Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-v2bm5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T08:18:35.556Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Corrective Justice Account of Disgorgement for Breach of Contract by Analogy to Fiduciary Remedies

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 February 2016

Abstract

A corrective justice account of a private law remedy attempts to the explain the remedy as giving back to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff had a prior right that was breached by the defendant's receipt of that thing. It has proven challenging to explain how disgorgement for breach of contract is consistent with corrective justice. This remedy gives to the plaintiff any profit that a defendant received from a third party by breaching a contract with the plaintiff. In this paper, I critique two leading attempts to show how disgorgement for breach of contract is consistent with corrective justice. I argue that these attempts fail, and I suggest that a plausible corrective justice account of disgorgement should be based on something other than the nature of the contractual rights borne by a plaintiff. I then develop an alternative account based on an analogy between disgorgement for breach of contract and disgorgement for breach of fiduciary duty. To do so, I draw on recent scholarship on the consistency of disgorgement for breach of fiduciary with corrective justice and analyze the leading judicial decision on disgorgement for breach of contract by the UK House of Lords in Attorney General v. Blake. I argue that the fiduciary-based account can provide a plausible explanation for how disgorgement effectuates corrective justice by giving back to a plaintiff something to which he had an antecedent right that the defendant violated by profiting from a breach of contract.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 2016 

I. Introduction

This paper is about disgorgement of profits for breach of contract. This private law remedy is potentially available to a plaintiff in a civil proceeding where the defendant has breached a contract between the parties and, as a result, has obtained a profit from a third party.Footnote 1 It measures the plaintiff’s damages award by reference to the defendant’s gain. Consider the case of Adras Building Material v Harlow & Jones Gmbh.Footnote 2 The plaintiff entered into a contract to purchase steel from the defendant. The cost of steel rose and the defendant sold the steel that was stored for the purposes of sale to the plaintiff to a third party at a higher price, thereby causing it to commit a breach of contract against the plaintiff. The plaintiff suffered no loss because it did not purchase substitute steel before the market price fell. The Supreme Court of Israel awarded the plaintiff the profits that the defendant realized by selling the steel to the third party.

Disgorgement is an exceptional remedy because it differs from standard, compensatory remedies for breach of contract. These are measured by reference to what the plaintiff lost, or expected to receive under the contract but was deprived of, due to the defendant’s breach. Hence, they put the plaintiff in the position he would have been if the defendant’s contractual duty were performed.Footnote 3 The exceptionality of disgorgement is underscored by the rare treatment that the remedy has received from common law courts.Footnote 4 The authoritative case of Attorney General v Blake,Footnote 5 where the UK House of Lords explicitly recognized the remedy and set out a framework for its application, does not appear to have received extensive judicial elaboration. For instance, the Supreme Court of Canada has recently cited Blake for the proposition that, in some cases, contract damages may be awarded without being measured by the plaintiff’s loss, but it did not comment on the nature of the disgorgement remedy articulated in Blake.Footnote 6 Disgorgement might in fact be seen as doubly exceptional, given that the availability of gain-based remedies for private law wrongs other than breach of contract, such as tort,Footnote 7 breach of fiduciary duty,Footnote 8 and breach of confidence,Footnote 9 are well established in the common law tradition. This state of affairs suggests that the remedy merits sustained academic attention, raising as it does such fundamental questions as the nature of contractual rights, the structure of private law remedies, and the relationship between contract and similar doctrines, such as fiduciary law and unjust enrichment.Footnote 10

