Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-hvd4g Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T12:00:59.426Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Washing Away the Sins of Debt: The Nineteenth-Century Eradication of the Debtors' Prison

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 June 2013

Gustav Peebles*
Affiliation:
The New School
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article seeks to come to terms with the extraordinarily swift demise of the debtors' prison in multiple countries during the nineteenth century. While focusing primarily on the reform debate in England, I argue that the debtors' prison quickly came to be seen as a barbaric aberration within the expanding commercial life of the nineteenth century. By turning to a copious pamphletic literature from the era of its demise, I show how pamphleteers and eye-witnesses described the debtors' prison in the idiom of ritual; it was seen as a dangerous sanctuary that radically inverted all capitalistic economic practices and moral values of the world outside its walls. Reformers claimed that, inside these shrines of debt, citizens were ritually guided and transformed from active members of society into “knaves” or “idlers,” or both. As such, the debtors' prison needed to be eradicated. To do so, reformers mobilized at least three critical discourses, all of which sought to mark the debtors' prison as a zone of barbarism that threatened the civility of the state and its citizenry. By focusing on the debtors' prison as a powerful and transformative ritual zone, the article provides a counterintuitive history of this institution that was so crucial to the regulation of credit and debt relations for centuries. In so doing, the article contributes to a broader literature on the spatiality of debt.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Society for the Comparative Study of Society and History 2013 

[T]he Bankrupt Law is a mass of folly and absurdity from beginning to end; that it violates every principle of common sense; that it is the occasion of the grossest injustice, and the most appalling fraud and perjuries; that as, a whole, it is a disgrace to a civilized community.

———Fane Reference Fane1838a: 26Footnote 1

INTRODUCTION

Hobbes famously believed that government existed in order to deliver us from our supposed original “barbarism.” And yet the birth pangs of the Industrial Revolution, watched over by governments, were deemed “barbarous” by many who witnessed them, including important authors and theorists such as Karl Marx and John Stuart Mill. In particular, I will argue here, many nineteenth-century reformers believed that the very core of nascent capitalism—the legal relationship between creditor and debtor—had yet to rise beyond its supposed barbaric underpinnings.

Specifically, the explicit right of the creditor to seize and sequester the body of the debtor, and the corresponding implicit right of the debtor to flee his debts and thereby “swindle” the creditor out of his assets, allegedly created the same dark Hobbesian world that reasoned capitalist trade should eradicate. For example, one eyewitness to the indignities of the debtors' prisons explained, “Among the hideous effects produced on society, by arming the creditor with the power of locking up the debtor, is that of occasionally generating in their breasts, undying hostility one to another; of fostering the hateful passion of revenge…. Both [the creditor and the debtor], under the influence of the basest propensities of our nature, breathe destruction to one another…” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 54, my emphasis).Footnote 2 Or, as William Wordsworth put it more succinctly, “and thus [due to imprisonment for debt] does many a link which might have formed the chain of virtue [via capitalist exchange], become corroded with the rust of wickedness and vice” (Reference Wordsworth1831: 25).Footnote 3

The laws governing credit and debt were clearly not conducive to fostering a fully “civilized” society; thus, a massive campaign ensued, wherein both proponents and opponents of seizure for debt agreed that the system needed to be either substantially amended or abolished altogether. As these attitudes gradually spread and intensified, a vast, international reform effort managed to shutter all the debtors' prisons of Europe.Footnote 4 Indeed, seen in the broad scope of historical time, they were shuttered quite quickly.Footnote 5

Deep harmonies within this debate resonate across many decades and many countries, wherein one can readily discern that the central issues that I will outline here were virtually the same everywhere. Nevertheless, for the sake of simplicity, I will draw primarily, though not exclusively, from the abolition discussion in England, in order to show how pamphleteers on both sides of the debate viewed the reigning practice of imprisonment for debt as a “barbarous indulgence” (Fane Reference Fane1838c: 16). Pamphleteering opponents and proponents alike claimed that the laws were twisted inversions of the admirable aims and goals of the rest of the legal edifice of their civilized countries.Footnote 6

Working through a sampling from many primary documents, I will argue that the debtors' prison and its legal infrastructure were seen as a form of internal barbarism inside the bounds of the nation-state.Footnote 7 And just like barbarism in the colonies, it needed to be rooted out by a proselytizing mission, initially spurred by Christian “missionaries” who were agitating the state for change.Footnote 8 With sensible reforms, many believed that diligent debtors would be able to step out of the jails and back into productive working life, without the creditor needing to seize them out of a fear that they could easily flee.

In this sense, eradicating the ancient practice can be best understood as a colonization of internal space—the alleged remnants of barbarism—by similar modernization tendencies that we have come to know so well in the colonies (Dirks Reference Dirks2001; Merry Reference Merry2000; Stoler Reference Stoler2002; and for this story inside nation-states, see Elias Reference Elias and Jephcott2000; Frykman and Löfgren Reference Frykman and Löfgren1996; and Herzfeld Reference Herzfeld1987; Reference Herzfeld2002). In other words, if nascent capitalism were to succeed, its advocates believed that it needed to be tamed into civility. The story of the shuttering of the debtors' prison, therefore, underscores the well-established claim that liberal, capitalist ideology relied upon the commensurate and simultaneous construction of a supposedly barbaric Other.Footnote 9 But further, this Other was marked by his failure to responsibly grasp the meaning of his financial obligations, whether as creditor (by cruelly seizing bodies) or as debtor (by disdaining debts in various nefarious ways).Footnote 10

Given this rhetorical divide between barbarism and civilization, it should be no surprise that opponents and proponents of the debtors' prison both described it in the idiom of ritual. If modernist reformers convinced themselves that they could gradually reduce ritual life in favor of rational life, in the debtors' prison they discovered a special ritual sanctuary that oddly sealed people off from the humming and calculating capitalism growing outside of the penal walls. Time and again, we find that the debtors' prison was referred to as a shrine or sanctuary where people could take “momentary shelter from the storms of life, within its peaceful haven” (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 102). Intuitively, if someone had clearly failed at market relations, it made sense to banish him from them; as such, this was a ritual space specifically designed to be set apart from the standard bustle and regulation of daily economic life. Far less intuitively, opponents and proponents both noted that this temple had the dangerous capacity to forgive the sin of unpaid debt, so long as the initiate was willing to undergo a period of punishment and repentance. Given this, critics and proponents alike believed that the debtors' prison actually took neophytes and transformed them into listless non-capitalists, uninterested and incapable of working and planning for their own future.

Like many other rituals studied by the budding armchair anthropologists of the day, these rituals were deemed a “survival of barbarism” (anonymous 1829: 32). Or, as Mill averred, the debtors' prison and its grounding logic (along with debt peonage) stood as “the barbarous expedients of a rude age, repugnant to justice as well as to humanity” (Mill Reference Mill2004b: 828–29). The distinct ritual life housed and honed inside the debtors' prison—sometimes mind-numbingly legalistic, sometimes extravagantly festive—threateningly stood as an outright inversion of the rigors of capitalist life outside.Footnote 11 As will be shown, inside what Finn calls the “unreformed” debtors' prison, one could find eternal and legally enforced leisure, debauchery, and even a sort of plenty.

Such ritual spaces that trained people in non-bourgeois values and inverted the reality of everyday legal and market life needed to be eradicated. And so, within a mere two generations or so, the debtors' prison went from being an integral and essential regulatory mechanism in credit and debt relations to being seen as a barbarous relic of a different era, unfit for civilized countries. In what follows, I will trace three central discourses that were consistently relied upon to root out this supposed barbarism at the very heart of capitalist states.

Firstly, the application of scientific techniques to governmental practice was becoming standard across many fields, and the laws of credit and debt were no different. Reformers of all stripes insisted that causes needed to be discovered. For too long, policies had merely attempted to circumscribe the surface-level effects of social life; now policies had to get to the “root” of a problem, to see what was producing it. With regard to the debtors' prison, this was seen as a potentially simple new insistence that lawyers, prison officials, judges, sheriffs, and creditors should all begin to distinguish between malfeasance and misfortune. Some debtors deserved their just due in prison, while others suffered there irrationally at the hands of a barbaric system of injustice. Only a new dedication to scientific jurisprudence could carefully segregate these two inappropriately conjoined populations (see Stoler Reference Stoler1995).

