e. that reports about norms capture a single shared norm, with error, and that the error is mere noise. Second, they assume “norm stability”, or that absent intervention the norm doesn’t change, such that the average change in reports about the norm should equal zero in a panel setting. Finally, these theories assume “preference stability”: that individual norm-following propensity is a constant individual-level characteristic.

In this paper, we elicit norms and a proxy measure for individual norm-following propensity in two periods using an experiment to test these assumptions (Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018; Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013).Footnote 3 Specifically, we exploit a convenience panel with a large sample of adolescents: 1,468 student participants aged 11–15 years who were subjects in a study on smoking norms and social networks.Footnote 4 As a control question, the study collected panel data on normative beliefs about dictator game giving and a proxy measure of propensity to follow norms two times separated by 10 weeks. Since the dictator game is a workhorse in the norms literature, this presented an opportunity to explore these important conceptual and methodological issues. Collecting such data among adolescents also presents a valuable opportunity since moral reasoning and social cognitive skills are both developing in these years (Maggian & Velleval, Reference Maggian and Villeval2016; Sutter et al., Reference Sutter, Zoller and Glätzle-Rützler2019). We use these data to test the hypotheses that norms and norm-following propensity are stable, on average, at the population level, and then at the individual level.

We find that norm-following propensity is stable, on average, but reported norms show some evidence of change, even over a 10-week period. While we did not start our research project expecting to find unstable norms, that is what our data reveal. Thus, we take the opportunity to explore the nature of this instability. Since peoples’ normative views of the “same game” seem to be changing over time, this raises the question of whether people perceive the same norm to begin with (i.e. evidence of instability may also contain evidence of non-uniqueness). Thus, we explore whether individual-level variation in reported norms between people and within people across time has interpretable structure using latent transition analyses, which extend latent class models to a panel setting. Our analysis reveals that individual-level variation in reported norms has structure. The best fitting model includes five latent classes corresponding to five sets of normative beliefs that can be interpreted in terms of what respondents view as “appropriate” (e.g. equality vs. generosity) and how they view deviations from the most appropriate action (e.g. deontological vs. consequentialist). We also find that many subjects appear to change latent classes over time. Thus, subjects arrive at our study with heterogeneous views about what is normatively appropriate in the dictator game, and many exhibit some change in those views over time.

This raises the question of why normative views are changing over our 10-week period in the absence of intervention. A reasonable hypothesis is that a subject pool in which peers repeatedly interact between waves should only get better at guessing each other’s views in the presence of incentives to coordinate. With initial heterogeneity in beliefs, the incentive to coordinate may therefore encourage subjects to report entirely different normative beliefs at wave 2 if they learn that their beliefs differ from their peers. Thus, we exploit another convenient feature of our data, which includes measures of peer networks, and we show that observed changes in normative perspective are not arbitrary but can be predicted by information about subjects’ similarity to their peer networks.Footnote 5 We find that subjects who are more dissimilar to their peers are more likely to be categorized in a different latent class in wave 2. Surprisingly this does not lead to a higher coordination rate in wave 2. Thus, we can predict to some extent who changes, but not how they will change. This suggests that there is genuine normative uncertainty or disagreement in this environment. More broadly, this exercise serves as a proof of concept that illustrates the kinds of questions researchers can ask when analyzing heterogeneous normative beliefs.

Our first contribution is to advance research on norms by testing some of the basic assumptions of models of norm-driven behavior. We provide evidence that the propensity to follow norms is stable, on average, in our sample. We show that normative beliefs are not entirely consistent over time, on average, and we thus unpack the working assumption that there is a single, stable injunctive norm in any choice context. We argue that researchers should be careful to conceptualize injunctive norms as a complete profile of beliefs about the relative appropriateness of all possible actions. We show that such normative belief profiles, even in the dictator game, are strikingly heterogeneous and that this heterogeneity can be decomposed into meaningful classes. In this, we join a recent paper by Fromell et al., (Reference Fromell, Nosenzo, Owens and Tufano2021) which also finds that a plurality of norms exists in the specific context of norms that regulate the trade-off between wealth accumulation through saving and sharing income with kin and neighbors in rural Kenya.

Our second contribution is methodological; we use repeated experimental elicitation and latent transition analysis to make sense of observed heterogeneity in our data. The novel approach using latent transition analysis allows us to identify the relevant classes of normative beliefs and assess the extent to which subjects change classes over time. Latent variable models allow us to identify distinct “types” and transitions between them in a constant decision environment. Using adolescents has some drawbacks related to how malleable and sensitive to social influences they may be. However, it also has some strengths for the question we are looking at and the methods we employ. Notably, this subject pool is brought together daily in a social context and in a similar way each day (i.e., they attend school). The attrition in our subject pool is thus minimal. In addition, the students are motivated to participate and interested in being part of the study. As such, their attention is likely high. Taken together, these factors mean that our subject pool is ideal for demonstrating the promise of latent transition analysis, which requires a large panel with minimal attrition.

Third, we show how to use the identified classes to characterize and predict normative belief change such that people who hold similar normative views to their peers, are less likely to change their views. With these advances in how we treat variation, we hope researchers will have much more to say about when a norm is shared in a population, whether it is strong or weak, and how and at what moment norm change (at the individual and aggregate level) has taken place.

Finally, we contribute to the nascent experimental literature on the economic behavior of children and adolescents. In particular, we contribute to a topic that has received little attention—the study of coordination games among this population. That said, the malleability of opinion or belief formation at this age suggests that our findings could be an upper bound on norm heterogeneity, norm profiles and norm change.

2 Background and motivation

We start from the premise that choice data is not sufficient to reveal an injunctive norm, because the same choice can be attributable to different motives (e.g. an equal split in the dictator game could reflect both a norm of generosity and a norm of egalitarianism). Thus, economists have developed methods designed to elicit normative beliefs directly, and the idea of norm uniqueness has guided the design of these measurement techniques (Nosenzo & Görges, Reference Nosenzo and Görges2020). Krupka and Weber (Reference Krupka and Weber2013) elicit individual normative beliefs by asking participants to play a “pure matching” coordination game (Mehta et al., Reference Mehta, Starmer and Sugden1994; Schelling, Reference Schelling1960) in which their goal is to anticipate the extent to which others in their group will rate an action as socially appropriate or inappropriate, and to respond accordingly. The incentives do not reward participants for revealing their own views, but instead reward them for matching their appropriateness ratings with other participants in the experiment. This technique neatly captures the idea of a norm as a set of shared beliefs about what is and is not appropriate, and reported norms have been shown to be robust to alternative (non-normative) focal points (Fallucchi & Nosenzo, Reference Fallucchi and Nosenzo2021).

Norm uniqueness also infuses how norms are discussed in the literature; the typical approach describes a norm in terms of a single prescriptive action (e.g. the “norm is to tip 20%” or “to split 50–50”), with all remaining actions (implicitly) seen as equally inappropriate actions that should not be taken (e.g., Akerlof & Kranton, Reference Akerlof and Kranton2005; Andreoni & Bernheim, Reference Andreoni and Bernheim2009). This has influenced the interpretation of data collected to measure norms: the norm is often identified by the action that was given the highest mean (or modal) normative evaluation by participants (e.g. “there is a clear norm of equal division” in the dictator game, Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, p. 633).

However, as several papers note, using only the most appropriate action to capture the norm discards valuable information about normative beliefs (Chang et al., Reference Chang, Chen and Krupka2019; Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013). Instead, thinking of norms as a profile of normative beliefs across a set of related actions emphasizes that norms define both what is most appropriate and how bad it is to deviate from that (Nosenzo & Görges, Reference Nosenzo and Görges2020). The profile of normative evaluations across a set of related actions conveys both of those features of a norm. That is, the shape of the function mapping actions to evaluations of appropriateness is what really defines a norm. The relevant normative tradeoff is then characterized by a norm-dependent utility function that incorporates heterogeneity in norm-following propensity (Bicchieri, Reference Bicchieri2006; Cappelen et al., Reference Cappelen, Hole, Sørensen and Tungodden2007; Kessler & Leider, Reference Kessler and Leider2012; Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2022; Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013; Lopez-Perez, Reference López-Pérez2008).Footnote 6

Even when researchers have focused on the profile of responses in their analysis, the emphasis on shared-ness has led to a working assumption that there is a single norm profile representing the injunctive norm in a given choice context. One exception is a recent paper by Fromell et al., (Reference Fromell, Nosenzo, Owens and Tufano2021). They use a lab-in-the-field experiment in Kenya and identify multiple parallel social norms that regulate the trade-off between wealth accumulation through saving and sharing income with kin and neighbors. Specifically, they find that one group (a minority) of participants perceive a “strict” norm of sharing while a second group (most participants) recognize moderate accumulation of wealth as socially acceptable and yet a third group (about a quarter) of participants perceive a “pro-saving” norm, whereby keeping most of one’s wealth for oneself is the most appropriate course of action. Notwithstanding the Fromell et al., paper, it is a wide-spread practice to assume that individual deviations from the average (or sometimes modal) response for any one action being evaluated represent measurement error (Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013). But if individual deviations from the average norm profile have structure, then they are not “errors”. Rather, they may instead be evidence of multiple contemporaneous norms and/or ongoing normative change. These two possibilities are the focus of this paper.

