In or around 204 b.c.e,Footnote 1 the Romans sent an expedition to Asia Minor. The ambassadors brought back a stone that had fallen from the sky and was regarded by the Romans as an embodiment of the Magna Mater.Footnote 2 The Senate chose Publius Cornelius Scipio Nasica (cos. 191) to be the uir optimus who was required to welcome the new goddess. At Ostia, Nasica, along with Claudia Quinta, was to receive the Magna Mater before she was installed in her new temple on the Palatine Hill.
Over the last century, the arrival of the Phrygian goddess and her cult has provoked much scholarly interest and debate, primarily focussed on its significance for the religious and political landscapes of third-century Rome.Footnote 3 This article, by contrast, will conduct a literary critical analysis of this episode across different Latin texts, and in particular the meaning ascribed to Scipio Nasica's selection as uir optimus.Footnote 4 The reason for the Senate's choice of Nasica was unclear even to historians working in antiquity. Instead, Nasica the uir optimus came to embody a range of different but related virtues across the Graeco-Roman literary world.
In what follows I shall chart the moments in which the exemplarity of Scipio Nasica undergoes a change in meaning, with particular focus on how these shifts are constructed in the narrative system of Livy's Ab urbe condita and Augustine's De ciuitate Dei. At Ab urbe condita 29.14, Livy uses Scipio Nasica's reception of the Magna Mater to reflect upon exemplarity, contemporary mythmaking and the tenuousness of the relationship between past and present. Augustine likewise produces a reading of Scipio Nasica which calls for re-evaluation of Nasica as an exemplum through an extended comparison of Republican and late antique cultural mores.
In so doing, both Ab urbe condita and De ciuitate Dei foreground their awareness of the fluidity of cultural memory, a Roman self-consciousness which has captured the attention of recent scholarship on exempla in the Roman world.Footnote 5 The 2018 monograph of Rebecca Langlands in particular has convincingly shown that exemplary discourse from the first century b.c.e to the first century c.e. assigns many different meanings to its moral models and does not consistently portray them as embodiments of contemporary Roman values. To explore in full the pay-off of this approach to Roman exempla, however, its chronological scope must be widened. Incorporating the inherent dynamism of exemplarity into our understanding of ‘later’ Latin texts brings to light important points of resemblance between classical and late antique treatments of exemplary figures. Indeed, close study of Scipio Nasica reveals that Augustine's use of exempla to expose a rupture between past and present is not simply the result of Christian repurposing of earlier rhetorical practices, as believed by previous scholarship.Footnote 6 Instead, my treatment of Nasica illustrates in microcosm a larger phenomenon at work in De ciuitate Dei—namely, that Augustine's supposedly innovative refashioning of classical exempla to fit a late antique context suggests continuities with classical exemplary discourse, which likewise highlights the gap between the moral paradigms of the past and present mores. In both Livy and Augustine, thoughts on the problems with Nasica as an exemplum accompany the descriptions of his selection as uir optimus.
SECTION 1: THE IDENTITY (ANCIENT AND MODERN) OF SCIPIO NASICA
As with many of the figures who are at the forefront of ancient exemplary discourse, the historical Scipio Nasica is shrouded by legend. Unlike the case of some exemplary actors from the earliest days of the Republic, however, modern scholars can securely identify the name with a historical figure. For a member of the Roman elite, Nasica lived a life of relative obscurity, aside from his selection to help introduce the Magna Mater to Rome.Footnote 7
The ancient authors who discuss Nasica, on the other hand, are less certain about his identity than twentieth- and twenty-first-century scholarship. The surviving sources on Nasica, eager to attribute to him notable deeds beyond the reception of the Magna Mater, often conflate this Scipio Nasica with his son, Publius Cornelius Scipio Nasica Corculum (cos. 162, 155), and with his grandson, Publius Cornelius Scipio Nasica Serapio (cos. 138). Some such conflations, namely of Nasica with Nasica Serapio, complicate Nasica's exemplarity, as they note his selection by the Senate together with Nasica Serapio's electoral defeat for the aedileship in his youth.Footnote 8 This lack of consensus on the exact qualities which secured Nasica the honour of uir optimus indicates confusion on the nature of his achievements.Footnote 9 Thus, although it is chronologically possible that the prototypical Scipio Nasica and Nasica Corculum were the same individual and not father and son, the sources are not consistent enough to allow for such a conclusion.Footnote 10 This article will therefore adopt the approach taken by modern historians, and refer to Scipio Nasica and Nasica Corculum as two different men.