Secondly, a fascinating dialectic between credit and debt emerges in this historical battle. Consistently, indebtedness is seen as a form of weakness and credit as a form of power.Footnote 12 If noted by reformers, then this weakness was something to be pitied; if noticed by proponents of imprisonment, then it required reform via disciplinary practice. But there is more. The dialectic appears to be one that pits credit as the vehicle of an expanding capitalism whereas debt is the standard-bearer of a gradually disappearing “economic traditionalism” (see Weber Reference Weber1958). Thus, both sides of the debate saw debtors as trapped by a decadent present, while creditors had their eyes keenly on a profitable future. Carefully planning for the future and denying oneself present pleasures was deemed the height of civilized behavior, and economic traditionalism supposedly brushed off such worries of tomorrow. Thus, society had to put in place new systems—either based on carrots or sticks—that would transform debtors from present-oriented spenders into future-oriented savers.

Finally, a supposedly Christian drive toward elevating the soul of the individual to the status of pricelessness took center stage. If the soul was priceless, then it became abhorrent to treat its vessel, the body, as a mere thing that could be seized as collateral like a piece of cheap property. Such conflations of money and the body, as I will show, came to be associated with “barbarism,” whereas a civilized society insisted upon a stark bifurcation of money-value and body-value. Simmel summed up this trend long ago by claiming that because the soul was proclaimed “to be the vehicle of God's grace, it became incommensurable with all worldly measures and has remained so” (Simmel Reference Simmel1978: 362).Footnote 13 It therefore became abhorrent to treat man as a commodity (which Simmel argues had previously been the practice), and “a later stage [in history] further severs the value of man from the value of money” (ibid.: 367). That “later stage,” so far as this paper is concerned, commences with the widespread and rapid abolition of imprisonment for debt.

Though Foucault oddly neglected the rapid demise of the debtors' prison in Discipline and Punish (Reference Foucault and Sheridan1977), the story of its pan-national institutional collapse nonetheless fits nicely with his famous model.Footnote 14 The rhetoric and action that led to the demise of the debtors' prison turns upon the three emergent trends discussed here: A categorizing spirit, a disciplining of the body, and an expanded surveillance over the circulation of people and things. Parties on all sides of the debate converged in their belief that citizens within national spaces had to be transformed into a new cadre of disciplined economic actors who could turn to a newly rationalized and more efficient governmental apparatus for adjudicating credit and debt relations. Proponents and opponents of the debtors' prison both asked governments to step into this void of failed adjudication in order to better aid its citizens in meeting their obligations to their fellow citizens and in responsibly planning for their own futures. Within the ambit of its power, reformers expected the state—in Hobbesian fashion—to banish the supposed barbarity that remained at the core of exchange relations.

MALFEASANCE VERSUS MISFORTUNE

As mentioned above, all parties in this debate hoped that a new scientific and categorizing spirit could rationally categorize economic behavior in new ways. The state and its reformers sought to find the “true” reasons for debt delinquency and then treat the cause, rather than rely on an unscientific catchall law from a previous era. As Field put it, “The duty of society is not only to resent and punish the crimes committed, but also to carefully to seek out their causes, and, so far as it is in human power, to remove them…” (1848: 91). In the past, all debtors were treated de facto the same—as quasi criminals, locked up in a custodial prison even if they were not seen as guilty of anything other than bad luck. As one resident of Whitecross debtors' prison expounded, “Some of the greatest scoundrels have been discharged, and others whose misfortunes have proceeded from the most venial errors, have got a remand” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 45).Footnote 15

But a reformist spirit began to insist that there was a grand and necessary divide between honest and dishonest debtors, and that it was the state's task to objectively delineate the two, rather than allowing private creditors to keep subjectively treating them in an identical fashion. As the governor of the Whitecross put it, “I divide debtors into only two classes, honest and fraudulent…. it is monstrous that the same sentence should await the guilty and the guiltless” (Hicks Reference Hicks1858: 19–20). One anonymous pamphleteer spoke of the ignorant way in which multiple categories of human action bled into each other under the unscientific approach of the reigning legal system: “Should the same punishment await the industrious and the unfortunate—the young and innocent, the defenceless widow, the blind, the ingenious, as the gamester, and swindler?… He who would maintain it must be either ignorant or heartless. Yet the law of Arrest subjects all to the same insulting useless and cruel degradation” (anonymous 1837: 15). Reformers such as these now demanded that malfeasance and misfortune be treated as the potential proximate cause of bankruptcy, and that judges seek out the true reason for insolvency rather than criminalize the lack of money per se.Footnote 16

Before these reforms, the law turned on no other data point than the lack of payment, regardless of the reason for it. Even Fane, one of the more vociferous proponents of imprisonment, complained, “By the law, as it at present stands, insolvency is assumed to be a crime!” (1838a: 27). And the lobbyists for the creditor class of this era were quick to point out why; in practice, they explained, it was virtually impossible to empirically study the etiology of debt. One partisan of the debtors' prison, J. H. Elliott, explained, “A man's moral conduct is not easily ascertained; his pecuniary embarrassments can only be learned by a scrutinizing and inquisitorial investigation, which is too severe for many to submit to, or to be enforced” (1838: 22). Mill complicated matters further by stating that the line between negligence and fraudulence was highly fraught: “If a man has been a spendthrift, or a gambler, with property on which his creditors had prior claim, shall he pass scot-free because the mischief is consummated and the money gone? Is there any very material difference in point of morality between this conduct, and those other kinds of dishonesty which go by the names of fraud and embezzlement?” (2004b: 830). And anyway, empirically speaking, debtors had made off with resources originally owned by someone else, and therefore, they asserted, it was no giant leap to assume that “by far the greater part of all insolvencies arise from notorious misconduct” (Elliott, cited by Mill Reference Mill2004b: 830). Elliott concludes that the loss of someone else's money should be seen “as prima facie evidence of something wrong” (ibid.: 831).Footnote 17

Fane and others suggested that misguided laws that treated all inabilities to pay as prima facie evidence of criminality resulted in countless people becoming fraudulent only because of those laws. One lawyer from Spain, when queried by a committee of London merchants about bankruptcy law in his country, stated, “I am of the opinion, that punishment being very severe, as in Spain, opens the door to fraud, the original report of the failure being framed to avoid criminal results” (Committee of Merchants 1851: 31). Both he (an opponent) and Fane (a proponent) agreed that hefty punishments for non-fraudulent bankruptcies created the conditions to legally transform honest people into dishonest people (Fane Reference Fane1838b: 40–42). They both asserted that, in this manner, the existence of the debtors' prison effectively worked as a ritualistic space of personal transformation, virtually cajoling people to turn themselves into criminals.

Hoping to eliminate such perverse outcomes, people such as Beccaria and Bentham, and countless reformers in their wake, believed that the nefarious intent or hapless misfortune of a debtor could be rooted out with some simple efforts on the part of judges and juries: “It should be possible to distinguish fraud from grievous culpability, the grievous from the mitigated culpability, and this last from perfect innocence” (Beccaria Reference Beccaria and Bellamy1995: 90). With such fine-grained assessments of how people became insolvent, punishment could then finally be meted out that scientifically matched the offense. To be clear, reformers were stating that all cases of insolvency should go through this process, not just those of people deemed prima facie innocent.