Disgorgement for breach of contract has indeed attracted much academic discussion.Footnote 11 This paper is concerned with only a corner of this literature, specifically, that bearing on the question of how disgorgement might be explained by the theory of corrective justice in private law. According to this theory, the normative structure of private law entails that a remedy corrects a wrong perpetrated by a defendant and suffered by a plaintiff. It does so by requiring the defendant to transfer to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff has a right that was infringed by the defendant’s wrongful conduct. In the words of Chief Justice Cardozo, “[w]hat the plaintiff must show is ‘a wrong’ to herself, i.e., a violation of her own right,”Footnote 12 and “the commission of a wrong imports the violation of a right.”Footnote 13 Ernest Weinrib has argued that disgorgement for breach of contract is inconsistent with corrective justice because the profit that the remedy transfers to the plaintiff is not part of the plaintiff’s contractual right that the defendant infringed through the breach.Footnote 14 This is another exceptional conclusion because Weinrib and others hold that corrective justice explains related private law remedies, including restitution for unjust enrichmentFootnote 15 and gain-based tort damages.Footnote 16 In response to Weinrib, Peter BensonFootnote 17 and Andrew BotterellFootnote 18 have offered corrective justice accounts of disgorgement by attempting to clarify how contractual rights can, in some cases, be understood so as to allow that a plaintiff has a right to the profits that a defendant might derive through breach of contract and, thus, explain how disgorgement corrects a defendant’s violation of a plaintiff’s right.

In this paper, I assess these attempts to reconcile corrective justice with disgorgement for breach of contract by appeal to the nature of a plaintiff’s contractual rights. I find that they fail to show that, by requiring a defendant to transfer to the plaintiff the profits that the defendant derives from breach of contract, disgorgement gives to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff had a right that the defendant violated by profiting from the breach. I infer from this conclusion that a corrective justice account of disgorgement must regard the remedy as correcting the infringement of a right of the plaintiff other than his contractual right.

I argue that disgorgement is appropriate in cases where the plaintiff’s right that the defendant violates by profiting from breach of contract is not a contractual right but a right to the defendant’s discretionary power. This right is acquired in special cases where the contract superimposes over the parties’ contractual relationship a separate relationship that resembles a fiduciary relationship. In such cases, the plaintiff is placed in a position of vulnerability and dependence relative to the defendant’s exercise of discretion. The defendant is placed under a duty to exercise his discretion in accordance with the plaintiff’s practical interests, which correlates with the plaintiff’s right that defendant so act. It is this right that the defendant wrongfully infringes when acquiring a profit by breaching the contract. Hence, if we can see how some contracts are analogous to fiduciary relationships, and how corrective justice can explain disgorgement of the profits obtained by breach of fiduciary duty, we can also see how corrective justice explains disgorgement for breach of contract as responsive to the defendant’s infringement of a right held by the plaintiff. To make this argument, I interpret the leading decision to award disgorgement in Blake as rooted in a finding that the contractual relationship between the parties was akin to a fiduciary relationship. I also draw upon Paul Miller’s recent work on how corrective justice explains disgorgement for breach of fiduciary duty.Footnote 19

In purporting to develop a novel corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract in this paper, I do not mean to contend that the theory of corrective justice is the best or most plausible theory of the nature of private law remedies. Nor do I contend that the only way that it could be justifiable for a court to award a disgorgement remedy is if the remedy is consistent with in tenets of corrective justice. It is entirely possible for the rationale for awarding disgorgement in some cases to rest on a different theory of the nature of private law. It requires a further argument to conclude that these cases should be regarded as not founded on a defensible rationale. I remain agnostic in this paper about these sorts of arguments, as their substantiation would require a separate and dedicated undertaking. Instead, my goal is to show that, if one finds it illuminating to approach private law through the lens of corrective justice, one need not accept Weinrib’s position that this is never possible to do when it comes to disgorgement, and, furthermore, there is a more defensible way to do so than that suggested by Benson or Botterell. Although this conclusion may count in favour of the plausibility of corrective justice as a theory of private law remedies, this kind of broader inquiry is distinct from and beyond this scope of this paper’s thesis.

I proceed as follows. In Part II, I explain the theory of corrective justice, the nature of contractual rights adopted by Weinrib, Benson, and Botterell to formulate their views on the compatibility of corrective justice with disgorgement for breach of contract, and Weinrib’s argument that this compatibility is not possible. In Part III, I argue that Benson’s and Botterell’s attempts at reconciliation are unsuccessful. In Part IV, I analyze the Blake case to show that the decision to award disgorgement was based on the view that some contractual relationships are analogous to fiduciary relationships. In Part V, I discuss Miller’s corrective justice account of the remedy of disgorgement for breach of fiduciary duty. In Part VI, I argue that this account can be used to develop a corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract by analogy to fiduciary remedies. I conclude in Part VII.

