Why study the history of modern German-speaking Central Europe? If pressed to answer this question fifty years ago, a Germanist would likely have said something to the effect that one studies modern German history to trace the “German” origins of Nazism, with the broader aim of understanding authoritarianism.Footnote 1 While the problem of authoritarianism clearly remains relevant to this day, the nation-state-centered approach to understanding it has waned, especially in light of the recent shift toward transnational and global history. The following essay focuses on the issue of authoritarianism, asking whether the study of German history is still relevant to authoritarianism. It begins with a review of two conventional approaches to understanding authoritarianism in modern German history, and then thinks about it in a different way through G. W. F. Hegel in an effort to demonstrate the vibrancy of German intellectual history for exploring significant and global issues such as authoritarianism.
Hegel’s discussion of recognition in The Phenomenology of Spirit (1807) identified the central bulwark of authoritarianism in the social interaction between master and slave. This intersubjective interaction is governed, he claimed, by the problem of recognition, specifically, the desire to be recognized as possessing authority over another and the desire to recognize someone as possessing such authority. The twin, self-interested desires to be obeyed and to obey form the basis of any relationship of domination. While others had already made this point––above all, Jean-Jacques Rousseau in Discourse on the Origin and Basis of Inequality Among Men (1775)––Hegel analyzed it with unmatched erudition and sophistication.Footnote 2 Moreover, Hegel offered an intriguing approach to transcending authoritarianism, one that entailed a dynamic process of mutual transformation between Self and Other that moves beyond the violent and dominating struggle for individual recognition.
By turning to Hegel, this essay seeks to emphasize the value of a philosophically-informed intellectual history for the study of Central European history in general and of authoritarianism in particular. If such an approach might not hold as much appeal in the field as perhaps it once did, as evidenced by the relatively small number of “traditional” intellectual history articles published in Central European History since 1989, the example of Hegel will demonstrate the valuable historical insights that can be gained from philosophical-intellectual approaches to the past.Footnote 3 Indeed, Hegel's understanding of authoritarianism offers rich possibilities for historians to explore. Specifically, Hegel draws attention to the crucial relationship between authority and recognition.Footnote 4 For him, authoritarianism constitutes a hierarchical relationship of domination in which one person commands obedience from another without recourse to force because the latter freely recognizes the legitimacy of the former's authority. If a particular regime of authority is not recognized as legitimate, then it must compel obedience through coercion. To be sure, authoritarian regimes must resort to coercion to compel obedience from those who refuse to recognize their authority. But an authoritarian regime that enjoys no authority at all, and thus has to command obedience exclusively through force, would not be able to remain in power. Viewed from this perspective, a key issue for historians to explore is how and why specific regimes of authority gain recognition and command obedience. What allows a given regime of authority to compel assent? Why is a particular claim to authority recognized as legitimate?Footnote 5
Recognition and Authoritarianism
The first of the two most conventional narratives of authoritarianism in the field of modern German history situates the problem of authoritarianism in German history, whereas the second locates it in modern European history. The first is commonly known as the Sonderweg narrative, but the second might be referred to as the modernity narrative, insofar as it is concerned with the relationship of authoritarianism to European “modernity.”Footnote 6 The following remarks simply provide a thumbnail sketch of how both narratives address the issue of authoritarianism, i.e., how the Sonderweg and “modernity” narratives answer the following questions: Why did Germans obey the authority of the Nazi dictatorship? What in German culture or “modern” European society can be said to have enabled such obedience to authority?