There is some cause for skepticism about the assumption that variation reflects mere measurement error. One reason is that norms are arguably indexed to identity groups such that normative prescriptions depend on one’s identities and their salience at a particular moment (Akerlof & Kranton, Reference Akerlof and Kranton2000). Consistent with this view, Burks and Krupka (Reference Burks and Krupka2012), Chang et al., (Reference Chang, Chen and Krupka2019), Pickup et al., (Reference Pickup, Kimbrough and de Rooij2021), and Groenendyk et al., (Reference Groenendyk, Kimbrough and Pickup2021) provide evidence that different social groups, such as managers and employees, democrats and republicans, or liberals and conservatives, disagree about the appropriateness of a variety of actions. More important for the purposes of this paper, starting even before the most widely used techniques for measuring norms were published, evidence began to accumulate that different people sometimes apply different norms to the same experimental situation (e.g. Yaari and Bar-Hillel (Reference Yaari and Bar-Hillel1984), and later Rueben and Riedl (Reference Reuben and Riedl2013) and Carpenter and Matthews (Reference Carpenter, Holmes and Matthews2008)). Thus, there is evidence of normative heterogeneity among anonymous participants interacting in the sparse, abstract contexts studied in the lab, even absent cues about identity.

Another working assumption in the literature is that norms are stable over time in the absence of interventions that alter peoples’ incentives or information about a given setting. Without panel data, it is impossible to test stability directly. Most research that addresses norms over time tests whether a change has been induced by an intervention rather than testing their temporal stability (see for example, Chang et al., Reference Chang, Chen and Krupka2019). Moreover, research on the robustness or stability of the results produced by norm-elicitation techniques has thus far largely focused on the robustness of the mean, e.g. asking whether the mean report is influenced by the perspective from which the task is described (1st, 2nd or 3rd person) (see e.g. Erkut et al., Reference Erkut, Nosenzo and Sefton2015). Alternatively, it has focused on whether the norm is robust to whether the elicitation is conducted with the same participants whose choices are observed or instead conducted with a separate sample drawn from the same participant pool (D’Adda et al., Reference d'Adda, Drouvelis and Nosenzo2016). Further, all of these studies employ adult populations while we are focusing on stability among a younger group who, there is some evidence to suggest, may be more sensitive to norms or for whom norms may be less stable than for adult populations (Blakemore & Mills, Reference Blakemore and Mills2014; Do et al., Reference Do, Prinstein and Telzer2020). In particular, there is evidence that peer effects play an especially important role in shaping the behavior of children (see e.g. List et al., Reference List, Petrie and Samek2023).

There is strong evidence to suggest that, on average, elicited norms for the dictator game do not differ much among adult (primarily WEIRD) populations (D’Adda et al., Reference d'Adda, Drouvelis and Nosenzo2016; Erkut et al., Reference Erkut, Nosenzo and Sefton2015; Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018), and they appear to be fairly well-established by the time children become adolescents. Sutter et al., (Reference Sutter, Zoller and Glätzle-Rützler2019) and List et al., (Reference List, Petrie and Samek2023) review economic behavior of children and adolescents and find that by the time children enter school (around age 6), rationality and social preferences for fairness are fairly stable.Footnote 7 In particular, they note that “…fairness concerns seem deep rooted and [are] early developed.” (Sutter et al., p. 113; Blake et al., Reference Blake, Piovesan, Montinari, Warneken and Gino2015; Fehr et al., Reference Fehr, Bernhard and Rockenbach2008). A smaller group of papers show that even children as young as 3–5 years old who understand the emotional consequences of moral violations (they feel bad and another person might feel bad) allocate stickers more generously in the dictator game. Maggian and Villeval (Reference Maggian and Villeval2016) show that the majority of adolescents (ages 7–14) who could lie for advantage, do not do so. Both of these studies suggest that the ability to understand and incorporate norms into decision making is present in the population we study. Evidence on peer effects noted above suggests that children regularly incorporate social information into their decisions, but, to our knowledge, there has been little work directly measuring normative beliefs among children. Our research thus contributes to this literature. Moreover, Grueneisen et al., (Reference Grueneisen, Wyman and Tomasello2015a, Reference Grueneisen, Wyman and Tomasello2015b) and Grueneisen et al., (Reference Grueneisen, Wyman and Tomasello2015b) show that from at least the age of 5 on, children can coordinate with peers by converging on a salient solution, and Brocas and Carillo (Reference Brocas and Carrillo2021) show that children become better at coordinating as they become adolescents. This suggests that adolescents are also likely to be capable of playing our coordination game, which we use to measure normative beliefs.

A final assumption undergirding models of norm-dependent decision-making is “preference stability”. In the tradition of Stigler and Becker (Reference Stigler and Becker1977), economists tend to treat preference parameters as exogenous. Norm-dependent utility is intended to explain context-dependent behavior by reference to context-dependent norms, which enter the utility of agents who care about following them to varying degrees. For example, agents are assumed to maximize norm-dependent utility v i x = u i x + ϕ i η ( x ) , where u i ( x ) is i's consumption utility at outcome x , η x [ - 1 , 1 ] is the normative appropriateness of outcome x according to the context-dependent norm, and ϕ i is the weight placed on norm-following by i. Kimbrough and Vostroknutov (Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018) introduced a method for eliciting a proxy for the parameter ϕ i , but to our knowledge, no one has assessed the test–retest reliability of this measure.

In sum, in the absence of intervention, the literature on norms makes assumptions that we call “norm uniqueness”, “norm stability”, and “preference stability”. To our knowledge, these assumptions have not been thoroughly tested, and so we set out to do so. Ultimately, we reject the first two hypotheses. We show that there is significant heterogeneity in perceptions of the norm that are not obvious when only looking at an aggregate norm measurement. We also show that perceptions of norms enjoy some stability over time, but that a major predictor of change in normative perception comes from dissimilarity to others in one’s network. Perhaps most importantly, we demonstrate how researchers might engage with this heterogeneity in normative perceptions by identifying classes of norm perceptions (e.g. a deontological equality norm or a consequentialist generosity norm) and asking how those classes can be used to deepen our understanding of norm emergence and norm change.

3 Methods

As part of the MECHANISMS study (Hunter et al., Reference Hunter2020), we collected repeated measures data on 1468 students aged 11–15 years old in 15 schools in and around Belfast, Northern Ireland and in Bogotá, Colombia. Participation was open to all students in a school-year group (approximately 100 students per school); uptake was approximately 90% at each location. These data provide us with two measures from each participant of a proxy for norm-following propensity and beliefs about injunctive norms in the dictator game, collected approximately 10 weeks apart.

These measures were not expected to change between waves as they were collected as controls alongside a broad set of other measures including norms related to smoking/vaping, self-reports of smoking behavior and intentions, social networks, and personality traits. These control measures served two purposes. First, since the dictator game is the most widely studied game in the social norms literature and yields remarkably consistent responses, on average, in norm-elicitation experiments, we had strong priors about what the elicited norm (hereafter DGN) would look like, on average.Footnote 8 Thus, deviations from this prior would serve as a sort of warning light to us regarding participants’ understanding of the norm elicitation procedure which was also being used to measure norms related to smoking. Second, and more important for the purposes of this paper, while we anticipated that the interventions would influence norms related to smoking–since they were designed to do so–we had no reason to expect the interventions to influence the DGN or in norm-following propensity since the interventions were not designed to influence either of these. Thus, our (null) hypotheses were that neither the DGN nor the norm-following propensity would change, on average over time.

In this paper, we focus only on the measures of dictator game norms, norm-following propensity, and social networks. Data about pre-treatment norms and behavior related to smoking and on the effects of our anti-smoking interventions are reported in Murray et al., (Reference Murray, Sanchez-Franco, Sarmiento, Kimbrough, Tate, Montgomery, Kumar, Dunne, Ramalingam, Krupka, Montes, Zhou, Moore, Bauld, Llorente, Kee and Hunter2021). All instruments were previously translated and adapted to Spanish. Data collection was conducted on individual tablet computers using Qualtrics. Instructions were read aloud by a monitor as participants followed along on screen. Screenshots of the interface and the instructions in English are reported in Appendix B. Participants received no feedback about their choices or the choices of others until the completion of the second survey wave. Participants were paid for either wave 1 or wave 2 for each task with equal probability. All payments were delivered, in cash in Northern Ireland and in a gift card in Bogotá, at the conclusion of the MECHANISMS study.

3.1 Dictator game norms

Following the protocol developed by Krupka and Weber (Reference Krupka and Weber2013) we measured participants’ normative expectations in the dictator game using an incentivized coordination game. Participants read the following vignette in Northern Ireland; these instructions were translated into Spanish and adjusted for purchasing power parity and instructions compressibility in Bogotá:

“Individual A and Individual B from the class are randomly paired with each other. Individual A received £10.00. Individual A will then have the opportunity to give any amount of his or her money to Individual B. For instance, Individual A may decide to give £0.00 to Individual B and keep £10.00 for him or herself. Or Individual A may decide to give £10.00 to Individual B and keep £0.00 for him or herself. Individual A may also choose to give any other amount between £0.00 and £10.00 to Individual B. This choice will determine how much money each will receive, privately and in cash, at the end of the experiment.”