II. The Normative Principles of Corrective Justice, the Nature of Contractual Right, and the Puzzle of Disgorgement for Breach of Contract

I begin by describing the normative principles of corrective justice presupposed in this paper. I then explain the conception of contractual right adopted by Weinrib, Benson, and Botterell. Lastly, I show why disgorgement for breach of contract presents a puzzle from the perspective of corrective justice.

Earlier, I described the corrective justice view of the normative structure of private law by reiterating the Aristotelian notion that a private law remedy corrects an injustice suffered by the plaintiff at the defendant’s hand.Footnote 20 The remedy is triggered by a court orderFootnote 21 that requires the defendant to give to the plaintiff something that rectifies a wrong that the plaintiff suffered at the defendant’s hand. This wrong consists in the defendant’s violation of a duty to not interfere with a correlative right of a plaintiff to the thing that the remedy transfers back to the plaintiff.Footnote 22 To further clarify these claims, I explore Weinrib’s understanding of corrective justice.Footnote 23

A. The Normative Principles of Corrective Justice

Corrective justice’s theory of the normative structure of private law interprets that practice as governing the norms of rightful interaction applicable between parties to a private transaction and as concerned with the rectification of transactional injustice.Footnote 24 It regards the parties as under a relation of equality that consists in each party having what is rightfully his. The relation is disrupted, thereby producing injustice, when there is a departure from this baseline of equality in that one party has too much or too little relative to the other, such as when one party realizes a gain and the other a corresponding loss.Footnote 25 Private law remedies rectify this injustice and re-establish the initial equality by simultaneously depriving one party of the gain and using it to replenish the other party’s deficiency.Footnote 26 Injustice is corrected when “the plaintiff recovers precisely what the defendant is made to suffer.”Footnote 27

The correlativity of a private law remedy indicates that it rectifies an injustice because the injustice itself is correlatively structured.Footnote 28 Plaintiff and defendant are “connected as doer and sufferer of the same injustice”; what the defendant has done and what the plaintiff has suffered are “active and passive poles of the same injustice, so that what the defendant has done counts as an injustice only because of what the plaintiff has suffered, and vice versa.”Footnote 29 A remedy reverses the polarity of the injustice by making the defendant, initially the perpetrator of the injustice, the sufferer of the remedy. It treats the parties as correlatively situated because the injustice that it corrects is the same from both parties’ perspectives.

Private law expresses the parties’ correlativity through the concepts of the plaintiff’s right and the defendant’s correlative duty to not infringe that right. It regards the reasons that justify protecting the plaintiff’s right as the same as those that justify the existence of the plaintiff’s duty:

The identity of the content of the right and the object of the duty informs what it means to do and suffer the same injustice. One suffers an injustice when one’s right is infringed. One does an injustice when one breaches one’s duty not to infringe another’s right. This doing and suffering come together in the same injustice when the duty breached is correlative to the very right that was infringed. Given the correlative positions of the parties, imputing the breach of such a duty to the defendant justifies his or her liability to the plaintiff. For the juridical conception of corrective justice, then, an injustice is an inconsistency with the plaintiff’s right that is imputable to the defendant.Footnote 30

Thus, on a corrective justice theory of the normative structure of private law, a private law remedy corrects an injustice that the defendant perpetrated in breaching a duty to not violate the plaintiff’s right. The remedy transfers from the defendant to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff had a right where the defendant’s possession of that thing is unjust. In these circumstances, there is “justificatory continuity”Footnote 31 between the transfer brought about by the remedy and both the content of the plaintiff’s right and the correlative object of the defendant’s duty. The correlativity that a private law remedy presupposes “is present only when the [defendant’s] gain represents something to which the [plaintiff] had a right of which he or she was deprived by the [defendant’s] wrongful conduct.”Footnote 32