In other words, people began to make the radical demand that debtors should not be locked up for ages prior to their culpability being proven. As Bentham pointed out, under the existing system, “The door is shut against evidence, and presumptions made without grounds are substituted to it” (Reference Bentham1843: 176). Further, debtors often did not know for which debts they were being incarcerated, since creditors were not obliged to come forth immediately. Any creditor in England, even a fraudulent one, could easily obtain a writ stating that a sheriff must apprehend a debtor who “lurks, wanders, and runs about in your county” (Farley Reference Farley1788: 63). One author tells the story that there is “A gentleman in Newgate [prison], who was arrested by the wicked contrivance of a villain that he might live in infamy with the gentleman's wife” (ibid.: 22). Evidence, such as it was, was heard ex parte, a sort of evidence ordinarily enjoined in British courts.Footnote 18 Sham witnesses and sham creditors named “John Doe” and “Richard Roe” appeared in the record all too commonly (e.g., ibid.: 52). In a word, the debtors' prison apparatus stood as the inverse of the standard legal infrastructure. As one famous leader begged to know, “Can a more wretched state of man be conceived? Nay, more, does even the fraudulent debtor merit this perpetual, undefined punishment, in all the wantonness of its tyranny?” (Neild Reference Neild1808: 24). All this, reformers asserted, needed to change, by bringing the hallmarks of science into the picture—objectivity, transparency, and etiology. The personal power of imprisonment based on these sorts of slim claims needed to be taken over by an impartial judge, who could weigh the evidence, presume innocence, and better sanction the proceedings with the prestige of the state.

Without such reforms, the system was ripe for abuse. Not least, people on all sides of the debate noted that authentically fraudulent debtors seemed to be far less likely to do time in jail than did honest ones. Because fraudulent debtors could easily set themselves up as traders and enjoy certain protections of the bankruptcy statutes, Neild explained, “The honest debtor may be starved before he can have the benefit of its [of one of the latest bankruptcy bills] provisions; while the fraudulent debtor finds in it the very probable, if not certain prospect of his liberation” (1808: 31). As a consequence, honest debtors “constitute by far the greater number of those who fill our prisons—with a considerable proportion of poets, authors, mathematicians, and men of science, who are the instructors, the amusers, and the pioneers of civilized society…. The gamesters, spendthrifts and profligates, constitute only a small proportion, and from all that is known are not much improved by this method of annoying them” (anonymous 1837: 14, my emphasis). In the prison, the honest debtors would become ritually contaminated by the spendthrifts and gamesters, and reenter society worse than they had gone in: “The great flux and reflux of men continually going in and out of prison, is like a stinking water, that poisons the wholesome rivers of the kingdom” (Farley Reference Farley1788: 133–34).

If, by turning to these new scientific means, fraudulence were proved, then all universally agreed that the body of the debtor should be punished in any number of ways. Beccaria recommended that they “be punished with the same penalties which attach to the counterfeiter, because counterfeiting a metal coin, which is a token of the obligations citizens owe to each other, is no greater crime than counterfeiting the obligations themselves” (1995: 89). A lawyer in Berlin announced his preference for the death penalty, while the Finns remained committed to pillory in the market square with an iron collar. The Antwerpians had abolished branding, but were still quick to lock up the fraudulent debtor.Footnote 19 Negligence was not as egregious as fraudulence, but one could still land in jail in countless countries if such behavior were proven. For example, in Sweden one could get a sentence of two years and hard labor for “carelessness” with other people's money (Committee of Merchants 1851). All of these beliefs turned on the idea that fraudulent debtors were criminals; as such, they should not be tried in civil courts, but in criminal ones, and their punishments should be the same as for any other form of criminality.

Lacking this dividing line between malfeasance and misfortune, the system that undergirded the debtors' prison was deemed a vile and aberrant space within the heart of the state, achieving goals that were precisely the opposite of its stated intention. One author likened it to a cultural system that takes in multifarious categories of people, churns them through its system, and then christens them with an untrue, but no less real, legal status: “It involves the honest and dishonest, the truthful and the habitually false, the accidentally unfortunate and the pre-determined cheat, in the meshes of the same net, returning all ‘tarred with the same brush’—rogues all in fact” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 4). Approaching credit and debt relations with a new scientific epistemology would allow for these categories to stop blending into unjust hybrids; people would be assessed for their “true” status as either knave, or victim. Reformers agitated against the mystified and barbarous understanding of money as itself an index of moral standing and upright behavior, and hoped to build a homogenous national space dedicated to empirical evidence and fair treatment to all, regardless of monetary wealth. The temple would be razed in favor of the laboratory.

ECONOMIC TRADITIONALISM VERSUS CAPITALISM

This new drive to discover empirical evidence that could scientifically distinguish malfeasance from misfortune rested on a moral distinction: Had a debtor behaved in an “upstanding” manner with the money, or not? Via this question, a sustained rhetoric connecting loose money with loose morals came to the fore in the debate over the demise of the debtors' prison. Getting to the heart of a debtor's behavior hinged on the emergent distinction—newly vital within political economic debates—between a supposedly “spendthrift and decadent” economic traditionalism and a “parsimonious and hard-working” capitalism.Footnote 20

Honest debtors, it was claimed, thought about tomorrow. They had simply suffered through unforeseeable events, such as a nationwide financial panic. Dishonest debtors—often called “swindlers,” “rogues,” or “knaves”—were seen to appropriate economic value unto themselves merely for “luxuries” or daily enjoyments at the tavern. Attempting to get one debtor thrown in jail, a lawyer argued before an insolvency judge, “Mr. Yearlar, an officer of the court, proved that the defendant was in the habit of getting drunk nearly every night” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 71). If suspected of leisure, the house of confinement beckoned. In short, a dominant strain of discourse saw a direct and harmonious linkage between a lack of control over one's body and a lack of control over one's wallet.

Mill's favorite pamphleteer on the topic of credit law reform, Mr. J. H. Elliott, provides the most transparent announcement of this attitude: “If we place creditors in one lot, and debtors in another, justice and mercy will characterize the former, as often as fraud and improvidence will characterise the alter…. Creditors, as a body, are a superior class of men; those who are able to give credit are usually better men, possessing a higher morale, more intelligence, habits of far distant calculation, than the debtor who cannot pay; he is the converse of all this…” (Elliott Reference Elliott1838: 23).

Given this alleged ethical distinction between creditors and debtors, what was Elliott's formula for reform? To turn debtors into capitalists: “Severe as it may seem, they must learn to live in the daily and hourly habit of enduring labour, and of abstaining from the instant enjoyment of its fruits. The master virtues for them, and for all mankind are industry, providence, and self-dependence” (ibid.: 24). Mill approvingly quotes Elliott when he compares bankrupts to children at school who have no care for the morrow and are surprised when they discover that they have no more money left. The body and mind of the debtor needed to be cajoled into thinking—like the noble creditor—about tomorrow. According to the proponents of retaining imprisonment for debt, the fear of the prison was the technology most ideally suited to enforcing this moralistic regime. If one could just dread tomorrow's prison sentence, then one would easily deny oneself the pleasures of today.

The problem, however, was that the debtors' prison itself gradually came to be seen as a ritualistic space that cultivated precisely this “indolence” and pleasure-seeking: “Who has not heard of Queen's Bench prison? … Is there a lounger in Pall-mall, a saunterer in Regent-street, who has not had a friend there at one time of his life or another? Has not everyone known men prefer it to Rome, Baden-Baden, or Vienna?” (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 102).Footnote 21 Perhaps even more astonishingly, one author cited Defoe, who pointed out as far back as 1722 that the King's BenchFootnote 22 had better outdoor facilities, while the Fleet had better indoor ones (see Image 1, depicting the outdoor space of the King's Bench in use). For this reason, “Some of those gentlemen that are in for vast sums, and probably for life, choose the one for their summer, the other for their winter habitation; and indeed both are but the show and name of prisons” (ibid.: 114–15).Footnote 23 Many writers of the day who shared this perspective saw the debtors' prison as a space outside of quotidian time, and for them the terms “shrine” or “sanctuary” stood as far more apt monikers than “prison” or “jail.”

Image 1. Enforced leisure at the King's Bench, with people playing squash and strolling in their Sunday finest, all while behind the barbed wired wall to the left.

To keep the dangers of inveterate debtors at bay, the debtors' prison was designed to be segregated from commercial life, and inside, leisure reigned by decree; some prisoners who tried to maintain their good work habits failed nonetheless, given the tempting surroundings and poor moral fiber of their compatriots (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 283). More than one author referred to it as a strict regime of “enforced leisure” (e.g., H. [anonymous] 1859). Another writer called it a “sanctuary of the unfortunate” (anonymous 1823: 4), while yet another describes the all-night parties in the prison bar (Hicks Reference Hicks1858: 12–13).Footnote 24 In the bar, prisoners revealed themselves to be “apparently insensible to the effects of that high and gloomy wall which surrounds and shuts them from the world: this is their world, and their ideas seem scarcely ever to soar beyond it. It is not here you see the pensive brow, the lengthened countenance, and the dejected gait” (anonymous 1823: 12). By day, prisoners played squash and gambled, prior to singing and carousing at night. In short, “You will almost forget that you are suffering imprisonment, but find yourself involved in a bustling and active life, and may regale at pleasure” (ibid.: 10).