Uncertainty over the identity of Nasica aside, the significance of the Senate's pronouncement in 204 b.c.e. has proven obscure to ancient and modern scholars alike. Scipio Nasica appears to be the only figure to have been named a uir optimus by the Senate.Footnote 11 The closest parallels for the honour, moreover, reveal an intriguing but vague image of the (self-)presentation of the Scipionic familia. The comparandum most contemporary with Nasica is the epitaph of Lucius Cornelius Scipio (cos. 259), which offers an encomiastic description of its dedicatee as an optumo uiro.Footnote 12 In a slightly more sarcastic and chronologically later context, Appian refers to Scipio Nasica Serapio, who has just stormed the Capitol to confront Tiberius Gracchus, as ἀνὴρ ἄριστος, thereby simultaneously recalling the illustrious repute of Serapio's grandfather as ἄριστος while contrasting Serapio's violence with Nasica's more peaceful reception of the Magna Mater.Footnote 13 Whether employed for praise or subtle criticism, the honorary epithet seems to have close ties to the Scipiones and their prominence amongst the aristocracy during the third and second centuries b.c.e.Footnote 14 As the epitaph of Lucius Cornelius Scipio suggests, it may originally have played a role in a larger rivalry with Lucius Scipio's contemporary Atilius Caiatinus, whose own funerary inscription claimed him to be primarius.Footnote 15 Beyond these general outlines, however, it is not possible to draw further connections between the men each of whom was referred to as uir optimus.Footnote 16 Indeed, Livy's account sheds little additional light on this larger family portrait, as the sections discussing Lucius Cornelius Scipio and Scipio Nasica Serapio are lost, and he does not make any further references to a uir optimus or an optimus uir outside of his discussion of Nasica's selection.Footnote 17
Finally, neither the immediate context of Nasica's selection itself nor the cultural milieu of the earliest attestations of Nasica proves fruitful for gaining further clarity. Although the exhortation to the Romans in 204 b.c.e. to choose a uir optimus is usually reported as coming from a Greek source,Footnote 18 attempts to understand uir optimus as a mere translation of, and thus deriving its meaning from, the Greek ἄριστος ἀνήρ have generally been rejected.Footnote 19 On the other hand, the first extant references to Nasica's selection come from the first century b.c.e., a period in which the phrase uir optimus had a wide variety of meanings, thereby creating ambiguity as to what meaning it may have had for authors such as Livy and for their audiences. Within the corpus of Cicero alone, uir optimus can be a term simply denoting the Roman elite, as it is in a number of his speeches, or a description of the ideal, almost divine ruler, as used in the De re publica.Footnote 20
SECTION 2: LIVY AND NASICA THE UNKNOWN
The mystery surrounding the Senate's choice of Nasica is reflected in Ab urbe condita Book 29, where Livy pauses for a series of meta-reflections on exempla and on the gap between past and present. At the very outset of the rituals which introduced the Magna Mater to Rome, Livy describes Scipio Nasica's selection as uir optimus (29.14.9–10):
P. Scipionem Cn. f. eius, qui in Hispania ceciderat, adulescentem nondum quaestorium, iudicauerunt in tota ciuitate uirum bonorum optimum esse. id quibus uirtutibus inducti ita iudicarint, sicut traditum a proximis memoriae temporum illorum scriptoribus libens posteris traderem, ita meas opiniones coniectando rem uetustate obrutam non interponam.Footnote 21