As the second question already anticipates, the division between the Sonderweg and modernity narratives concerns the particular historical context in which authoritarianism should be placed. Both narratives stress historical particularities, though they conceive of them differently as either “modern German” or “modern European.” The work of representative scholars from each approach––Leonard Krieger and Hannah Arendt, respectively––illustrates the basic differences between the Sonderweg and modernity narratives with regard to authoritarianism. A proponent of the Sonderweg narrative, Krieger, whose most important book, The German Idea of Freedom (1967), dealt extensively with the supposed German propensity for obedience, embraced a clichéd view of German society and culture that Arendt's work challenged in several ways.Footnote 7 In that sweeping work, Krieger identified two different notions of freedom. The first notion refers to the granting of individual rights by a liberal state, the second to the German notion of freedom that valorizes state authority and thus rejects liberalism.Footnote 8 Krieger explains this illiberal notion of freedom most lucidly in his polemical portrait of Hegel as a conservative monarchist who had allegedly developed “in an extreme form the subordination of the individual and the independence of state power.”Footnote 9 In making this argument, Krieger not only aims to understand the roots of National Socialism, but also seeks to defend the liberal concept of freedom as the individual pursuit of what one wishes. That this liberal affirmation of individual freedom reaches its fullest expression in consumerist capitalism—an economic system that generates hierarchies of a different kind from those investigated by Krieger—does not attract his attention, since he rejects out-of-hand the Marxist critique of liberalism as yet another tyrannical suppression of individualism.Footnote 10
Although Arendt shares Krieger's rejection of Marxism, she departs from his German-centric account of authoritarianism.Footnote 11 In Origins of Totalitarianism (1951) and Eichmann in Jerusalem (1963), she characterizes authoritarianism as a product of modern European history. In the first study, she suggests, among other things, that the atomized, isolated individuals of modern European society found meaning in a totalitarian movement that demanded “total loyalty” from them; in the second, she focuses instead on the banality of modern bureaucratic obedience to authority.Footnote 12 In both accounts, however, Arendt assumes that modern society has transformed individuals into “subordinate creatures” who are exceedingly obedient.Footnote 13 Arendt does not indicate why modern society produces such servile individuals, other than to imply that it engenders the problem of what she calls “thoughtlessness.” For her, “thoughtlessness” involves rigid, ideological adherence to a specific position that one dogmatically imposes on another—in stark contrast to the ever-restless activity of thinking, which undermines assertions of authority.Footnote 14
Both Arendt and Krieger largely avoid raising the issue of recognition, which Hegel makes central to authoritarianism—or what he calls “lordship” (Herrschaft) in his famous master-slave section of the Phenomenology.Footnote 15 Hegel begins this section by emphasizing one of his most important philosophical claims: that self-consciousness depends on another self-consciousness. An intersubjective relation of some kind is the necessary condition of self-consciousness. In other words, human reality is inherently social; who or what one conceives oneself to be relies on others recognizing that individual as such, based on what he or she has done to earn their recognition. For example, one might think of oneself as a gifted pianist. This self-interpretation, though certain in that person's mind, holds no truth in the world outside of that person—until he or she performs in such a way that leads others to view that individual as an excellent pianist. The success of that person becoming what he or she desires to be depends, in short, on recognition from others.Footnote 16
In the section on the master and slave, Hegel identifies two different kinds of intersubjective relations. The first is an unequal, hierarchical relation driven by the desire to be recognized as a particular individual (Einzelnes).Footnote 17 The struggle for individual recognition, by definition, places others in a subordinate position since it denies them the same priority that it confers to the self. Recognition is exclusively oriented toward the self: one asserts oneself over others to satisfy a desire to be recognized as individually distinct in some manner (e.g., in terms of expertise, power, authority, property, etc.).
If the desire for individual recognition motivates the impulse to elevate oneself over others, what motivates the desire to obey the master and accept the hierarchical relationship that he or she has established? The answer depends on whether one voluntarily recognizes the legitimacy of the master's authority or not. If one does not recognize it, then one either refuses to obey his or her commands, or one obeys them under some sort of duress, the most extreme form of which is the threat of death. But, if one does, then one obeys voluntarily and without reservation. The question of why one would recognize the legitimacy of a given authority is a crucial one that Hegel's philosophy raises, and to which we shall return. For now, though, the main point is that recognition is a necessary condition of any regime of authority.