By the nineteenth century, English commentators remarked that there were even “wealthy beggars” inside the debtors' prisons (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 121). Another report insisted, “Indeed the most extensive tavern can hardly ever shew a better assortment of the good things of this life … and the absolute gourmand be excited to regale. There is nothing of insolvency in the appearance of this department of the establishment, indeed so much the reverse, that the epicure stranger would consider it the paradise of feasting” (anonymous 1823: 9). This luxury extended beyond drink and food, and we find that, at least at the King's Bench, “Many of the cells of these detenues are beautifully fitted up; carpets, books, pictures, and luxuries of every kind may be seen in them according to the taste and opulence of the inmate. There are men here who make up their minds to consider themselves at home” (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 118). Thus, in many instances, a life of mandated ease was complemented by a life of relative plenty—two conditions that were far from operative for the vast majority of citizens outside the prison.Footnote 25

And all this decadence was couched in the terms of ritual. One dispatch from inside Whitecross prison reads as if it were taken straight from the anthropological record, complete with ritual elders, initial debasement of the neophyte, and subsequent social rebirth:

At his entrance among the infected herd of confined debtors, the neophyte is naturally cast down and dispirited. With his liberty he has lost his self-respect. The sudden change from locomotion at will to narrow limits, terminating in bolts and bars unnerves him. He looks about with a vacant stare, and fancies he reads a reproach in every eye. He is thoroughly abased. But these effects are of very short duration. He is suddenly startled by the sound of boisterous merriment…. All sense of shame, all dignity of manhood is crushed out of him…. All are prompt to lend their zealous aid in forwarding, in shaping, and in accomplishing the education of our neophyte (H. [anonymous] 1859: 5–6).

This is an education in living for the present—in lifting the veil from the ideology of work (see Day, Papataxiarchis, and Stewart Reference Day, Papataxiarchis and Stewart1999). Prisoners, once tempted by this life of ease and plenty, will rarely manage to rediscover the supposed pleasures of commercial life again. Instead, “After a short term of imprisonment on the indolent system, men, who by nature are full of energy, become listless, taking interest in trifles, and restoring to modes of killing time to which they would not descend when at liberty” (Hicks Reference Hicks1858: 15).

But it is worse, for this ritualistic life of ease and plenty not only teaches them to walk away from the future and instead indulge in today's trifles, it actually debases them and turns them into mere shadows of civilized humanity. To wit, “He becomes careless in his language, in his attire, in his gestures, and his every day voluntary actions…. and as the heart is abundantly wicked, its native wickedness, freed from the reins of caution and decorum, has ample room to expand in all its rank luxuriance” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 13). Innocent people subjected to this training and luxury supposedly lost their ability to plan for the future. One prisoner, for example, was sent a guinea once a week by his charitable friends, only to spend it that very first evening on an extravagant meal, without a care for how he might procure the next six nights of food (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 110–11). Loose money, loose morals.

Fascinatingly, the prison did have an active commercial life of buying and selling, but only with hard cash. Since anyone confined there had already proven themselves incapable of paying back their debts, credit was (somewhat obviously) not relied upon as a medium of exchange. But credit was further dead on arrival because profligacy was apparently one of the paramount social values of the prison, according to the reform literature surveyed here. Prisoners shared freely with one another (anonymous 1823: 12), failed to respect property (H. [anonymous] 1859: 35), and when they did manage to get their hands on money, they often squandered it on beer and food before the day was up (anonymous 1837: 15). These are all the classic hallmarks of the supposed barbaric economic traditionalist and his lackadaisical approach to his own economy. Without credit lashing anyone to the future, the debtors' prison was, by definition, a space that enforced a timeless orientation toward the present.

But reformers sought to eradicate this educational facility, which was perversely dedicated to living in the present. The governor of Whitecross, in one of his reform tracts put it bluntly: “I desire also to prevent a prison from being used as a sanctuary where fraudulent debtors can defy upright creditors and live in luxurious indolence” (Hicks Reference Hicks1858: 30–31). Like countless other reformers, he proposed that prisoners' work be allowed and even remunerated inside the prison. Work provides the only “honest road to freedom” out of the “condemned idleness” of the jail (ibid.: 21, 24). The transformation to degeneracy facilitated by the debtors' prison must be broken by a new commitment to bring previously banished future-planning into the confines of the prison.

In demanding this radical reform, the governor implies, perhaps unconsciously, that life inside the debtors' prison resembles nothing so much as the Garden of Eden, for he wrote, “Scripture says, ‘In the sweat of man's face shall he eat bread;’ why should imprisoned debtors be compelled to form the exceptions to the rule of the Omnipotent? Why should man issue a counter mandate, ‘Thou shalt not work,’ and thus clash with the Divine command?” (ibid.: 29).Footnote 26 This verse comes from Genesis 3:19—the author was citing the new stricture pronounced by God that humankind must forever and anon suffer a life of toil, directly after discovering that Eve had eaten the forbidden fruit. The governor of Whitecross has acknowledged here that the debtors' prison stood as a space apart, an inversion of the life of toil and trouble that characterized the burgeoning industrial city outside its confines. Lest this sound like a stretch, Bentham also criticized the debtors' prison for providing a “paradise” to the swindler (1843: 177). Civilizing Man could never allow this antediluvian “survival of barbarism” to remain (anonymous 1829: 32). The ideology of work and future-orientation had to penetrate the prison too—into its “peaceful haven.”

MONEY AND FREEDOM

Bolstering their arguments that an internal barbarism had to be eradicated from within the nation-state, reformers also homed in on the manner in which the debtors' prison implied that human life and its “God-given” soul could have a price tag. Following a well-known trope, that anything given by God cannot, by definition, have a price, they reasoned, “It is most iniquitous to authorize the creditor to make the debtor expiate his default of goods or money, by taking his flesh and blood, his body and bones. The maxim: ‘If you cannot pay in purse, you shall in person,’ is unworthy of the enlightening age in which we live…. You take an invaluable jewel, for a worthless pebble. You take the precious immortal soul, and carry it to your place of torment, in satisfaction of perishable goods; things called into existence by the hand of art, but yesterday, and which may cease to be, to-morrow” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 62–63). According to this logic, only barbarians are unenlightened enough to place a money value on human life, whereas civilized people raised it to the level of the sacred.Footnote 27 But reformers voices were beginning to be heard, and, “Happily the influence of our holy religion is felt by those who administer the law. Its truths control both opinion and practice. The magistrates of our land are increasingly sensible of the inestimable value of the human soul” (Field Reference Field1848: 86–88).

The practical solution, according to both sides of the debate, was to carefully acknowledge the segregation of monetary-value and human-value, goods from man. A monetary dispute involved things that were worth money—goods and chattel and land—and not human bodies. Thus, legislation needed to establish that the “laws should be directed against the property and not the person, excepting in the case of fraud, or intended departure from England” (anonymous 1837: 18). “Let property be balanced against property; let not bodily pain and mental suffering be inflicted, as the penalty of misfortune…. Take his property in satisfaction of the property he has acquired from you and dissipated; but bring not his crown to the dust—riot not in his life-blood” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 38–39). Turning to more ritualistic imagery, this same pamphleteer poetically inveighed, “The Juggernauth [sic] of the law, alike insensible to pity or remorse, drives his blood-stained car over your prostrate and butchered liberty. Another victim has been passed through the fire to Moloch, to whom as with the ensanguined idol of old, innocence is only an additional cause for prey” (ibid.: 9).