Livy's confession of uncertainty about the reasons for the Senate's selection constitutes the only commentary on the qualities which may have won Nasica the distinction. Despite two subsequent mentions, one by the authorial persona and one by Nasica himself in indirect discourse, that the selection exceeds any other political honour, neither of these discussions gives a reason for the desirability of Nasica's nomination.Footnote 22 Such a refusal to shed light on the motivations for the selection produces significant literary effects. While Livy acknowledges that exempla can fade from Roman cultural memory, he admits to the incompleteness of his information in only one other exemplary narrative.Footnote 23 When tracing the injustices suffered by the virtuous Verginia, the historian explains that he will relate the decision, but not the actual speech, which pronounced her the property of the predatory Appius Claudius owing to the inaccuracy of the written accounts.Footnote 24 Livy's aside on Nasica likewise breaks the narrative flow to authenticate the credibility of his project. Livy as historian will not invent reasons in order to provide a continuous narrative, but rather will accurately report the information as handed down by the sources closest to the period on which he reports.Footnote 25
In advertising the caution (and thus authenticity) of his work, Livy implicitly places himself in opposition to other traditions which embellish the tale of Scipio Nasica. Indeed, when read alongside the commentary on Nasica's commendable qualities provided by roughly contemporary authors, Livy's claim that he lacks adequate source material sets his work apart.Footnote 26 Whereas Diodorus Siculus notes Nasica's piety and wisdom, Cicero his dignitas, Valerius Maximus his holiness, and Silius Italicus his illustrious lineage,Footnote 27 Livy lingers on the difficulty of the historiographical tradition and does not provide further explanation for the selection in his later, passing references to Nasica's role in the arrival of the Magna Mater at Rome.Footnote 28 His assertion at 29.14.9 that Nasica's exceptional traits have not been handed down proximis memoriae temporum illorum scriptoribus twice uses the verb tradere, a verb associated with attempts to review the historiographical tradition at large in the Ab urbe condita,Footnote 29 and thereby hints at later interpolations from which Livy must distinguish historical truth. Moreover, Nasica's story is from the very outset surrounded by authorial scepticism. As Livy recounts, Nasica's selection to welcome the Magna Mater is the product of a more general interest in the arrival of the Magna Mater in order to expiate the prodigies of 204, which Livy believes were engendered by superstitio.Footnote 30 The connection between Nasica's honour and prodigies of questionable credibility further supports the presence of an underlying critical attitude towards Nasica's narrative. In short, the possibility emerges that Livy is responding to Late Republican and Early Imperial literary treatments of the events of 204 b.c.e.Footnote 31
This possibility is further strengthened by verbal echoes of the wording of the Preface. At the opening of his work, Livy is dismissive of new attempts to write history, claiming that ‘clever attempts to compete’ with antiquity, uetustas, are the very reason his topic has been vulgarized.Footnote 32 In Book 29 the authorial persona likewise sets himself in contrast to the practice of modifying uetustas. This reaffirmation of Livy's approach to uetustas marks the aside in Book 29 as part of a larger project of authorial self-positioning within the historiographical and literary traditions.Footnote 33
When he includes Scipio Nasica's selection as uir optimus, Livy invokes a nexus of concepts laden with paradigms for moral behaviour.Footnote 34 The exemplum of Nasica, however, is redirected to launch a unique, self-conscious criticism of contemporary mythmaking. In the whole of the Ab urbe condita, the selection of Scipio Nasica is the only exemplary narrative to highlight the distance between the content of Livy's history and Livy's present day through an emphasis on the unattainability of knowledge about the subject at hand.Footnote 35 While the circulation of Scipio Nasica's deeds in forms other than Livy's history may have mitigated the apparent remoteness of this episode for a contemporary audience,Footnote 36 Livy's description places the virtues of Scipio Nasica in a past that is irrecoverable within his Augustan present.