Then, participants were provided with a list of 11 possible actions that a dictator could take (from keeping the entire endowment to giving the entire endowment to the recipient) and asked to report on a 6-point Likert scale whether each action was: ‘extremely socially inappropriate’, ‘very socially inappropriate’, ‘somewhat socially inappropriate’, ‘somewhat socially appropriate’, ‘very socially appropriate’, or ‘extremely socially appropriate’. This task was included in both the pre- and post-intervention survey.

Respondents were told that at the end of the study, we would randomly select one of their two surveys, and then choose one of the possible actions at random to determine their payment. They were told that if their normative evaluation of the chosen action matched the modal response of others in their school-year group, they would receive £10 (10.000 COP in Bogotá); otherwise, they would receive £0 for this task. This incentivizes participants to report shared beliefs about the appropriateness of each action, which is the definition of an injunctive social norm. As in Krupka and Weber (Reference Krupka and Weber2013), the idea is that the social norm is a focal point that resolves the coordination problem.

3.2 Norm-following propensity

Following the protocol developed by Kimbrough and Vostroknutov (Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018), we measured a proxy for norm-following propensity using a variant of the rule-following task (Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016) designed to be culturally portable. Participants are given 50 virtual balls and shown two virtual buckets, one yellow and one blue.

Participants are told that for each ball they drag into the yellow bucket, they will earn 10 pence (in Northern Ireland; 200 COP in Bogotá), and for each ball they drag into the blue bucket, they will earn 5 pence (in Northern Ireland; 100 COP in Bogotá). The instructions then state “The rule is to put the balls in the blue bucket.” However, there are no costs imposed for violating the experimenter-stated rule, and so following the rule only results in forgoing the opportunity to earn a higher payoff. Participants’ willingness to incur such costs has been shown to correlate with norm-consistent behavior in a variety of tasks that have been used to study social preferences (Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018; Ridinger, Reference Ridinger2018; Thomsson & Vostroknutov, Reference Thomsson and Vostroknutov2017). Participants are told that we will randomly choose either their first or second survey to be the one that counts for payment, and they receive an amount equal to the sum of the value of balls placed in the two buckets. They were also paid based on their decisions from two other incentivized tasks, and they earned an average of £15.52 (31,140 COP in Bogotá). To this we added a base participation payment of £5.00 (5,000 COP in Bogotá).

3.3 Peer networks

In addition to behavioral data, the study also conducted a survey to measure peer networks. These data allow us to assess whether peer effects can explain any observed changes in norms across the survey waves. Participants were asked to nominate up to 10 of their school-year-group peers as friends. We match the listed names to a master list of students in a participant’s year-group. We define the peer network as all those people who a participant nominated as a friend in the social network survey. For comparison, we also look at peer effects from (1) the people in the same classroom as a participant, and, because this was the relevant matching group for the coordination game, (2) the people in the same school-year group as a participant.

4 Results: aggregate analysis

The full study sample is described in detail in Murray et al., (Reference Murray, Sanchez-Franco, Sarmiento, Kimbrough, Tate, Montgomery, Kumar, Dunne, Ramalingam, Krupka, Montes, Zhou, Moore, Bauld, Llorente, Kee and Hunter2021). Table 1 presents summary statistics of some of the demographic characteristics of our sample. The study was conducted in multiple schools (7 in Northern Ireland and 8 in Bogotá), and each school was treated with either the ASSIST or Dead Cool anti-smoking intervention (8 received ASSIST and 7 received Dead Cool).Footnote 9 Each school consisted of a different number of classes (36 in Northern Ireland and 32 in Bogotá).

Table 1 Baseline mean sample characteristics for MECHANISMS schools

Northern Ireland (N = 7)

Bogotá (N = 8)

All schools (N = 15)

ASSIST (intervention)

4

4

8

Dead Cool (intervention)

3

4

7

No. of classes, N

36

32

68

No. of pupils, n

825

999

1824

Participation, n (%)

764 (92.6%)

892 (89.3%)

1656 (90.8%)

Boys

335 (47.8%)

436 (50.0%)

771 (49.0%)

Girls

355 (50.6%)

431 (49.4%)

786 (50.0%)

Prefer not to say

11 (1.6%)

5 (0.6%)

16 (1.0%)

Age, n (%)

11 years old

1 (0.1%)

26 (3.0%)

27 (1.7%)

12 years old

279 (39.8%)

320 (36.3%)

599 (37.8%)

13 years old

414 (59.1%)

313 (35.5%)

727 (45.9%)

14 years old

7 (1.0%)

146 (16.6%)

153 (9.7%)

15 or more years old

-

77 (8.7%)

77 (4.9%)

We have a very high participation rate in our studies due to recruitment of whole school year groups. In Northern Ireland the participation rate is 92.6% and in Bogotá it is 89.3%. We have a somewhat larger number of participants from Bogotá than from Northern Ireland (55 vs. 45% of our sample). In both locations, boys and girls each made up about 50% of all participants. Most participants are 12 or 13 years old.

In what follows, we combine data from both countries since prior empirical work done with adult populations offers no ex-ante reason to expect different dictator game norms or norm-following propensities in urban populations (e.g. Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018). Appendix A presents the same analysis for the two settings separately and shows that that are no economically meaningful differences. Figure 1 presents the distribution of the number of balls placed in the blue bucket (i.e., the extent to which people followed the rule) in the RF task in wave 1 and wave 2, which is our proxy for a subject’s norm-following propensity. The Figure shows that there are three main types of behavior when it comes to norm-following: (i) complete disregard for the rule captured by those who put no balls in the blue bucket, (ii) equal split captured by those who allocate half the balls to the blue bucket and half to the yellow bucket, and (iii) complete rule-following captured by those who allocate all 50 balls to the blue bucket. While there are participants who allocate other numbers of balls to the blue bucket in both waves, such allocations are rare and are never more than 5% of participants.

Fig. 1 Estimates of norm-following propensity

The distribution of RF task behavior appears relatively stable over the two waves. The percentage of those who completely disregarded the is 12% in wave 1 and 15% in wave 2. The percentage of participants with exactly equal splits is just over 14% in wave 1 and slightly under 13% in wave 2. There is a more pronounced increase in complete rule-following from wave 1 (~ 31%) to wave 2 (~ 36%). There is no discernible difference in the percent of participants allocating other numbers of balls to the blue bucket between the two waves.

Figure 2 shows the profile generated by the average appropriateness rating across all schools for each possible allocation to the recipient in the dictator game in the two waves. On the y-axis the average ratings range from -1 (extremely socially inappropriate) to 1 (extremely socially appropriate). The x-axis records the possible transfer amounts from the dictator to the recipient (ranging between giving nothing, 0, and transferring everything, 10).

Fig. 2 Dictator game norms, on average

Ratings in both waves show very similar patterns. We see that an equal split between the dictator and recipient was viewed as “very socially appropriate” on average, and that there is a sharp decline in the appropriateness ratings for any deviation (on either side) from the equal split. In both waves there is a more gradual decline in appropriateness with increasing distance from the equal split, and allocating 0 to the recipient is viewed as less appropriate than allocating 100% to the recipient. Overall, average norms are fairly stable over time. Except for the focal allocations of 0, 50 and 100% to the recipient, appropriateness ratings are slightly lower in wave 2 than in wave 1.

Table 2 presents summary statistics of the change in rule-following and the change in appropriateness ratings for all the possible dictator allocations between the two waves for all individuals who participated in both waves (N = 1,468). In addition, the Table presents results from Wilcoxon signed rank tests for zero difference between the two waves.Footnote 10

Table 2 Change in norm-following and norms

Measure

Mean

Standard error

Confidence interval

Norm-following

RF Task

-0.01

0.01

-0.01

0.03

Give 0

-0.00

0.02

-0.03

0.03

Give 1

-0.09***

0.02

-0.12

-0.06

Give 2

-0.10***

0.02

-0.13

-0.07

Give 3

-0.07***

0.02

-0.10

-0.04

Appropriateness ratings

Give 4

-0.07***

0.02

-0.11

-0.04

Give 5

-0.04

0.02

-0.07

0.00

Give 6

-0.03

0.02

-0.07

0.00

Give 7

-0.06**

0.02

-0.09

-0.02

Give 8

-0.03

0.02

-0.07

0.00

Give 9

-0.05

0.02

-0.08

-0.01

Give 10

-0.03

0.02

-0.08

0.01

*** p < 0.01, ** p < 0.05, * p < 0.10, Wilcoxon signed-rank tests with Holm-Bonferroni correction to account for multiple comparisons. N = 1468

The tests in Table 2 confirm earlier impressions from Figs. 1 and 2. The average change in rule-following (proportion of balls in the blue bucket) is small (0.01), and this is not statistically significant. Allocations giving small amounts to the recipient (£1—£4) were rated as significantly less appropriate in wave 2 than in wave 1. However, allocations higher than 50% are not rated significantly differently between waves, with the exception of allocating £7 (at the 5% level). However, an allocation of £7 is seen as less appropriate in wave 2.