Quotes such as these reveal that the debtors' prison was viewed as a monstrous assemblage that allowed the body to be contaminated with money-value. Indeed, it actually provided a peculiar and socially sanctioned space for continuing to evaluate bodies on a monetary scale. All too often, apparently, people happily traded money and bodies back and forth, agreeing to lose their freedom rather than acknowledge a monetary debt. Because imprisoned debtors were protected from any further seizures, even if they carried “the very means of payment in the current coin of the realm on his person,” debtors quickly discovered that they could stay in the prison rather than meet payment (Fane Reference Fane1838a: 28).Footnote 28 Suddenly safe from additional losses and banished from normal commercial life, “The prisons afford harbour to many men … who would rather spend their small remains of property there, than give it the creditor who has been his ruin” (Farley Reference Farley1788: 149–50). Footnote 29 One reforming governor found, “A great many [prisoners] … lying there without an object in life, except to indulge in a lazy inanity.” He managed to get rid of many, but “some, however, successfully resisted the pressure put upon them, and still present the strange anomaly of men who prefer captivity to liberty, boasting, as they do, of being ‘their own gaolers’” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 32–33).

The problem that these authors are addressing is a fascinating one. Citizens were supposed to relish their priceless liberty as a foundational and inalienable right. But the history of the debtors' prison reveals that many preferred an entirely different form of liberty—liberty from monetary relations. For example, Hardouin complains that the reforms must create measures to cope with people who have “apathy or indifference for liberty” and therefore opt to stay in prison indefinitely (Reference Hardouin1874: 484). Contrary to the aims of the institution, debtors “have found the King's bench, and its rules, a happy and welcome asylum, where persecution ends. To such men a calm and quiet retirement is a blessing—they seek it—they seek a noiseless privacy, where they may commune with their own thoughts, and be in themselves the world which they have left” (anonymous 1823: 1). Another author explained, “Some of the detenues are smoking long pipes with the resigned and settled air of Orientals; they have apparently ceased to struggle with their fate.… Several of these persons have been locked up here five, six, or seven years.… Some of them have now no other homes, and wish for none. Others of the motley group are lounging jauntily about with a reckless and devil-may-care manner (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 277).Footnote 30

Finding that prisoners had taken on supposedly foreign traits, not least by descending into opium use, reformers discovered a legally demarcated zone of reprieve from standard capitalist life. They were clearly befuddled and flummoxed by such brazen refusals to submit to the rigors of future-oriented capitalism, and its promises of bodily freedom. They failed to grasp how some people might prefer freedom from the market over freedom in the market.

But the prison's enshrined and protected borders from market life frustrated reformers for yet another reason. As has been shown, the prison had a capacity to protect debtors from paying their debts while locked up. But it also provided a series of dense legal rituals that allowed debtors to “wash” themselves of their debts. In many instances, one could go into a prison for a specific period and perform specific legal rituals instead of paying off the debt. As one inside report from Whitecross put it,

The fact is, that just then the furnace at the Insolvent Court was in full blast, turning out, monthly, again on the community, its scores of spick-and-span new characters that had been purified by the fire, and thus renovated were rendered again fit to re-enter the world of trade and commerce, from which they had for a time been banished…. I had yet to learn that Whitecross Street was the vestibule to Portugal Street [the location of the Insolvent Debtors' Court], and that its principal mission was to afford the needy debtor the means of escape from the grasp of his hostile creditor (H. [anonymous] 1859: 19).Footnote 31

The debtors' prison banished people from commercial life. Once inside, should they decide that living a life outside of capitalism was appealing, they could stay forever inside the bounds of the prison and become its ritual elders; should they decide that they would like to return to it, the system allowed them to be cleansed of their debts and reenter commercial life as a new soul, afresh.Footnote 32

This ritual complex, with its high priests (lawyers), elders (inveterate debtors), neophytes (newly imprisoned debtors) and temples (the prisons), was seen to threaten capitalism itself. Credit, as Elliott and Mill both insisted, was “the life of commerce.” But the debtors' prison created and sustained a world where people could brazenly abuse credit by manipulating the status of their bodies, either by way of cleansing or confinement. This foundational bleeding between two categories that supposedly should be kept separate then succeeded in inverting societal values and goals, by “turning it [the law] from its mission of protecting the rights of person and property, into that of invading, harassing, and destroying them!” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 4).

CONCLUSION

With capitalism growing at an ever-faster clip during the Industrial Revolution, more and more people became enmeshed in debt relations. With debt seemingly everywhere, the prison's ritualistic capacity to nullify the power of monetary obligations and endorse the present-orientation of economic traditionalism was far more dangerous than it had been in the past. One author suggested that the number of debtors had grown so large “that a wall should be built round the borough of Southwark, [the southern half of London, where the King's Bench Prison could be found] because it might be then possible to find a room for every single debtor” (Farley Reference Farley1788: 39). For their earlier history, the debtors' prisons had primarily housed only the poorest and the wealthiest members of society, excluding the broad middle classes.Footnote 33 But once its function as a space free from the rigors of bourgeois capitalism had been democratized beyond these two groups, the debtors' prison's power became more of a threat to the system, and it had to be removed.

If reformers believed that there was a distinct correlation between loose money and loose morals, then they needed to eradicate any special zones that enshrined such non-bourgeois behavior. They needed to recommend new ways to instill a capitalist ethos that could combat the pernicious power of economic traditionalism. The intriguing concept of “The Rules” that surrounded debtors' prisons in many countries lays the groundwork for this. Physically outside the prison, The Rules stood as an extension of the prison itself, but without the extreme constraints of bars and bolts. For example, Image 2 shows “The Rules of the Kings Bench prison in London,” with the prison itself slightly left of center. Prisoners with special privileges to inhabit The Rules were free to reenter civic life inside The Rules, in the hopes that they might better pay off their debts, at less cost to the state to boot.Footnote 34 But economic traditionalism was still clearly policed inside The Rules, for public houses inside them remained forbidden ground.Footnote 35

Image 2. The “Rules” of the King's Bench in 1830, with the prison in the middle-left section of the map, and the Rules marked by the dotted line.

One American reformer, in critiquing the debtors' prison, hinted that The Rules could serve as an adequate replacement for the prison itself. He explained that many American states have “denounced the practice [of imprisonment for debt] as sanguinary, and as a foul blot upon our national character. In many parts of New England, the prison bounds are extended to the limits of the township or county in which the prison is located. The Legislative Council of Michigan have [sic] extended the gaol limits to the bounds of the county” (Johnson Reference Johnson1823: 15). With The Rules, we see prison surveillance spilling out beyond its traditional walls, without the need of imprisonment itself. Once this form of surveillance had proven its capacities, it was perhaps but a small step to imagine that the walls themselves were unnecessary. The only remaining way to escape such surveillance was to disappear into exile abroad—to become, in a word, “socially dead” to the community, only to be reborn with a clean slate in a new community.Footnote 36

Thus, much in line with Foucault's arguments in Discipline and Punish, the evolution from debtors' prison to The Rules to state borders suggests that the nation-state replaced the immuring function of the debtors' prison.Footnote 37 That is to say, the nation-state served to replace the debtors' prison by itself becoming a zone of custodial surveillance—both by eradicating ritualistic zones that cleansed or harbored the indebted, and by improving border management to ensure that citizens could no longer easily flee their debts by decamping abroad. In so doing, it held adequately at bay the menacing threat of internal barbarism that supposedly trained people to hold disdain for their debts or taught them to seize bodies as collateral. In his testimony before the U.S. Senate, Colonel Johnson provides an ironic and unintentional synopsis of much of this battle between internal barbarism and national civilization. As he closed his fiery speech against the barbarity of the debtors' prison, he reached deep into the mythical construction of America itself, in order to conclude, “For this love of liberty, a principle inherent in man, the savage still adheres to his wandering life, and spurns the proposition for civilization, because, in his view, prisons mark its bounds” (1823: 20). Foucault could not have agreed more.

Footnotes

1 C. Fane, Esq., was a commissioner in the English bankruptcy courts, and despite this quote, a proponent of retaining imprisonment for debt.

2 This stands in contrast to Hirschman's (Reference Hirschman1997) well-known argument that many early proselytizers of capitalism claimed that it actually restrained “natural passions.”