SECTION 3: AUGUSTINE'S REPUBLICAN EXEGESIS
In contrast to many of the authors referring to Scipio Nasica, who tend to mention him only very briefly, Augustine shares with Livy this deeper interest in and engagement with the significance of Nasica and his reception of the Magna Mater at Rome. Like many classical exempla in De ciuitate Dei, Augustine thinks critically about Nasica across the course of several chapters (from the end of Book 1 to the beginning of Book 2), examining him from a variety of different, even slightly conflicting, angles.Footnote 37 In each of his appearances, Nasica is moulded by Augustine in the image of his own concerns about historical change, luxury and spectacle.
The interaction with Nasica begins at De ciu. D. 1.30, in a diatribe which criticizes the luxury of Augustine's contemporary non-Christians with language of decline borrowed from Sallust's depiction of Rome at the end of the Third Punic War (1.30):Footnote 38
si Nasica ille Scipio uester quondam pontifex uiueret, quem sub terrore belli Punici in suscipiendis Phrygiis sacris, cum uir optimus quaereretur, uniuersus senatus elegit, cuius os fortasse non auderetis aspicere, ipse uos ab hac inpudentia cohiberet. cur enim adflicti rebus aduersis de temporibus querimini Christianis, nisi quia uestram luxuriam cupitis habere securam et perditissimis moribus remota omni molestiarum asperitate diffluere? neque enim propterea cupitis habere pacem et omni genere copiarum abundare, ut his bonis honeste utamini, hoc est modeste sobrie, temperanter pie, sed ut infinita uarietas uoluptatum insanis effusionibus exquiratur, secundisque rebus ea mala oriantur in moribus quae saeuientibus peiora sunt hostibus. at ille Scipio pontifex maximus uester, ille iudicio totius senatus uir optimus, istam uobis metuens calamitatem nolebat aemulam tunc imperii Romani Carthaginem dirui et decernenti ut dirueretur contradicebat Catoni, timens infirmis animis hostem securitatem et tamquam pupillis ciuibus idoneum tutorem necessarium uidens esse terrorem.Footnote 39
Augustine uses a slightly different strand of the tradition than does Livy, attributing the achievements of Scipio Nasica Corculum and Scipio Nasica to the same Nasica.Footnote 40 Like Diodorus Siculus, Augustine gives Nasica's rebuttal against Cato's efforts to destroy Carthage as a reason for his selection as uir optimus.Footnote 41 Augustine thus inscribes Nasica within a discourse of exemplarity familiar to pre-Christian Roman literature, while painting a picture of Scipio Nasica in which his status as uir optimus is consistently juxtaposed with, and thereby linked to, what Augustine believes were his views on moderation and restraint.
This opening of Augustine's engagement with Nasica is suffused with multiple layers of significance. The emphasis on Nasica's involvement with the Magna Mater at the very start of De ciu. D. 1.30 follows upon a vivid description of the worldliness, and hence inferiority, of traditional Roman gods.Footnote 42 Augustine's notional Nasica therefore illustrates the severity of the Roman decline into luxury—even a critic whose interaction with the Magna Mater involved him with an inherently problematic polytheistic theology would recognize the shamefulness of the behaviour in fifth-century Rome. Using Nasica to critique Roman immorality, however, also sheds light on a series of similarities between late antique and Republican moralists.Footnote 43 Like Nasica, Augustine too fears for the integrity of Roman moderation in the face of the luxurious inclinations of his contemporaries.