Importantly, the evaluations of the most salient actions (give 0 and give 5) do not change significantly on average. For the evaluations that do change, the maximum average change is approximately -0.1, which is equivalent to ¼ of the change that would occur if participants all changed their evaluation by a single category (e.g. from “somewhat socially inappropriate” to “very socially inappropriate”). Compare this to Chang et al., (Reference Chang, Chen and Krupka2019) Tables A.1 and A.4, in which an experimental treatment causes normative evaluations of dictator game decisions to change by approximately 0.5 (5 × as much) in a between-participant design. Thus, though the within-participant differences are statistically significant, they are not large on average, and the overall visual profile of the average normative beliefs remains quite consistent.

Table 2 suggests that average changes are small overall. This could result from small changes at the individual level, or from individual changes in opposite directions that cancel each other out. To investigate this issue, Fig. 3 plots the distributions of all individual changes in norm-following (top row, first panel) and changes in appropriateness ratings of each potential dictator allocation.

Fig. 3 Histograms of individual-level changes in norms and norm-following

In the top left panel of Fig. 3, we see that a material proportion of participants (> 40%) do not change their behavior in the rule-following task. No more than 10% of the participants change their choices completely between waves (e.g. moving from fully rule-following to fully rule-breaking or vice versa). Moreover, the magnitudes of changes are small on average.

The remaining panels depict histograms of the appropriateness ratings for each action (e.g. “give 0”). Visually, we find little evidence of substantial changes in ratings from wave 1 to wave 2 for transfers of 0, £5 or £10. In particular, more than 50%, 45% and 40% of participants respectively do not change their ratings between waves. For all other allocation levels, the modal change between waves is still zero. Even when there are changes by participants, these changes are small. In all eleven possible dictator allocations, more than 70% of participants either do not change their rating or the change is a single appropriateness category.

These findings suggest that both norm-following and norms on dictator allocations are, on average, relatively stable over the 10-week period in our study. However, some of the changes in normative beliefs are statistically significant, and we do note that there are changes at the individual level. The rest of the paper explores the sources of this individual heterogeneity and asks to what extent it reflects the existence of multiple contemporaneous norms and of ongoing normative change.

4.1 Results: evidence of multiple norms

While the between-participant average normative valences across the eleven possible actions in the dictator game generate the singular, familiar pattern shown in Fig. 2, the averages conceal substantial heterogeneity in the patterns of responses given by individual participants. So far, in analyzing whether norms change, we’ve tested for significant changes in the normative valence of each action independently of the other actions (e.g. Table 2), but in doing so, we are implicitly treating variation at the individual level as measurement error in our estimate of the norm. However, individual heterogeneity may stem from the fact that individuals actually have different beliefs about what the norm is in the situation. Thus, what matters for understanding the impact of norms on behavior in a heterogeneous population is characterizing heterogeneity in beliefs about the norm.

Latent transition analysis (LTA) is a mixture modeling approachFootnote 11 that extends latent class analysis (LCA) to include panel data. LCA identifies unobservable (latent) subgroups (aka classes) from observed response patterns. This approach expresses a multivariate distribution as a composite of a finite number of component distributions, each representing a latent class. LTA is an extension of LCA and uses longitudinal data to identify the degree of movement between the classes over time.

For this reason, LTA is well-suited to uncover the extent and nature of heterogeneity in the norms that participants bring with them and to subsequently test for their stability over time. We thus conduct a series of LTAs, in which we model profiles of normative responses as a function of latent class variables, where each class represents a different norm. Specifically, we identify latent class membership in each wave from the 11 normative valences reported for the dictator game (the ratings of each action from “Give 0” to “Give 10” on our 6-points Likert scale).

Our model restricts the set of classes to be constant across the two time periods and identifies the set of classes that best fit the data, including random intercepts for each participant to control for time-invariant unobservable characteristics (Muthén & Asparouhov, Reference Muthén and Asparouhov2022). The key assumptions of the model are conditional independence, i.e. that after controlling for random effects and class membership, the reported normative valences are independent, and measurement invariance, i.e. that the set of latent classes are the same at both time periods (Nylund-Gibson et al., Reference Nylund-Gibson, Garber, Carter, Chan, Arch, Simon, Whaling, Tartt and Lawrie2022).Footnote 12

Under the model, each latent class can be summarized via an implied probability distribution over the possible responses in the Krupka-Weber norm elicitation task for each of the eleven actions. Comparing model fit statistics (e.g. AIC, BIC), we determined that the best fitting model includes 5 latent classes, which we describe in detail below before examining individual transitions between them.

One important consideration in latent class modelling is the need to distinguish heterogeneity from noise. AIC, BIC, and Adjusted BIC penalize the addition of parameters to the model and trade that off against the improvement in fit. Thus, the convention in LCA and LTA models is to choose the number of classes that minimizes AIC, BIC, and adjusted BIC. In our case all three statistics favor the 5-class model. When they give conflicting results, the convention is to favor the model with fewer classes. As a robustness check, we also estimated LCA models using the wave 1 and wave 2 data separately. As in the LTA estimates, both AIC and BIC favor a 5-class model. Moreover, the norm profiles estimated from both wave 1 and wave 2 show a striking visual resemblance to one another and to the profiles estimated in the 5-class LTA model.

Figure 4 shows both the average responses of subjects who were classified into each class and the implied pattern of responses to the Krupka-Weber elicitation task for each estimated latent class, constructed by computing the expected value of the normative valence of each action, with panel (f) showing the average of the five classes. Each class represents a different injunctive norm, and thus the model reveals substantial heterogeneity in normative beliefs, even in a setting as simple as the dictator game. Under a norm-dependent utility model in which people trade off consumption utility and adherence to injunctive norms (see e.g. Kessler & Leider, Reference Kessler and Leider2012; Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013; Kimbrough & Vostroknutov, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016), each distinct norm will result in a different distribution of choices, depending on the norm that the decision-maker follows.

Fig. 4 Estimated classes of norms from the latent transition analysis, and mean responses for individuals assigned to each class (± 2SEs). Note: The LTA model returns, for each class and each possible dictator action, the estimated probabilities of choosing each normative evaluation (i.e. 6 probabilities that sum to 1). Each grey dashed line plots the mean of those 6 probabilities for each dictator action, in a given class. Intuitively, the grey line captures the expected norm profile for someone in that class. Each solid black line shows the mean reported normative evaluation by subjects assigned to that class in either wave + / − 2 standard errors of the mean. Intuitively, overlap between grey and black shows how well the LTA model classifies the subjects. The solid grey reference line indicates where responses change from approval to disapproval. The title of each panel indicates how many subjects were assigned to that class in each wave

Moreover, the pattern of responses implied by each latent class has an intuitive interpretation that coheres with widely-known ethical theories and with the kinds of normative interpretation that have been offered in the dictator game (c.f. Yaari & Bar-Hillel, Reference Yaari and Bar-Hillel1984 for early examples of these intuitive classes). The best fitting model includes five latent classes corresponding to five sets of normative beliefs that can be interpreted in terms of what respondents view as “appropriate” (e.g. equality vs. generosity) and how they view deviations (e.g. deontological vs. consequentialist). We attempt to characterize the nature of the norm implied by each class in turn:

Class 1: Strongly egalitarian, consequentialist. Normative evaluations span the entire range from “extremely inappropriate” when keeping the whole endowment or giving the whole endowment away, to “extremely appropriate” when splitting the endowment equally. This norm strongly favors the equal split, but in keeping with consequentialist ethics, deviations from the normatively best outcome are evaluated according to the magnitude of the deviation. Under norm-dependent utility, such a norm would imply choices that become gradually more self-interested as the intrinsic propensity to follow norms decreases.

Class 2: Egalitarian, deontological. Like the norm implied by Class 1, this norm strongly favors the egalitarian outcome; however, the appropriateness ratings of all ten inegalitarian outcomes are low and virtually indistinguishable from one another. This suggests a deontological view of dictator game decisions, with any deviation from the normatively best outcome seen as equivalently wrong. Such a norm would imply a bimodal distribution of dictator decisions, with participants either giving half or keeping the whole endowment for themselves, with indifference defined by a threshold value of the norm following propensity.

Class 3: Egalitarian, consequentialist. This norm has a similar shape to Class 1, but views deviations from the egalitarian ideal as somewhat less problematic overall, while still respecting the consequentialist principle that larger deviations are increasingly unacceptable. Such a norm would again imply a distribution of choices ranging from self-interested to egalitarian depending on the propensity to follow norms, but for a given distribution of norm-following propensities, choices would be skewed toward self-interest, compared to choices under the norm in Class 1.

Class 4: Weakly egoistic. Class 4 reveals a pattern of normative evaluations consistent with egoism, since nearly every allocation (except for keeping the whole pie and giving away the whole pie) is rated as at least somewhat appropriate. The implied distribution of choices is similar to that in Class 3, but further skewed towards self-interest.

Class 5: Generous, consequentialist. Class 5 reveals a qualitatively different kind of norm, in which appropriateness is essentially monotonically increasing in the amount given to the recipient. This is consistent with a norm of generosity which respects the consequentialist principle that larger deviations from the ideal are worse. Since appropriateness increases much more rapidly for allocations to the left of the egalitarian outcome than for those to the right, the implied distribution of choices in the dictator game for this norm is quite similar to those for Class 1. Only those with the most extreme norm-following propensities would choose to give more than the egalitarian amount, and so choices in the dictator game would not be likely to reveal the existence of this fundamental difference in normative beliefs.