3 Margot Finn (Reference Finn2003) has written a superb book related to this topic, as has Bruce Mann (Reference Mann2002). Duffy's (Reference Duffy1985) and Lester's (Reference Lester1995) separate contributions are also essential reading, especially as they relate to the many intricate distinctions among different acts of the English Parliament as it gradually worked its way through nineteenth-century reforms of the law of creditor and debtor. Balleisen (Reference Balleisen2001), Graeber (Reference Graeber2011), and Sandage (Reference Sandage2005) all also productively tackle the history of the debtors' prison. Hautcoeur (Reference Hautcoeur2008) provides guidance on French reforms, but he complains about the general lack of scholarly interest in the debtors' prison inside France. Wennerlind (Reference Wennerlind2011) provides an excellent depiction of the financial revolution that sets the stage for the later demise of the debtors' prison.

4 As will be shown, even the famed inventor of the Panopticon, Jeremy Bentham, got in on the act (Bentham Reference Bentham1843). Beyond him, specific leaders within the general prison reform movement were well-known adversaries of imprisonment for debt: De Tocqueville in France, Julius and Mittermaier in Germany, Olivecrona and King Oscar in Sweden, Bentham and Howard in England, and Ducpetiaux in Belgium. The list goes on, but they all formed a tight-knit circle of scholars and prison officials who believed that Europe was gradually leaving behind a benighted “ancient” age, and would deliver humanity and justice to a new era. See Nutz Reference Nutz2005, and Vanhulle Reference Vanhulle2010, for excellent articles on the transnational connections of the prison reform movement.

5 Eventually, societies did succeed in eradicating the debtors' prison and all this international agitation bore fruit. Due to federalism, the United States abolished it piecemeal, beginning in Kentucky as early as 1821. In Europe, France was apparently the first, with legislation in 1867. The northern German union followed in 1868, Austria and Belgium in 1871, Denmark in 1872, and Switzerland and Norway in 1874. England closed the doors of its debtors' prisons in 1869. Finland joined this clear international trend in 1895 (see Nordisk Familjebok 1905: 792–93).

6 Pamphleteers in England mostly hearkened from the legal profession (e.g., Fane was a judge in the bankruptcy court; Hicks was a prison warden), the merchant classes, imprisoned debtors, and finally from the emergent brand of “Christian economists” described by Hilton (Reference Hilton1988). All of their views were wide-ranging, and the debate was hotly contested over many years. Nevertheless, the background context of that national conversation coalesced, I believe, around the civilizing mission that I outline here.

7 There is an immense amount of precise information about specific laws changing in specific years in specific countries. But here I will focus on the deep resonances across multiple discourses rather than on distinctions between them. So, for example, I will not dwell on differences between the English reform of 1823 and that of 1844, or compare the laws of Spain and Holland.

8 Neild (Reference Neild1808) stands as one of the exemplars of this tradition, but countless reformers discuss the role of Christianity in the reform movement. In doing so, they endlessly cited Matthew 6:12: “And forgive us our debts, as we also have forgiven our debtors.” Boyd Hilton's (Reference Hilton1988) work lays the groundwork for much of this argument about “Christian Economics,” though his text only turns to the issue of insolvency as a beneficial Job-ian moral test for the capitalist, and does not probe the debate surrounding the debtors' prison itself.

9 Herzfeld (Reference Herzfeld1987) provides a particularly incisive contribution to the social construction of this divide between barbarian and civilized, and how it has been operationalized in decades of anthropological writings. Povinelli (Reference Povinelli2002) offers a sustained and fascinating critique of how liberalism manages to cope, or not, whenever it encounters radical difference, or in the nineteenth-century terminology, “barbarism.” Darian-Smith and Fitzpatrick (Reference Darian-Smith and Fitzpatrick1999) tackle the same divide and probe its long-standing implications for the global legal order; see also Fitzpatrick Reference Fitzpatrick1992. Finally, for a compelling argument on new bankruptcy reforms and the birth of liberal ideology, see Joseph Reference Joseph and Creed2006.

10 Mill's redefinition of liberty during this era as not only an inalienable right, but also a core responsibility of the civilized is crucial here (see, e.g., Mill Reference Mill2004a: 84; also Berkowitz Reference Berkowitz and Eisenach1998); in this regard, his statements on debtors' prison reforms can be made to harmonize with his statements on self-governance in the colonies (see Mill Reference Mill2004a: 14). I thank the anonymous reviewers of this article for pointing out this crucial aspect of the barbarian/civilized divide, as discussed in this article.

11 Since Van Gennep (Reference Van Gennep1960), anthropology has a long tradition of probing rituals that create bounded spaces or times intentionally separate from everyday life (e.g., Bakhtin Reference Bakhtin and Iswolsky1968; Engelke Reference Engelke2007; Keane Reference Keane1997; Kaplan Reference Kaplan1995; Ortner Reference Ortner1978; Turner Reference Turner1967; Robbins Reference Robbins2004; Valeri Reference Valeri2000). Korobkin (Reference Korobkin2003) is a legal scholar who insightfully and fruitfully turns to the anthropological theory of ritual in order to provide a more sweeping history of insolvency regulation and remediation.

12 I have treated this issue extensively elsewhere (see Peebles Reference Peebles2010).

13 Hartman (Reference Hartman1997) provides a sustained and important discussion of the intermingling of bodies and money. Zelizer's work (e.g., Reference Zelizer2005) can also be turned to for some very illuminating cases of the potential bleeding between these categories, and the frequent desire to keep them separate. Guyer (Reference Guyer2004; Reference Guyer2010), Maurer (e.g., Reference Maurer2005; Reference Maurer2007; Reference Maurer2010), and Zaloom (Reference Zaloom2006) have all probed the related discourse concerning the segregation of quantity from quality, so often tied up, as Maurer specifically points out, with the mutual intertwining of bodies and money. See also Graeber's discussion of the body/soul divide and its relationship to money (2011: 243ff).

14 Foucault's text, which charts the rise of the modern penitentiary system, fails to mention anywhere within it the rapid simultaneous collapse of the debtors' prison complex. See Finn Reference Finn2003; and Joseph Reference Joseph and Creed2006. See also Garland (Reference Garland1990) for a deep study and helpful critique of Discipline and Punish.

15 Since the debtors' prison is all about money, a misunderstanding could arise here. He writes the word, “venial,” and not “venal.” The former is defined by the Oxford English Dictionary (2013) as, “Worthy or admitting of pardon, forgiveness, or remission; not grave or heinous; pardonable, light,” as well as, “Of an error or fault: That may be excused or overlooked; of a light, unimportant, or trivial nature; excusable.”

16 On the point that the debtors' prison incarnated a general system that criminalized poverty, see Johnson Reference Johnson1823.

17 Incidentally, after an impressive search through the archival evidence, Mann (Reference Mann2002: 223) finds that, at least in the American case, much of this common rhetoric concerning a scourge of fraudulent debtors was “essentially groundless.” But the frequent claims still persuaded people, and thus led to social action, which is critical for the story being told here.

18Ex parte” evidence is evidence heard in secret with the accused not allowed—and often not even notified—to respond in kind.

19 The ancient practice of branding the debtor should almost surely be seen as the prehistory of the credit rating agency. By way of this technique, the person is marked as not credit-worthy, for all to see. Korobkin (Reference Korobkin2003: 2135) asserts that, in torturing the physical body of the debtor, “the creditor on behalf of the society enacts a kind of remembering, marking the transgression by the maiming of the debtor's physical body.”

20 As emblematized so vividly by people such as J. H. Elliott (cited below) and Adam Smith, political economy of the day relied on this divide intimately, believing that parsimony stood as the core behavior necessary to a capitalist, and thus, a daily form of behavior that everyone should aspire to (e.g., Hirschman Reference Hirschman1997). Marx discusses this upstanding parsimonious behavior as a foundational myth of political economy in his chapter on “primitive accumulation” (Reference Marx and Fowkes1990). For similar debates from a different sphere of political economic debate, see Peebles (Reference Peebles2008) on how individual hoarding practices were similarly labeled barbaric and benighted. For a benchmark anthropological study that calls into question this supposed non-saving behavior on the part of non-capitalists, see Gudeman and Rivera Reference Gudeman and Rivera1990.