The two chapters which follow present more correspondences between the rhetoric of the two men. At De ciu. D. 1.32, Augustine is spurred to a diatribe against the popularity of theatrical spectacle which both echoes in sentiment and improves upon the rejection of dramatic performance by Nasica. As we shall see in more detail later, Augustine establishes important differences between his own views on the theatre and Nasica's.Footnote 44 Nevertheless, the description of the Republican senator's wise concern for his fatherland (hac prouidentissima patriae caritate) and of his distinguished speech (oratione grauissima) against building a permanent theatre in Rome also reveals an admiration for Nasica's arguments.Footnote 45
The ethical standards of Augustine and Nasica converge even further at the beginning of Book 2, where Nasica is resurrected in a manner almost recalling prosopopoeia (De ciu. D. 2.5):
nequaquam istos, qui flagitiosissimae consuetudinis uitiis oblectari magis quam obluctari student, sed illum ipsum Nasicam Scipionem, qui uir optimus a senatu electus est, cuius manibus eiusdem daemonis simulacrum susceptum est in Vrbemque peruectum, habere de hac re iudicem uellem. diceret nobis, utrum matrem suam tam optime de re publica uellet mereri, ut ei diuini honores decernerentur; sicut et Graecos et Romanos aliasque gentes constat quibusdam decreuisse mortalibus, quorum erga se beneficia magnipenderant, eosque inmortales factos atque in deorum numerum receptos esse crediderant. profecto ille tantam felicitatem suae matri, si fieri posset, optaret. porro si ab illo deinde quaereremus, utrum inter eius diuinos honores uellet illa turpia celebrari: nonne se malle clamaret, ut sua mater sine ullo sensu mortua iaceret, quam ad hoc dea uiueret, ut illa libenter audiret?Footnote 46
Augustine renders Nasica the judge over the worship of the Magna Mater and suggests posing him questions. Scipio Nasica, in turn, ‘responds’ to Augustine's queries, in indirect speech, diceret nobis. The ventriloquism of Nasica's opinion on religious spectacle highlights the relevance of the Republican moralist and his values to late antique theological debates. Scipio Nasica sets a classical precedent for Augustine's critique of theatrical luxury, thereby placing Augustine's newer, Christian moral code in continuity with the principles of the Republican maiores.Footnote 47
Augustine's imagined Nasica offers more than a model of rhetoric on restraint. When Augustine mentions Scipio Nasica's conveyance of the Magna Mater to Rome, he cites an event in which accepting a new god into Rome is tied to Roman victory after traumatic attacks on Italian soil.Footnote 48 Including the Magna Mater episode in Nasica's accomplishments allows Augustine to underscore the central thesis of Books 1 and 2—namely, that the introduction of new gods does not incur political disasters and hardship at Rome. As a result, the Republican past both surfaces as a parallel for Augustine's interpretation of his (to us, late antique) present, and subtly furthers the argument for a lack of causality between the Roman adoption of Christianity and the invasion of Rome by the Goths.
However, Augustine does not forge connections between Nasica's exemplary behaviour and his own conservative rhetoric without qualification. After praising him in 1.30, Augustine's tone changes in the next paragraph, where he lays out in detail what he sees as the Republican youth's principal shortcoming (De ciu. D. 1.31):
quanto studio iste ab urbe Roma ludos ipsos scaenicos abstulisset, si auctoritati eorum, quos deos putabat, resistere auderet, quos esse noxios daemones non intellegebat aut, si intellegebat, placandos etiam ipse potius quam contemnendos existimabat! nondum enim fuerat declarata gentibus superna doctrina, quae fide cor mundans ad caelestia uel supercaelestia capessenda humili pietate humanum mutaret affectum et a dominatu superborum daemonum liberaret.Footnote 49
According to Augustine, Nasica's imperfections result from the inherently partial metaphysical view afforded by traditional Roman religion. The inability to remove dramatic performance altogether is depicted as a pagan failing, from which Christians are freed through their knowledge that theatrical spectacle is nothing but honour rendered to superbi daemones. As an incomplete shadow of Christian virtue, Nasica cannot be an unquestionable exemplar, but rather serves as an admirable yet flawed foil to the superior set of Christian ethics advocated by De ciuitate Dei.Footnote 50
Nasica's participation in Roman religious ritual likewise becomes the primary object of Augustine's criticism in Book 2. He writes (De ciu. D. 2.5):