A historical example helps to illustrate this point. Adolf Hitler desired recognition as a “salvific leader” and “conqueror,” who promised to return Germany to greatness by building a vast empire in Eastern Europe. Germans faced the choice of either recognizing or resisting his assertion of authority over them. Most Germans chose the former for various reasons. Some Germans voluntarily supported Nazism because they embraced Hitler's portrayal of himself as a leader who could save Germany from Jews, Bolsheviks, and other alleged enemies; others complied with the regime to ensure their own individual security; still others were compelled to obey out of duress. The price of resisting Nazism was high, resulting in harassment, imprisonment, and death.
Overcoming Recognition
Hegel's discussion of the master-slave dialectic seeks not merely to understand domination, but also to find a way out of the authoritarian dynamic of one individual lording oneself over another. His resolution of the problem of authoritarianism hinges on overcoming the desire for recognition of oneself as a particular individual. Committed to the ancient Greek fusion of self and communal interest, Hegel's thought seeks to create a community in which the individual frees oneself from the vain desire to be recognized as distinct from others.
What would such freedom entail? It could be that Hegel, taking the dialectical relationship between the particular and the universal to be productive, had in mind a reconciliation of the individual-community divide, in the sense that the freely chosen norms of the community provide the boundaries and restrictions that allow each individual to pursue his or her own desires and aspirations. Or one might interpret Hegel's concept of freedom as the extirpation of individuality: one becomes a universal being in the universal and homogeneous state that brings historical conflict to an end.Footnote 18 Another possibility is that Hegel imagines a sort of social interaction between Self and Other that is wholly different from that accorded by the authoritarian relationship.
This possibility alerts us to the second approach to otherness that Hegel briefly described in his section on the master and slave. In contrast to the authoritarian relation of one dominating another, Hegel envisioned a relation of interaction between two different and independent selves—an interaction of mutual significance whereby both individuals mutually transform the other.Footnote 19 An example of this insight is the difference between a dialogue between two people who have relinquished the egotistical impulse to assert themselves against each other and thus against the conventional conversation driven by that very impulse. The conventional conversation involves two or more people talking against each rather than with each other. One advocates X against Y because X is more correct than or, in some manner, superior to Y. Another advocates the opposite position and each seeks to defeat the other person's arguments to win recognition as the victor of the conversation. At stake in achieving victory is the correctness of one's beliefs and, ultimately, confirmation of one's identity in the world outside the self. A dialogue is something different: it is an exploration in which both participants open themselves up to transforming their views and their selves as they discuss a topic that might, in turn, be transformed through that very conversation into something different. In a dialogue, the impulse to dominate recedes as neither party expresses any interest in achieving recognition from the other.Footnote 20
Why Authority?
How might these remarks help us think about where Central European History––as a field and as a journal––might go in order to remain relevant in the trend toward transnational and global history? German intellectual history offers rich possibilities for understanding and confronting such enduring and timely issues as authoritarianism—not only in the “classic” case of fascism but also in other cases, such as continental and overseas colonialism, where the authoritarian relation to otherness dominates in various ways.Footnote 21 More broadly, Hegel's point about the intersubjectivity of self-consciousness allows for a view of history that might open up avenues for historians in other fields to explore.
As we have seen, Hegel does not admit the possibility of a purely individual identity isolated from others-an identity somehow completely divorced from the world of sociality and interaction. Self-interpretation requires action and language, and both require participation in a community comprised of specific conventions, or of what could more precisely be called narratives. No historical actor thinks, acts, or speaks without working in relation to a given narrative: Hitler appealed to a wide variety of narratives to support his claim to rule—not least the nationalistic narrative of restoring German superiority. He not only propagated this line in his many speeches, but also acted on it in his violent attempt to build an empire in Eastern Europe. That Hitler ultimately failed and suffered catastrophic defeat does not diminish the fact that a considerable segment of the German population recognized his promise to make Germany great again as a legitimate assertion of authority.
If historical actors speak and act in terms of narratives, then historians might attempt to understand the complex relationship between narrative, authority, and recognition in history. Which narratives gain recognition to support a given regime of authority at a particular moment in history? And, most important, why do they attain the recognition that they do? Why, in short, are specific regimes of authority recognized as legitimate?