21 To be clear, Baden-Baden is one of the most famously luxurious spa towns in all of Europe.

22 The King's Bench and the Queen's Bench were the same prison. It was only a question of who was regent at the time.

23 By another legalistic trick that was much criticized, people who could afford good legal counsel only had to make a writ of Habeas Corpus in order to get remanded to the finer debtors' prisons.

24 The King's Bench, incidentally, contained multiple bars, restaurants, and coffee houses.

25 Here it can be helpful to turn to Day, Papataxiarchis, and Stewart (Reference Day, Papataxiarchis and Stewart1999), Sahlins (Reference Sahlins1972), and Woodburn (Reference Woodburn1982). Perhaps debtors found the inside of the jail a space of relative abundance because they had reduced the relatively more extravagant needs that they typically sought to satisfy outside the prison walls. Not desiring much translated into a higher degree of contentedness.

26 In most countries, prison officials were specifically enjoined from dictating debtors' daily activities, since the prison was de jure designed as merely a custodial holding pen so that debtors—whose guilt was still unproven—could not flee their debts. Thus, for example, in Scotland, “We have a hall where they can meet and read, and they are also allowed to play at draughts and chess…. Outside we have a little square where they play at 9 pins” (quoted in Haythornthwaite Reference Haythornthwaite1993: 30).

27 On this common rhetoric, see Pietz (Reference Pietz1997), Nietzsche (Reference Nietzsche and Golffing1956), and Simmel (Reference Simmel1978). Franzen gives us a very specific example from Middle Ages Sweden concerning the relationship between body parts and monetary values: One man who had committed a crime could choose between paying a fine of 40 marks or “losing his nose” (Reference Franzen1998: 182).

28 Due to an ancient English law that only allowed creditors to seize either the person or his “goods and chattel,” debtors could actually carry ready money into English prisons, for money was not considered to reside within these two categories. Indeed, one author reports that a prisoner was robbed of 1200 sovereigns of gold while in The Fleet prison (Fane Reference Fane1838c: 28).

29 Margot Finn (Reference Finn2003) has detailed this in exquisite form.

30 Seven years was not the outside limit of how long one could stay in a debtors' prison. One prisoner with a debt “which he vowed he would never pay” stayed for thirty-eight years (anonymous 1823: 16).

31 Other rituals attended to the process of whitewashing, and not all of them revolved around legal arcana. Upon a successful petition through the Insolvent Debtors' Court, we are informed that the newly cleansed debtor “is shouldered by half a dozen, and carried around the yard, whist the whole body of the prisoners follow, cheering lustily, until they reach the first gate” (H. [anonymous] 1859: 45).

32 To be sure, some prisoners could not get out and did not stay by choice, especially prior to specific reforms of the nineteenth century that facilitated “whitewashing.” But the evidence shows that a significant number of people, both poor and wealthy, actively chose to stay rather than meet their debts and seek release, so we must also probe this phenomenon.

33 Another notorious zone of banishment for insolvency beckoned for the very poorest members of society: the workhouse, wherein the attempt to “civilize” the lower classes via new forms of bodily discipline was far more transparent than anything afoot in the debate over the debtors' prison. Describing the workhouse's demise, which occurred during these same years, is outside the scope of this paper, but in tandem, both reform efforts reveal two related nineteenth-century trends: (1) the gradual attempt to decriminalize poverty, and (2) aiming to do so by “civilizing” the lower classes.

34 People with enough money could rent out rooms inside The Rules, thereby freeing up space inside the prison proper for additional debtors.

35 Similarly, day-passes to leave the prison and even its Rules were common in many countries, and were dubbed “liberty tickets” in England (Dixon Reference Dixon1850: 114–15).

36 Mann writes, “The lists of Virginia debtors compiled for British creditors after the Revolution to assist them in collecting pre-war debts under the terms of the peace treaty recorded that debtor after debtor had ‘gone to Kentucke’ or, even more tellingly, was ‘presumed gone to Kentucke,’ as though the mere fact of a debtor's absence created a presumption of flight across the mountains … ‘the Debtors will be gone to Kentucke very soon and good bye to all their Debts due here.’ By uprooting their families and moving to distant places, they were trying to create the fresh start in life that would have been theirs had there been a bankruptcy law in force [in Revolutionary America] to discharge their debts. Since there was not, they substituted distance for discharge” (2002: 128–29).

37 In many countries today, people filing for bankruptcy must forfeit their passports, precisely in order to eliminate the creditors' fear that the debtor represents a flight risk.