proinde talis mater deum, qualem habere matrem puderet quemlibet etiam pessimum uirum, Romanas occupatura mentes quaesiuit optimum uirum, non quem monendo et adiuuando faceret, sed quem fallendo deciperet, ei similis de qua scriptum est: mulier autem uirorum pretiosas animas captat, ut ille magnae indolis animus hoc uelut diuino testimonio sublimatus et uere se optimum existimans ueram pietatem religionemque non quaereret, sine qua omne quamuis laudabile ingenium superbia uanescit et decidit.Footnote 51
Augustine's shift in emphasis from Nasica's attitude towards luxury to his religious scruples qualifies his earlier praise of Nasica's exemplarity. Instead of the uir optimus, who is praiseworthy for his ascetic tendencies, and possibly even acts as a forerunner for Augustine's own religious project, Nasica becomes the uir optimus whose involvement with the Magna Mater prevents him from attaining true virtue. Despite his laudable qualities, he does not practise pietas or religio and thus perishes as a result of his own pride.Footnote 52
In inserting the Republican moralist into this Christian teleology, Augustine also grounds his diatribe in a discourse familiar to classical exemplarity—namely, that of examining an exemplum from many different, including critical, angles. His distinction between his own theology and that of Nasica brings to light the problems in using Nasica as a model. Like Livy, Augustine uses Nasica's introduction of the Magna Mater to Rome to indicate a disjuncture between two eras, in his case the classical past and the Christian present.
The connections between Augustine's rhetoric and classical paradigms of exemplarity come into even sharper focus in Book 5 of De ciuitate Dei. In his effort to represent pre-Christian Rome as the earthly (but imperfect) counterpart of the Christian city in heaven, Augustine argues that even Virgil saw Roman exempla as more complex than mere models of virtue, since the poet referred in Aeneid Book 6 to the pain and loss suffered by Brutus after murdering his children.Footnote 53 Although Augustine is careful to note that Virgil's description of Brutus provides a justification for his actions—love of the patria and glory—an argument to which Augustine's portrayal will not subscribe, his invocation of Virgil's Brutus nevertheless serves as proof for the argument of the De ciuitate Dei itself about the problematic nature of traditional Roman heroes. In so doing, De ciu. D. 5.18 points to the precedent for its reading of classical exempla as imperfect and complicated.
CONCLUDING THOUGHTS
To conclude, both Augustine and Livy introduce a Scipio Nasica whom they present as a possible moral exemplum. Livy's description of Scipio Nasica's selection as uir optimus suggests that Nasica may have been a model of virtue. Livy, however, refuses to expatiate on the notional exemplary qualities of Scipio Nasica, highlighting instead his own caution towards relying upon sources that are at a chronological distance from the events they narrate.
Augustine's De ciuitate Dei engages in more profound ways with exemplary discourse than does Ab urbe condita Book 29. He elucidates the Senate's preference for Scipio Nasica by pointing to the invective against luxury and security traditionally attributed to his son Corculum. Although this Scipio Nasica affords a series of compelling parallels between Augustine's imagined Roman Republican past and his own (late antique) Roman present, Augustine complicates his portrayal of Nasica by denouncing Nasica's belief in the ‘wrong’ gods. Just as in Ab urbe condita, De ciuitate Dei uses the character of Scipio Nasica to reveal an unbridgeable gap between past and present.
The tale of Scipio Nasica in Livy and Augustine demonstrates a continued interest in thinking with and about the difficulties of applying classical models of exemplarity from the Early Empire to Late Antiquity. Such continuities between Augustine's and Livy's thought and narrative strategies tell only one side of a multifaceted story, for the projects of Augustine and Livy differ in significant ways. Livy's concerns focus primarily on the historical veracity (or lack thereof) of exemplary discourse and the narratives it generates, whereas Augustine's engagement with Nasica is rooted in a series of ethical concerns about the moral weight of virtue in a non-Christian world. By highlighting the similarities in approach and outlook on the relationship between past and present in Livy and Augustine, I hope to have laid the foundations for charting a more nuanced understanding of those aspects of late antique exemplary rhetoric, which appreciates in full the fraught classical heritage of its portraits of pre-Christian figures.