The existence of such heterogeneity raises questions about how to interpret observed choices in the dictator game. Evidence that “context matters” has already shown that, in general, it is not possible to interpret choices in a dictator game as directly revealing stable social preferences defined over payoff distributions. Models of norm-dependent preferences were designed to address this by showing how dictator games might be used to infer the existence and nature of a shared injunctive norm commonly known to be applicable to a given interaction. The simultaneous existence of multiple normative perspectives on the same interaction further complicates this picture. If each participant’s choices depend on their own normative beliefs and those beliefs vary in the population, then observations of choices from a single dictator game become even more difficult to interpret. In fact, over the range of choices between keeping the whole endowment and the egalitarian allocation, even sharply diverging normative perspectives (e.g. egalitarianism vs. generosity) will generally not be revealed in choices.

This interpretive complexity will be further compounded if the distribution of normative beliefs varies across samples. While cross-country heterogeneity is not the focus of this paper (we only have 2 countries to compare), it is worth highlighting that, despite the similarity of average normative beliefs in Northern Ireland and Bogotá in our sample, we do see some differences in the relative frequency of the five injunctive norms captured by the latent classes. Figure 5 shows the percentage of subjects whose best-fitting latent class corresponds to each of the five injunctive norms, by location and wave. The data reveal that our Northern Irish subjects are more likely to be classified as Strongly Egalitarian Consequentialists or Generosity Consequentialists than are our subjects from Bogotá. Moreover, our subjects from Bogotá are more likely to be classified as Deontological Egalitarians, Weakly Egalitarian Consequentialists or Egoists. That the averages conceal this difference is perhaps coincidental, but the key implication is that the “same game” need not have the same interpretation in two distinct socio-cultural settings, and thus a focus on averages may ignore important and informative differences.

Fig. 5 Histogram of best-fitting latent class assignments, by location (Waves 1 and 2)

4.2 Results: evidence of transitions between classes of norms

Having identified 5 classes representing distinct injunctive norms, we now evaluate the stability of individual class assignment over time. The LTA also estimates a transition matrix giving the probability of transitioning between classes across the waves. Table 3a shows the transition probabilities between classes, and Table 3b shows the frequency distribution of types across both waves of the experiment. The strongly egalitarian consequentialist (class 1) and generosity consequentialist (class 5) types exhibit the most stability, with more than half of those classified as those types at T = 1 remaining in the same class at T = 2. No class stands out particularly strongly as an attractor for those who change their classes, though it seems there is a slight tendency for people to transition toward class 3 (and to a slightly lesser extent class 1).

Table 3 Transition probabilities and frequency distribution of types (T1 and T2)

T1

T2

T1

T2

Class1

Class2

Class3

Class4

Class5

Class1

Class2

Class3

Class4

Class5

(a) Transition probabilities

(b) Class counts

Class1

0.59

0.11

0.14

0.05

0.11

Class1

217

37

50

17

39

Class2

0.18

0.42

0.20

0.14

0.06

Class2

37

92

44

29

13

Class3

0.21

0.17

0.38

0.14

0.10

Class3

52

47

105

39

28

Class4

0.14

0.13

0.26

0.38

0.09

Class4

48

46

89

129

32

Class5

0.22

0.09

0.12

0.05

0.52

Class5

61

25

32

15

145

To better understand who changes their norms and why, we test whether holding similar normative views to one’s peers at T1 reduces the likelihood of changing one’s normative views by T2 via a linear probability model. Socialization in the time between T1 and T2 may inform subjects that their beliefs differ from their peers’. Thus, we might expect those with distinctive beliefs to change because of the incentives provided by the coordination game. The dependent variable is a dummy variable that takes a value of 1 if a participant’s best fitting latent class changed between T1 and T2 and 0 otherwise. The independent variable of interest is the percent of one’s peers that were in the same latent class as a given participant in T1. As noted above, we define the peer network in three different ways: (1) as the people who a participant nominated as a friend in our social network survey (participants could nominate up to 10 friends in their school year group), (2) as the people in the same classroom as a participant, and (3) as the people in the same school year group as a participant (which is the matching group for the coordination game). The results are reported in Table 4.

Table 4 Estimated peer effects on norm stability (i.e. probability of changing latent class assignment), by location

Friend

Classroom

School

% in Same latent class at T1

− 0.20***

− 0.45***

− 0.50***

− 1.00***

− 0.64***

− 1.45***

(0.07)

(0.10)

(0.11)

(0.13)

(0.14)

(0.19)

Bogotá

− 0.08*

− 0.26***

− 0.36***

(0.05)

(0.06)

(0.07)

Bogotá x % in same latent class at T1

0.46***

1.17***

1.60***

(0.14)

(0.21)

(0.27)

Constant

0.59***

0.63***

0.66***

0.78***

0.69***

0.88***

[Pr(Change class) | % same = 0)]

(0.02)

(0.04)

(0.03)

(0.04)

(0.04)

(0.05)

N

1115

1121

1121

Wald test p value (Bogotá peer effect > 0)

0.88

0.30

0.46

On average, those who initially hold normative beliefs that are more similar to their peers are less likely to change their normative beliefs over time, while those who are initially more dissimilar to their peers are more likely to change their beliefs. Note that initial similarity to larger peer groups such as the classroom or the school-year-group shows larger effects than similarity to the self-nominated friend group, despite the fact that the average share of peers who are in the same latent class at T1 is about the same, on average, for each definition of peer group (approx. ¼). This may be explained by the fact that the coordination game was played with the entire school-year-group.

In our setting we should expect to see coordination rates increase over time (due to incentives and socialization over the panel). The transition matrix, along with the regressions in Table 4, provide evidence that speaks to this hypothesis. We find that if a subject is different from their peers, they are more likely to change their beliefs (captured as a change in latent class assignment). Furthermore, similarity to the school-year-group has a larger effect on the likelihood to change beliefs than similarity to the other peer groups, which suggests that respondents are attentive to the incentives (see Table 4). However, the degree of coordination at wave 2 is not substantially higher than that at wave 1. In Northern Ireland, the raw rate at which subjects select the modal normative evaluation over all 11 actions is 0.43 at T1 and 0.44 at T2. In Colombia, the coordination rate is 0.38 at T1 and 0.35 at T2. Thus, we find that subjects change beliefs when dissimilar to their peers, but do not change them in a way that leads them to converge towards a single latent class in each school-year-group. Ultimately, we can predict to some extent who changes, but not how they change.

Table 4 also included specifications with a Bogotá dummy variable and an interaction, to assess whether peer effects vary across contexts. Strikingly, observed increases in consistency over time are almost entirely driven by the Northern Irish sample. Evaluated at the mean observed “% in the same latent class at T1”, we cannot reject the null hypothesis of zero peer effects in Bogotá for any peer group (Wald test that the sum of the coefficients equals zero, p values > 0.3), but we can sharply reject the null in Northern Ireland (p values < 0.001).

We are reluctant to speculate about the source of these differences. Since we observe norms in only two locations that differ along many socio-cultural dimensions, it is virtually impossible to apportion causality across those dimensions. That said, we note that our samples are drawn from two countries that have been shown to differ substantially on some major social-psychological dimensions. For example, South American countries tend to have relatively more “loose” attitudes toward norms (have weak social norms and a high tolerance of conflicting behavior) compared to Western European countries that tend to be “tight” (have many strong norms and a low tolerance of conflicting behavior) (Gelfand et al., Reference Gelfand, Raver, Nishii, Leslie, Lun, Lim, Duan, Almaliach, Ang, Arnadottir and Aycan2011). These observations are consistent with the fact that a slightly higher percentage of subjects in Bogotá were reclassified across waves (55 vs 51%) and the fact that evidence of peer effects on norm change appears to be stronger in Northern Ireland than in Bogotá. Finally, we note that an institutional peculiarity of the Bogotá schools may also have played a role in this finding: the school day is divided into two 4-h blocks due to capacity constraints. One set of students attends in the morning, and another set attends in the afternoon. This probably leads to less interaction between members of the same school-year-group in Bogotá than in Northern Ireland.

5 Conclusion

In light of growing evidence that social behavior can be profitably modeled in terms of individual tradeoffs between own consumption utility and normative goals, economists have turned to norm elicitation protocols, such as the coordination game developed by Krupka and Weber (Reference Krupka and Weber2013), to measure norms because choice data alone is not sufficient for this task. Models of norm-driven behavior tend to assume that norm-motivated agents are influenced by a single, stable, commonly known injunctive norm in each setting. Thus, little work has focused on studying the variation in normative beliefs, on what that variation means, nor on how such variation may be used to tell us about norms or their change over time and across contexts. We show that these basic assumptions about “the” norm do not hold, in the workhorse dictator game. We show how to exploit variation in normative beliefs to extend our understanding of norms in dictator games across two cultural settings and over time. We also show how researchers might use evidence of heterogeneous and changing normative beliefs to study the factors contributing to such changes.

In particular, we use peer networks to predict normative belief change. Previous research has shown that peer networks can be exploited in network interventions (i.e. intervention approaches that purposefully utilize network data within the intervention design). Findings from empirical and simulation-based studies suggest that such approaches could generate behavior change, yet there is little work to date on how to use these data within network interventions to change normative beliefs (Badham et al., Reference Badham, Kee and Hunter2018, Reference Badham, Kee and Hunter2019, Reference Badham, Kee and Hunter2021; Hunter et al., Reference Hunter, de la Haye, Murray, Badham, Valente, Clarke and Kee2019; Valente, Reference Valente2012). To do so, we use a panel data set on normative beliefs about dictator game giving and a proxy for norm-following propensity from a sample of 1468 participants from two different settings roughly 10 weeks apart.

