Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b95js Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T06:07:04.293Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Right to Do Wrong: Morality and The Limits of Law Mark Osiel Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 2019, 502 pp (hardback £36.95) ISBN: 978-0-674-36825-5

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 January 2021

David Turner*
Affiliation:
Chancellor of the Diocese of Chester
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © Ecclesiastical Law Society 2021

Any legal or political observer today knows that the law cannot undertake everything necessary to moral ordering in modern society and that it requires informal supplement at many points by concepts as diverse and socially complex as dishonour, shame, disrepute, reproach, disgrace, opprobrium, humiliation and stigma – to name but a few. These non-legal sanctions can, for good or ill, assume a life of their own. Often they have constituted a society's first line of defence against ethical transgression. As the author of this volume puts it:

Shared understandings of right and wrong inevitably fail to find their way fully into law, but nonetheless assert themselves – at observable points, in recognisable ways – when we seek to put our entitlements to use and encounter others who believe we act improperly. Ethical considerations barred from entering law's front door thus frequently sneak in through the back, influencing our conduct no less for the seeming circuity … Legal rights to do serious wrong, and the routine resistance against their abusive exercise, occupy the decisive points where these forces meet, contend and are compelled to mutually accommodate. (p 321)

The author sounds a wise and timely note of caution to those ‘keen to enlist the law against perceived defects in common morality wherever we discern them’ (p 319).

Professor Mark Osiel of the University of Iowa's College of Law has produced a wide-ranging, thought-provoking, interdisciplinary appraisal of this curious interplay between apparently lenient law and restrictive morality. ‘This book revives a certain dormant understanding of sociology, in the tradition of Montesquieu, to right this imbalance and the resulting distortion to our understanding of how law and morality interact’ (p 319). In support of his arguments he weaves an impressively detailed, copiously catalogued and carefully argued evaluation of ways in which factors like stigma and shame can, in some cases, be more effective than law in deterring action that humanity deems immoral. He draws on insights from philosophy, economics, the sociology of law and moral anthropology.

Although Osiel modestly (and humorously) characterises his work as ‘little more than sniffing about and sussing out the alternative scenarios’ (p 329) and assures his readers that his aim has not been to produce a ‘rousing jeremiad or soaring prophecy’ (p 329), there can be no doubting the seriousness of his purpose or the depth of his scholarship. That has, perhaps, come at the cost of an occasionally unwelcome wordiness (the notes and references alone run to 156 pages). The range of his analysis is, however, impressive, thoughtful, empirical and refreshing.

Much of what we could do, we shouldn't – and we don't. We could declare ourselves bankrupt to avoid debts, but not without stigma. We have a free-speech right to be offensive but may face outrage or even civil disturbance in response. We may decline medical attention and yet owe moral obligations to dependants or ourselves. Museums may retain masterworks looted from elsewhere decades before, but have at times to face opprobrium. The military has a right in international law to kill civilians during armed conflict if deaths are ‘incidental’ to the military purpose and not ‘clearly excessive’. But few Western powers openly embrace this right, voluntarily adopting more stringent rules of engagement. In each of these (and a host of other) situations, ‘the law permits what ordinary morality – widely shared notions of right and wrong – reproaches, sometimes severely’ (p 14).

Osiel's thesis in this significant and original book on the theory and practice of rights is that it is perhaps better to rely on these non-legal enforcement mechanisms than on the legal system itself. Too much law can lead to tyranny. There is paradox here. Law often grants people rights – in the hope that they will be exercised sparingly. Osiel calls these ‘rights to do wrong’.

Taking no assumptions for granted, the book is Osiel's attempt to

tame the extravagant claims of both those who ingenuously see the law as naturally, straightforwardly ‘reflecting’ or ‘mirroring’ common morality and those who cynically view these twin normative orders as traveling in altogether different orbits, as if lawmakers could afford to remain wholly unconcerned with what elicits keen indignation among ordinary people. (p 329)

He describes this complex study as ‘an elementary introduction from an advanced standpoint – or perhaps better, an advanced introduction to some elemental questions’ (p 12). His purpose: ‘to crisply formulate the concept of a right to do wrong, identify some of its sources and empirical expressions (with no pretence to exhaustiveness), suggest its significance within our legal order, and prompt its further study’ (p 12).

The author is very much alive to the ‘long term repercussions of living under conditions of acute moral plurality’ (p 42). He readily concedes that ‘common morality is an elusive notion, both conceptually and empirically’ (p 24), and he recognises that a ‘thick’ concept like ‘wrong’ has been substantially displaced by the thinner ‘inappropriate’. ‘Community standards’ seem ever harder to discern.

That this book ‘ventures no further reflection on these momentous matters’ (p 43) felt perhaps its greatest frustration. Osiel is too sophisticated a commentator to fail to recognise that ‘as a society fractures along any number of possible lines, common morality becomes at once more important for securing public order (in defensible form) and much more difficult to attain’ (p 43). He gently mocks the ‘weepy lamentations, periodically proclaimed from across the ideological spectrum, that we have lost a language of sharp moral appraisal’ (p 330).

It was not altogether easy to share the optimism of Osiel's concluding ‘good news’:

that modern liberal society discloses – here and there, in places both frequent and decisive – a demonstrable capacity for moral regeneration that remains little noticed. We do not depend entirely on the law and on an ever-dissolving inheritance of pre-liberal mores – the perennial fear of conservative culture critics. (pp 329–30)

One can only hope he is right.