References

REFERENCES

Anonymous. 1823. A Description of the King's Bench Prison; Being a Brief Review of Its Constitution; the Prison Itself; the Rules Thereof; the Day Rules; the Orders and Regulations of the Court; And Containing All Such Other Matter as Is Material to Be Known to All Persons in Custody of the Marshal. London: John McShee.Google Scholar
Anonymous. 1829. Gäldstugan, eller Desz Hemligheter, Hemtade ur Desz Uråldriga Arkiver. Stockholm: M. G. Lundberg.Google Scholar
Anonymous. 1837. A Letter to Her Most Gracious Majesty, Shewing the Cruelty and Inutility of the System of Arrest for Debt. London: Whittaker & Co.Google Scholar
Bakhtin, Mikhail. 1968. Rabelais and His World. Iswolsky, Helene, trans. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Balleisen, Edward J. 2001. Navigating Failure: Bankruptcy and Commercial Society in Antebellum America. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Beccaria, Cesare. 1995. On Crimes and Punishments and other Writings. Bellamy, R., ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy. 1843. The Works of Jeremy Bentham. Vol. 6. Published under the superintendence of his executor, John Bowring. Edinburgh: William Tait.Google Scholar
Berkowitz, Peter. 1998. Mill: Liberty, Virtue, and the Discipline of Individuality. In Eisenach, Eldon J., ed., Mill and the Moral Character of Liberalism. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
Committee of Merchants and Traders of the City of London. 1851. Replies from Foreign Countries to Questions Relating to the Law of Debtor and Creditor and to the Law of Partnership. London: W. Clowes and Sons.Google Scholar
Darian-Smith, Eve and Fitzpatrick, Peter, eds. 1999. Laws of the Postcolonial. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
Day, Sophie, Papataxiarchis, Evthymios, and Stewart, Michael, eds. 1999. Lilies of the Field. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Dirks, Nicholas. 2001. Castes of Mind: Colonialism and the Making of Modern India. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dixon, Hepworth. 1850. The London Prisons. London: Jackson and Walford.Google Scholar
Duffy, Ian. 1985. Bankruptcy and Insolvency in London during the Industrial Revolution. New York: Garland Publishing.Google Scholar
Elias, Norbert. 2000. The Civilizing Process: Sociogenetic and Psychogenetic Investigations. Jephcott, E., trans. Rev. ed.Malden, Mass.: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Elliott, J. H. 1838. A Remonstrance Addressed to the Right Hon. Lord Brougham, on the Injustice and Impolicy of the Proposed Bill for the Abolition of Imprisonment for Debt. London: Joseph Thomas. [N.B., This text is also known commonly as “Credit, The Life of Commerce.”]Google Scholar
Engelke, Matthew. 2007. A Problem of Presence: Beyond Scripture in an African Church. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Fane, C., Esq. 1838a. Bankruptcy Reform: In a Series of Letters Addressed to Sir Robert Peel, Bart. Letters I, II, III. London: S. Sweet, Law Bookseller and Publisher.Google Scholar
Fane, C., Esq. 1838b. Bankruptcy Reform: In a Series of Letters Addressed to Sir Robert Peel, Bart. Letters IV, V, VI, VII. London: S. Sweet, Law Bookseller and Publisher.Google Scholar
Fane, C., Esq. 1838c. Observations on the Proposed Abolition of Imprisonment for Debt on Mesne Process; Shewing Its Probable Effects in Disabling Creditors from Forcing Their Debtors into Bankruptcy, Trust-deeds, or Compositions. London: S. Sweet, Law Bookseller and Publisher.Google Scholar
Farley, Edward, Esq. 1788. Imprisonment for Debt Unconstitutional and Oppressive, Proved from the Fundamental Principles of the British Constitution, and the Rights of Nature. London: T. Hookham.Google Scholar
Field, Reverend J. 1848. Prison Discipline; and the Advantages of the Separate System of Imprisonment with a Detailed Account of the Discipline now Pursued in the New Country Gaol at Reading. London: Longman, Brown, Green, and Longman.Google Scholar
Finn, Margot. 2003. The Character of Credit: Personal Debt in English Culture, 1740–1914. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Fitzpatrick, Peter. 1992. The Mythology of Modern Law. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Sheridan, Alan, trans. New York: Vintage.Google Scholar
Franzen, Bo. 1998. Sturetidens Monetära System: Pant eller Penningar som Information i Köpstaden Arboga. Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell International.Google Scholar
Frykman, Jonas and Löfgren, Orvar. 1996. Culture Builders: A Historical Anthropology of Middle-Class Life. New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
Garland, David. 1990. Punishment and Modern Society: A Study in Social Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Graeber, David. 2011. Debt: The First 5,000 Years. Brooklyn, N.Y.: Melville House.Google Scholar
Gudeman, Stephen and Rivera, Alberto. 1990. Conversations in Colombia: The Domestic Economy in Life and Text. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Jane. 2004. Marginal Gains: Monetary Transactions in Atlantic Africa. Chicago: University Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, Jane. 2010. The Eruption of Tradition? On Ordinality and Calculation. Anthropological Theory 10, 1: 19.Google Scholar
H. [anonymous]. 1859. Prison Reminiscences; or Whitecross Street, and the Law of Imprisonment for Debt, with Facts Showing Its Cruelty and Impolicy. London: A. W. Bennett.Google Scholar
Hardouin, Henri. 1874. Essai Sur L'abolition de la Contrainte par Corps. Paris: Cosse, Marchal et Billard.Google Scholar
Hartman, Saidiya V. 1997. Scenes of Subjection: Terror, Slavery, and Self-Making in Nineteenth-Century America. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hautcoeur, Pierre-Cyrille. 2008. La statistique et la lutte contre la contrainte par corps. L'apport de Jean-Baptiste Bayle-Mouillard. Histoire et Mesure 23, 1: 167–89.Google Scholar
Haythornthwaite, J. A. 1993. Scotland in the Nineteenth Century: An Analytical Bibliography of Material Relating to Scotland in Parliamentary Papers, 1800–1900. Aldershot: Scolar Press.Google Scholar
Herzfeld, Michael. 1987. Anthropology Through the Looking-Glass: Critical Ethnography in the Margins of Europe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Herzfeld, Michael. 2002. The Absent Presence: Discourses of Crypto-Colonialism. South Atlantic Quarterly 101, 4: 899926.Google Scholar
Hicks, George Montagu. 1858. The Double Doom of the Poor Debtor, by the Governor of the Debtors' Prison for London and Middlesex, Whitecross-Street. London: Richardson Brothers.Google Scholar
Hilton, Boyd. 1988. The Age of Atonement: The Impact of Evangelicalism on Social and Economic Thought 1795–1865. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hirschman, Albert. 1997. The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism before Its Triumph. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, Richard. M. 1823. Speech of Col. Richard M. Johnson of Kentucky, on a Proposition to Abolish Imprisonment for Debt, Submitted by Him to the Senate of the United States, January 14th, 1823. Boston: Society for the Relief of the Distressed.Google Scholar
Joseph, Miranda. 2006. A Debt to Society. In Creed, Gerald, ed., Seductions of Community: Emancipations, Oppressions, Quandaries. Santa Fe, N.M.: School for Advanced Research Press.Google Scholar
Kaplan, Martha. 1995. Neither Cargo nor Cult. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Keane, Webb. 1997. Signs of Recognition. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Korobkin, Donald R. 2003. Bankruptcy Law, Ritual, and Performance. Columbia Law Review 103, 8: 2124–59.Google Scholar
Lester, V. Markham. 1995. Victorian Insolvency: Bankruptcy, Imprisonment for Debt, and Company Winding-Up in Nineteenth-Century England. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mann, Bruce. 2002. Republic of Debtors: Bankruptcy in the Age of American Independence. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Marx, Karl. 1990. Capital, Volume I. Fowkes, Ben, trans. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
Maurer, Bill. 2005. Due Diligence and ‘Reasonable Man,’ Offshore. Cultural Anthropology 20, 4: 474505.Google Scholar
Maurer, Bill. 2007. Incalculable Payments: Money, Scale, and the South African Offshore Grey Money Amnesty. African Studies Review 50, 2: 125–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maurer, Bill. 2010. Finger Counting Money. Anthropological Theory 10, 1–2: 179–85.Google Scholar
Merry, Sally Engle. 2000. Colonizing Hawaìi: The Cultural Power of Law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 2004a [1859]. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume XIX: Essays on Politics and Society, Part II. Indianapolis, Ind.: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Mill, John Stuart. 2004b [1848]. Principles of Political Economy. Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Neild, James, Esq. 1808. An Account of the Rise, Progress, and Present State of the Society for the Discharge and Relief of Persons Imprisoned for Small Debts throughout England and Wales. London: John Nichols & Sons.Google Scholar
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1956. The Birth of Tragedy and the Genealogy of Morals. Golffing, F., trans. New York: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Nordisk Familjebok. 1905. Bysättning. Stockholm: Nordisk Familjeboks Förlag.Google Scholar
Nutz, Thomas. 2005. Global Networks and Local Prison Reforms: Monarchs, Bureaucrats and Penological Experts in Early Nineteenth-Century Prussia. German History 23, 4: 431–58.Google Scholar
Ortner, Sherry. 1978. Sherpas through Their Rituals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Oxford English Dictionary Online. 2013. Oxford University Press; at: http://www.oed.com.libproxy.newschool.edu/search?searchType=dictionary&q=venial&_searchBtn=Search (accessed 19 Apr.).Google Scholar
Peebles, Gustav. 2008. Inverting the Panopticon: Money and the Nationalization of the Future. Public Culture 20, 2: 233–65.Google Scholar
Peebles, Gustav. 2010. The Anthropology of Credit and Debt. Annual Review of Anthropology 39: 225–40.Google Scholar
Pietz, William. 1997. Death of the Deodand: Accursed Objects and the Money Value of Human Life. Res 31: 97108.Google Scholar
Povinelli, Elizabeth. 2002. The Cunning of Recognition. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Robbins, Joel. 2004. Becoming Sinners: Christianity and Moral Torment in a Papua New Guinea Society. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Sahlins, Marshall. 1972. Stone Age Economics. New York: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Sandage, Scott. 2005. Born Losers: A History of Failure in America. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Simmel, Georg. 1978. The Philosophy of Money. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Stoler, Ann. 1995. Race and the Education of Desire: Foucault's History of Sexuality and the Colonial Order of Things. Durham: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Stoler, Ann. 2002. Carnal Knowledge and Imperial Power: Race and the Intimate in Colonial Rule. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Turner, Victor. 1967. The Forest of Symbols: Aspects of Ndembu Ritual. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Valeri, Valerio. 2000. The Forest of Taboos: Morality, Hunting, and Identity among the Huaulu of the Moluccas. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
Van Gennep, Arnold. 1960. The Rites of Passage. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Vanhulle, Bert. 2010. Dreaming about the Prison: Edouard Ducpetiaux and Prison Reform in Belgium (1830–1848). Crime, Histoire & Societies 14, 2: 107–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weber, Max. 1958. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.Google Scholar
Wennerlind, Carl. 2011. Casualties of Credit: The English Financial Revolution, 1620–1720. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Woodburn, James. 1982. Egalitarian Societies. Man 17, 3: 431–51.Google Scholar
Wordsworth, William. 1831. Observations on the Law of Arrest; Shewing Its Impolicy, and How It May Be, and Is, Abused. London: A. Maxwell.Google Scholar
Zaloom, Caitlin. 2006. Out of the Pits. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Zelizer, Viviana. 2005. The Purchase of Intimacy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Image 1. Enforced leisure at the King's Bench, with people playing squash and strolling in their Sunday finest, all while behind the barbed wired wall to the left.

Figure 1

Image 2. The “Rules” of the King's Bench in 1830, with the prison in the middle-left section of the map, and the Rules marked by the dotted line.