We first show that a proxy measure capturing norm-following propensity is stable, on average, at the individual level over the sample period. This is consistent with a common assumption in models of norm-dependent utility models that treats norm-following propensity as a fixed, individual-level characteristic. Tate et al., (Reference Tate, Kumar, Murray, Sanchez-Franco, Sarmiento, Montgomery, Zhou, Ramalingam, Krupka, Kimbrough, Kee and Hunter2022) present a detailed analysis of associations between demographic, personality and cognitive traits and RF task behavior in this sample and find very little evidence that such associations are present among adolescents. A comprehensive multivariate model showed a significant association only with gender, with women putting more balls into the blue bucket than men. This reiterates a finding from Kimbrough and Vostroknutov (Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016) who similarly identified gender as the only significant predictor of RF task behavior in their sample of 600 college students. Their evidence suggests that this proxy for norm-following propensity captures a distinctive aspect of decision-making, and our evidence complements this by showing that it reflects a relatively persistent individual-level characteristic.

Moreover, we find that, in aggregate, norm profiles constructed from the average normative beliefs for the dictator game are remarkably similar across our two settings and that our targeted age group of respondents, 12 and 13 years old, hold similar normative views, on average, to those documented elsewhere among college age students. However, we also see that a focus on the sample average conceals considerable heterogeneity. To document this heterogeneity, we use latent transition analyses to decompose the aggregate normative belief into latent classes of normative beliefs and to test for, and predict, change in norms over our waves. There are many prior studies showing that differences in behavior across contexts are associated with differences in perceived norms (e.g. Krupka & Weber, Reference Krupka and Weber2013). Our study suggests that differences in behavior within a given context could also be attributable to differences in perceived norms across people within that context.

Our analyses revealed 5 distinct classes representing different norms of dictator giving, each plausibly interpretable as reflecting a well-known ethical perspective. We also find that Northern Ireland and Colombia samples differ, to some extent, in the relative frequency of these 5 classes. The results further show that people transition to different classes from wave 1 to wave 2, and the dissimilarity of peers’ norms to one’s own norms is a significant predictor of the change in norms. So, people who hold similar normative views to their peers are less likely to change their normative views, suggesting that subjects respond to the incentives to coordinate. This effect is only observed in Northern Ireland, which we argue may reflect different patterns of interaction between school-year-group peers across contexts.

We advance research on norms by unpacking the working assumption that there is a single norm profile representing the injunctive norm in a given choice context. Normative beliefs regarding the actions one could take are dependent on each other and make the elicitation of an entire profile of normative beliefs imperative. This insight, in turn, can be combined with latent transition analysis to identify latent heterogeneity in beliefs. These analyses, in turn, suggest that observed heterogeneity is not measurement error but rather breaks down into meaningful classes of beliefs: Strongly egalitarian consequentialist, egalitarian deontological, egalitarian consequentialist, weakly egoistic, and generous consequentialist. We then use the output of our LTA model to characterize and predict normative belief change.

In short, what we know about norms and what we can test about them is dramatically expanded with these advances. With the modification to our theoretic framework that normative evaluations need to be treated as a profile, and with advances in how we treat variation, we will have much more to say about when a norm is shared in a population, whether it is strong or weak, how and at what moment norm change (at the individual and aggregate level) has taken place.

Our results also have further methodological consequences that need to be worked out. While latent variable models allow us to extract heterogeneous classes of normative beliefs from our data ex post, current elicitation techniques are not optimized to reveal such heterogeneity. For one thing, the presence of incentives to coordinate in the Krupka and Weber norm-elicitation protocol means that subjects will tend to report heterogeneous normative beliefs primarily when there is genuine normative uncertainty or unawareness about the most common injunctive norm. Even subjects who recognize that there may be “reasonable disagreement” about whether, say, a generosity norm or an equality norm is most fitting in a given context are forced to report only one norm and face incentives that encourage them to choose the one they believe is shared by the largest proportion of other subjects. This could imply that the heterogeneity we identify is an underestimate of the true heterogeneity. Future work should seek to develop methods that incentive-compatibly elicit beliefs about how many different norms there are, what they look like, and what percent of the population favors each one.

Finally, our findings have relevance not only to our theoretical understandings of norms but also to the practical application of how best to design norms-based policy interventions. Recognition of the importance of individual heterogeneity for the efficacy of such interventions is growing. For example, theorists from network science are now also updating their models to embrace heterogeneities in susceptibility to social influence (Cialdini & Goldstein, Reference Cialdini and Goldstein2004), and there is growing evidence for the moderating effects of individual traits like self-efficacy, self-identity and perceived benefits (of behavior change) on the impact of norms-based interventions (e.g. Chung & Rimal, Reference Chung and Rimal2016; Murakami et al., Reference Murakami, Shimada, Ushifusa and Ida2022; Probst et al., Reference Probst, Vu, Epstein, Nielsen, Buckley, Brennan, Rehm and Purshouse2020; Rimal et al., Reference Rimal, Lapinski, Cook and Real2005; Yun & Silk, Reference Yun and Silk2011). However, there is substantially less work on the interaction between policy interventions and heterogeneous pre-existing norms (for one example, see Pe’er et al., Reference Pe’erFeldmanGamlielSaharTikotskyHodSchupak2019). We suggest this is an important topic for future research.

Supplementary Information

The online version contains supplementary material available at https://doi.org/10.1007/s10683-024-09821-5.

Acknowledgements

The authors wish to thank the teachers and pupils for their participation in the study and William Wang for research assistance. We thank participants at RExCon International Conference on Social Norms and Social Preferences 2021, the MECHANISMs Study Concluding Conference 2021 and the Economic Science Association North American Meetings 2021 for useful comments. We also wish to acknowledge the support from our partners Cancer Focus Northern Ireland and Evidence to Impact.

Funding

Open access funding provided by SCELC, Statewide California Electronic Library Consortium. This study was funded by a grant from the Medical Research Council Population and Systems Medicine Board (reference number MR/R011176/1).

Data availability

The datasets generated during and/or analyzed during the current study are not publicly available as participants were informed that no-one outside of the research team would have access to the research data when they signed their consent forms. Scripts used to generate our results are available at: https://doi.org/10.7302/w77t-za90. For further information about the study datasets, please contact the authors (Emails: Jennifer.Murray@qub.ac.uk; ruth.hunter@qub.ac.uk).

Declarations

Ethical approval

The study was conducted with the approval of the IRB of Queen’s University Belfast.

Footnotes

1 Economists have studied norms to explain why people are willing to punish others for not cooperating in public goods provision (Fehr and Gaechter Reference Fehr and Gächter2000), why some communities are able to solve commons problems while others are not (Hardin Reference Hardin1982; Ostrom Reference Ostrom2000), why firms adopt particular price setting behaviors (Kahneman et al., Reference Kahneman, Knetsch and Thaler1986) or do not cut wages during periods of high unemployment (Akerlof Reference Akerlof1980; Bewley Reference Bewley1998), why countries adopt different redistribution policies (Alesina and Angeletos Reference Alesina and Angeletos2005; Lindbeck et al., Reference Lindbeck, Nyberg and Weibull1999), or why teenagers may engage in risky behaviors (Haines and Spear Reference Haines and Spear1996).

2 Injunctive norms, which are shared beliefs about what one ought to do, are distinguished from descriptive norms, which refer to actual patterns of behavior (Cialdini and Trost Reference Cialdini, Trost, Gilbert, Fiske and Lindzey1998).

3 It is important to distinguish between the theoretical claim that people have a propensity to follow norms and the existing techniques for eliciting this propensity; see Kimbrough and Vostroknutov (Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2016, Reference Kimbrough and Vostroknutov2018) for a discussion of the relation between this task and the underlying theoretical construct.

4 This was a large public health intervention intended to understand the mechanisms of behavioral change with regards to smoking/vaping behavior among middle-schoolers in two different contexts (Hunter et al., Reference Hunter2020). As List et al. (Reference List, Petrie and Samek2023) note, it is not uncommon for studies of policy or behavioral interventions among children to also include evidence regarding the impact of the intervention on non-targeted outcomes, as we do here.

5 We measure peer networks in 3 ways: similarity to self-nominated friends, to classroom peers, and to peers in the whole school year group.

6 In several papers the key assumptions of this protocol—that collectively-recognized social norms create focal points in the matching game – is tested. Burks and Krupka (Reference Burks and Krupka2012) compare elicited norms with ex-ante identified actual norms and find that the norms elicited using the coordination task track the ex-ante identified norms reliably, while norms elicited without the coordination task and without the matching incentive do not reliably do so. Pushing further on this assumption, Krupka et al. (Reference Krupka, Leider and Jiang2017) pair the Krupka and Weber norm-elicitation protocol with (1) an incentivized elicitation of participants’ beliefs about the distribution of actions actually taken by other participants (i.e. they ask raters about their “empirical expectations” as well as their beliefs about the social norm) and (2) a hypothetical question about what they themselves would do in the situation for which they are guessing about the norm. They find that participants’ beliefs about the norm, as measured using the Krupka and Weber norm elicitation protocol, are not primarily driven by their beliefs about others’ likely actions in the games (their empirical expectations), beliefs about what they personally would do in the same situation, nor do the norms ratings substantially differ by a limited set of measured participant characteristics. Fallucchi and Nosenzo (Reference Fallucchi and Nosenzo2021) test the vulnerability of the Krupka–Weber method to the presence of alternative salient focal points in two series of experiments with more than 3000 subjects. They find that the method is robust, especially when there are clear normative expectations about what constitutes appropriate behavior.

7 The study of adolescents is important in its own right. Though not the focus of our paper, this subject pool contributes to an important and growing literature studying economic preferences among children. These studies can reveal whether economic behavior develops in patterns over the course of life and it informs theory that seeks to model adolescent choice (eg. such as the decision to take up smoking, which has long term consequences). See Sutter et al. (Reference Sutter, Zoller and Glätzle-Rützler2019)for a comprehensive review on this topic.

8 While norms for the standard dictator game have turned out to be robust to elicitation with different (primarily WEIRD) populations, we know of little work that elicits them among children in two settings that vary on a number of dimensions. For example, the greater metro area of Bogotá has ± 11 million inhabitants and is the capital city of a upper-middle income country where 31% of the population are under 18 years old. Meanwhile, the entire population of Northern Ireland is about 1.8 million and though it is relatively poor by UK standards, it is well-off by global standards and has only 22% of the population under 18.

9 The ASSIST intervention trains influential peers to deliver anti-smoking information; the Dead Cool intervention employs a more traditional classroom-based pedagogy to teach participants about the influences and risks of smoking.

10 Table A1 in Appendix A presents summary statistics of rule-following and appropriateness ratings in each of the two waves in Northern Ireland and in Bogotá.

11 Mixture modelling approaches are common with behavioral data; see e.g. Conlisk (Reference Conlisk1989), Harless and Camerer (Reference Harless and Camerer1994), Harrison and Rutstrom (Reference Harrison and Rutström2009), and Kranton and Sanders (Reference Kranton and Sanders2017).

12 While R and other software packages have native LTA capabilities, they do not have packages that run the Random Intercepts-LTA model that we employ. This implementation exists in the proprietary MPlus software. There are packages in R that allow a user to run MPlus scripts and analyze MPlus output (so long as the user has a copy of MPlus). We have produced a folder containing a script to run our “Random Intercepts-LTA” scripts and produce figures and tables summarizing the revealed latent classes and transition matrices. This folder is available here: https://www.dropbox.com/sh/9dzpi3m0nvuvqy7/AADcmtMMjCxOkvklcCyTdNVka?dl=0

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

References

Akerlof, G. A. (1980). A theory of social custom, of which unemployment may be one consequence. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 94(4), 749775. 10.2307/1885667CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Akerlof, G. A., & Kranton, R. E. (2000). Economics and identity. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 115(3), 715753. 10.1162/003355300554881CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Akerlof, G. A., & Kranton, R. E. (2005). Identity and the economics of organizations. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19(1), 932. 10.1257/0895330053147930CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alesina, A., & Angeletos, G. M. (2005). Fairness and redistribution. American Economic Review, 95(4), 960980. 10.1257/0002828054825655CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andreoni, J., & Bernheim, B. D. (2009). Social image and the 50–50 norm: A theoretical and experimental analysis of audience effects. Econometrica, 77(5), 16071636. 10.3982/ECTA7384Google Scholar
Badham, J., Kee, F., & Hunter, R. F. (2018). Simulating network intervention strategies: Implications for adoption of behaviour. Network Science, 6(2), 265280. 10.1017/nws.2018.4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Badham, J., Kee, F., & Hunter, R. F. (2019). Effectiveness variation in simulated school-based network interventions. Applied Network Science, 4(1), 114. 10.1007/s41109-019-0168-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Badham, J., Kee, F., & Hunter, R. F. (2021). Network structure influence on simulated network interventions for behaviour change. Social Networks, 64, 5562. 10.1016/j.socnet.2020.08.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bewley, T. F. (1998). Why not cut pay?. European Economic Review, 42(3–5), 459490. 10.1016/S0014-2921(98)00002-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bicchieri, C. (2006). The grammar of society: The nature and dynamics of social norms. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Binmore, K., & Samuelson, L. (2006). The evolution of focal points. Games and Economic Behavior, 55(1), 2142. 10.1016/j.geb.2005.03.005CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blake, P. R., Piovesan, M., Montinari, N., Warneken, F., & Gino, F. (2015). Prosocial norms in the classroom: The role of self-regulation in following norms of giving. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 115, 1829. 10.1016/j.jebo.2014.10.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blakemore, S-J, & Mills, K. L. (2014). Is adolescence a sensitive period for sociocultural processing?. Annual Review of Psychology, 65, 187207. 10.1146/annurev-psych-010213-115202CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Brocas, I., & Carrillo, J. D. (2021). Dynamic coordination in efficient and fair strategies: a developmental perspective. SSRN Working Paper.Google Scholar
Burks, S. V., & Krupka, E. L. (2012). A multimethod approach to identifying norms and normative expectations within a corporate hierarchy: Evidence from the financial services industry. Management Science, 58(1), 203217. 10.1287/mnsc.1110.1478CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cappelen, A. W., Hole, A. D., Sørensen, , & Tungodden, B. (2007). The pluralism of fairness ideals: An experimental approach. American Economic Review, 97(3), 818827. 10.1257/aer.97.3.818CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carpenter, J., Holmes, J., & Matthews, P. H. (2008). Charity auctions: A field experiment. The Economic Journal, 118(525), 92113. 10.1111/j.1468-0297.2007.02105.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chang, D., Chen, R., & Krupka, E. (2019). Rhetoric matters: A social norms explanation for the anomaly of framing. Games and Economic Behavior, 116, 158178. 10.1016/j.geb.2019.04.011CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chung, A., & Rimal, R. N. (2016). Social norms: A review. Review of Communication Research, 4, 128. 10.12840/issn.2255-4165.2016.04.01.008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cialdini, R., & Trost, M. (1998) Social Influence: Social Norms, Conformity, and Compliance. In: Gilbert, D., Fiske, S., Lindzey, G. (eds) The Handbook of Social Psychology, 4th edition. Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
Cialdini, R. B., & Goldstein, N. J. (2004). Social influence: Compliance and conformity. Annual Review of Psychology., 55, 591621. 10.1146/annurev.psych.55.090902.142015CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Conlisk, J. (1989). Three variants on the Allais example. The American Economic Review, 79, 392407.Google Scholar
d'Adda, G., Drouvelis, M., & Nosenzo, D. (2016). Norm elicitation in within-subject designs: Testing for order effects. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 62, 17. 10.1016/j.socec.2016.02.003CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Do, K. T., Prinstein, M. J., & Telzer, E. H. (2020). Neurobiological susceptibility to peer influence in adolescence, in Kadosh, K. C. (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Developmental Cognitive Neuroscience (in press).Google Scholar
Erkut, H., Nosenzo, D., & Sefton, M. (2015). Identifying social norms using coordination games: Spectators vs. stakeholders. Economics Letters, 130, 2831. 10.1016/j.econlet.2015.02.021CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fallucchi, F., & Nosenzo, D. (2021). The coordinating power of social norms. Experimental Economics, 25, 125. 10.1007/s10683-021-09717-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E., & Gächter, S. (2000). Cooperation and punishment in public goods experiments. American Economic Review, 90(4), 980994. 10.1257/aer.90.4.980CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fehr, E., Bernhard, H., & Rockenbach, B. (2008). Egalitarianism in young children. Nature, 454(7208), 10791083. 10.1038/nature07155CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fromell, H., Nosenzo, D., Owens, T., & Tufano, F. (2021). One size does not fit all: plurality of social norms and saving behavior in Kenya. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 192, 7391. 10.1016/j.jebo.2021.09.028CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelfand, M. J., Raver, J. L., Nishii, L., Leslie, L. M., Lun, J., Lim, B. C., Duan, L., Almaliach, A., Ang, S., Arnadottir, J., & Aycan, Z. (2011). Differences between tight and loose cultures: A 33-nation study. Science, 332(6033), 11001104. 10.1126/science.1197754CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gintis, H. (2009). The Bounds of Reason: Game Theory and the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences-Revised Edition. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Groenendyk, E., Kimbrough, E. O., & Pickup, M. (2021). How norms shape the nature of belief systems in mass publics. American Journal of Political Science, 67(3), 623638. 10.1111/ajps.12717CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grueneisen, S., Wyman, E., & Tomasello, M. (2015). Children use salience to solve coordination problems. Developmental Science, 18(3), 495501. 10.1111/desc.12224CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grueneisen, S., Wyman, E., & Tomasello, M. (2015). “I know you don't know I know…” Children use second-order false-belief reasoning for peer coordination. Child Development, 86(1), 287293. 10.1111/cdev.12264CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haines, M., & Spear, S. F. (1996). Changing the perception of the norm: A strategy to decrease binge drinking among college students. Journal of American College Health, 45(3), 134140. 10.1080/07448481.1996.9936873CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hardin, R. (1982). Collective action. Resources for the Future.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harless, D. W., & Camerer, C. F. (1994). The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica, 62, 12511289. 10.2307/2951749CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, G. W., & Rutström, E. E. (2009). Expected utility theory and prospect theory: One wedding and a decent funeral. Experimental Economics, 12(2), 133158. 10.1007/s10683-008-9203-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunter, R. F., de la Haye, K., Murray, J. M., Badham, J., Valente, T. W., Clarke, M., & Kee, F. (2019). Social network interventions for health behaviours and outcomes: A systematic review and meta-analysis. PLoS Medicine, 16(9), e1002890 10.1371/journal.pmed.1002890CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hunter, R. F. et al., (2020). MECHANISMS Study: Using Game Theory to assess the effects of social norms and social networks on adolescent smoking in schools—study protocol. Frontiers in Public Health, 8, 377 10.3389/fpubh.2020.00377CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. (1986). Fairness as a constraint on profit seeking: Entitlements in the market. The American Economic Review, 76, 728741.Google Scholar
Kessler, J. B., & Leider, S. (2012). Norms and contracting. Management Science, 58(1), 6277. 10.1287/mnsc.1110.1341CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimbrough, E., & Vostroknutov, A. (2022). A Theory of Moral Reasoning. SSRN Working Paper.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimbrough, E. O., & Vostroknutov, A. (2016). Norms make preferences social. Journal of the European Economic Association, 14(3), 608638. 10.1111/jeea.12152CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimbrough, E. O., & Vostroknutov, A. (2018). A portable method of eliciting respect for social norms. Economics Letters, 168, 147150. 10.1016/j.econlet.2018.04.030CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kranton, R. E., & Sanders, S. G. (2017). Groupy versus non-groupy social preferences: Personality, region, and political party. American Economic Review, 107(5), 6569. 10.1257/aer.p20171096CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krupka, E. L., & Weber, R. A. (2013). Identifying social norms using coordination games: Why does dictator game sharing vary?. Journal of the European Economic Association, 11(3), 495524. 10.1111/jeea.12006CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krupka, E. L., Leider, S., & Jiang, M. (2017). A meeting of the minds: Informal agreements and social norms. Management Science, 63(6), 17081729. 10.1287/mnsc.2016.2429CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindbeck, A., Nyberg, S., & Weibull, J. W. (1999). Social norms and economic incentives in the welfare state. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114(1), 135. 10.1162/003355399555936CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, J. A., Petrie, R., & Samek, A. (2023). How experiments with children inform economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 61(2), 504564. 10.1257/jel.20211535CrossRefGoogle Scholar
López-Pérez, R. (2008). Aversion to norm-breaking: A model. Games and Economic Behavior, 64(1), 237267. 10.1016/j.geb.2007.10.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maggian, V., & Villeval, M. C. (2016). Social preferences and lying aversion in children. Experimental Economics, 19(3), 663685. 10.1007/s10683-015-9459-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mehta, J., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1994). The nature of salience: An experimental investigation of pure coordination games. The American Economic Review, 84(3), 658673.Google Scholar
Murakami, K., Shimada, H., Ushifusa, Y., & Ida, T. (2022). Heterogeneous treatment effects of nudge and rebate: Causal machine learning in a field experiment on electricity conservation. International Economic Review, 63(4), 17791803. 10.1111/iere.12589CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murray, J. M., Sanchez-Franco, S. C., Sarmiento, O. L., Kimbrough, E. O., Tate, C., Montgomery, S. C., Kumar, R., Dunne, L., Ramalingam, A., Krupka, E. L., Montes, F., Zhou, H., Moore, L., Bauld, L., Llorente, B., Kee, F., & Hunter, R. F. (2021). Homophily and peer influence effects for experimentally measured smoking and vaping norms, and smoking outcomes, for adolescents participating in school-based smoking prevention interventions: The MECHANISMS Study. Working Paper. 61pp.Google Scholar
Muthén, B., & Asparouhov, T. (2022). Latent transition analysis with random intercepts (RI-LTA). Psychological Methods, 21(1), 116. 10.1037/met0000370CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nosenzo, D., & Görges, L. (2020). Measuring social norms in economics: Why It Is important and how it is done. Analyse & Kritik, 42(2), 285312. 10.1515/auk-2020-0012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nylund-Gibson, K., Garber, A. C., Carter, D. B., Chan, M., Arch, D. A., Simon, O., Whaling, K., Tartt, E., & Lawrie, S. I. (2022). Ten frequently asked questions about latent transition analysis. Psychological Methods, 28(2), 284 10.1037/met0000486CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ostrom, E. (2000). Collective action and the evolution of social norms. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 14(3), 137158. 10.1257/jep.14.3.137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pe’erFeldmanGamlielSaharTikotskyHodSchupak, EYELANH (2019). Do minorities like nudges? The role of group norms in attitudes towards behavioral policy. Judgment and Decision Making, 14(1), 4050. 10.1017/S1930297500002898Google Scholar
Pickup, M., Kimbrough, E. O., & de Rooij, E. A. (2021). Expressive politics as (costly) norm following. Political Behavior, 10.1007/s11109-020-09667-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Probst, C., Vu, T. M., Epstein, J. M., Nielsen, A. E., Buckley, C., Brennan, A., Rehm, J., & Purshouse, R. C. (2020). The normative underpinnings of population-level alcohol use: An individual-level simulation model. Health Education & Behavior, 47(2), 224234. 10.1177/1090198119880545CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Reuben, E., & Riedl, A. (2013). Enforcement of contribution norms in public good games with heterogeneous populations. Games and Economic Behavior, 77(1), 122137. 10.1016/j.geb.2012.10.001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ridinger, G. (2018). Ownership, punishment, and norms in a real-effort bargaining experiment. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 155, 382402. 10.1016/j.jebo.2018.09.008CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rimal, R. N., Lapinski, M. K., Cook, R. J., & Real, K. (2005). Moving toward a theory of normative influences: How perceived benefits and similarity moderate the impact of descriptive norms on behaviors. Journal of Health Communication, 10(5), 433450. 10.1080/10810730591009880CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schelling, T. C. (1960). The strategy of conflict, Harvard University.Google Scholar
Stigler, G., & Becker, G. (1977). De gustibus non est disputandum. American Economic Review, 67(2), 7690.Google Scholar
Sugden, R. (1995). A theory of focal points. The Economic Journal, 105(430), 533550. 10.2307/2235016CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sutter, M., Zoller, C., & Glätzle-Rützler, D. (2019). Economic behavior of children and adolescents–A first survey of experimental economics results. European Economic Review, 111, 98121. 10.1016/j.euroecorev.2018.09.004CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tate, C., Kumar, R., Murray, J., Sanchez-Franco, S., Sarmiento, O. L., Montgomery, S. C., Zhou, H., Ramalingam, A., Krupka, E., Kimbrough, E. O., Kee, F., & Hunter, R. (2022). The personality and cognitive traits associated with adolescents’ sensitivity to social norms. Scientific Reports., 12, 15247 10.1038/s41598-022-18829-xCrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thomsson, K. M., & Vostroknutov, A. (2017). Small-world conservatives and rigid liberals: Attitudes towards sharing in self-proclaimed left and right. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 135, 181192. 10.1016/j.jebo.2017.01.023CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valente, T. W. (2012). Network interventions. Science, 337(6090), 4953. 10.1126/science.1217330CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yaari, M. E., & Bar-Hillel, M. (1984). On dividing justly. Social Choice and Welfare, 1(1), 124. 10.1007/BF00297056CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yun, D., & Silk, K. J. (2011). Social norms, self-identity, and attention to social comparison information in the context of exercise and healthy diet behavior. Health Communication, 26(3), 275285. 10.1080/10410236.2010.549814CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Figure 0

Table 1 Baseline mean sample characteristics for MECHANISMS schools

Figure 1

Fig. 1 Estimates of norm-following propensity

Figure 2

Fig. 2 Dictator game norms, on average

Figure 3

Table 2 Change in norm-following and norms

Figure 4

Fig. 3 Histograms of individual-level changes in norms and norm-following

Figure 5

Fig. 4 Estimated classes of norms from the latent transition analysis, and mean responses for individuals assigned to each class (± 2SEs). Note: The LTA model returns, for each class and each possible dictator action, the estimated probabilities of choosing each normative evaluation (i.e. 6 probabilities that sum to 1). Each grey dashed line plots the mean of those 6 probabilities for each dictator action, in a given class. Intuitively, the grey line captures the expected norm profile for someone in that class. Each solid black line shows the mean reported normative evaluation by subjects assigned to that class in either wave + / − 2 standard errors of the mean. Intuitively, overlap between grey and black shows how well the LTA model classifies the subjects. The solid grey reference line indicates where responses change from approval to disapproval. The title of each panel indicates how many subjects were assigned to that class in each wave

Figure 6

Fig. 5 Histogram of best-fitting latent class assignments, by location (Waves 1 and 2)

Figure 7

Table 3 Transition probabilities and frequency distribution of types (T1 and T2)

Figure 8

Table 4 Estimated peer effects on norm stability (i.e. probability of changing latent class assignment), by location

Supplementary material: File

Kimbrough et al. supplementary material

Kimbrough et al. supplementary material
Download Kimbrough et al. supplementary material(File)
File 1.3 MB