We can reach this same conclusion by taking a different route favoured by other corrective justice theorists. The normative structure of private law includes the ascription in civil proceedings of primary rights to plaintiffs—the familiar rights of contract, tort, property, unjust enrichment, and fiduciary law—that correlate with defendants’ primary duties to not interfere with those rights.Footnote 33 If the plaintiff proves a breach of his primary right and the defendant’s failure to discharge a correlative primary obligation, the defendant becomes liable for having committed a private law injustice. A remedial court order imposes on the defendant a liability to respond to the plaintiff’s grievance in the form of a secondary duty to transfer any gains accrued as a result of the breach to the plaintiff. This duty itself correlates with the plaintiff’s secondary right to have any loss occasioned by the breach restored through receipt of the defendant’s gain.Footnote 34 But this secondary right is simply the plaintiff’s primary right to the benefit accrued to the defendant in another guise.Footnote 35 The right survives its own violation and transforms into a right to redress.Footnote 36 The defendant’s secondary duty to redress reflects the reasons justifying his primary duty to refrain from infringing the plaintiff’s primary right because it derives from the continuing normative force of the primary right.Footnote 37 The secondary duty is “a rational echo” of the primary duty because, although the primary duty was not satisfied, the reasons for its recognition persist and “call for satisfaction in some other way.”Footnote 38 Hence, corrective justice regards a remedy as restoring to the plaintiff “something to which the plaintiff has some sort of normative entitlement.”Footnote 39 It corrects a wrong committed by the defendant by requiring him to redress the plaintiff’s right after having breached it by giving to the plaintiff what the plaintiff had a right to all along.

I pause here to observe that, at least for Weinrib, and for those who subscribe to his version of corrective justice, it is a crucial desideratum for a corrective justice account of a private law remedy such as disgorgement that the remedy is consistent with contemporary private law jurisprudence and doctrine. The general aim of a corrective justice theory of private law is to elucidate the abstract normative presuppositions indigenous to or immanent in private law, conceived as a coherent and systematic normative practice. It aspires to expound the internal structure of private law as it is actually practiced to “understand the law in its own terms”; it takes private law doctrine “at face value” to explain “the ways in which participants in a sophisticated legal system reason within the concepts that it provides.”Footnote 40 It is, therefore, necessary for a corrective justice account of a private law remedy to cohere with private law doctrine because it intends to explicate normative principles of private interaction that are specifically juridical in that they are seen as normatively grounding the decided cases that shape the actual practice of private law. As Weinrib writes:

The aim of the juridical conception is to disclose the structure and the normative presuppositions of the law’s internal processes of justification. It takes the doctrinal and institutional features that are characteristic of a regime of liability, and asks what must be presupposed about them and about their interconnection if the law is to be (as it claims) a coherent justificatory enterprise. The answer lies in identifying the most abstract unifying conceptions implicit in the doctrinal and institutional arrangements of private law. Thus the juridical conception of corrective justice purports to bring to the surface ideas that are latent in liability as a normative practice.Footnote 41

That it is a desideratum of a corrective justice account of a private law remedy that it coheres with contemporary private law doctrine will be important to understanding both the critical and constructive arguments presented later in this paper.

B. The Nature of Contractual Right

If a remedy must restore to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff had a right, a right that the defendant infringed by gaining that thing, it is not immediately obvious how standard contract remedies, which give to the plaintiff something that he would have received had the contract been performed, are consistent with corrective justice. Standard contract remedies do not appear to compensate the plaintiff for a loss of a right because the object transferred under the contract is not something to which the plaintiff had a right prior to the defendant’s failed performance. The defendant owns the object until the promised time of performance. The plaintiff has only an expectation of receiving it until that time, not a present right to it acquired at the time of contract formation. Thus, it appears that the standard loss-based measure of contract damages treats a plaintiff as entitled to the value of the object of a contract even though he is not its owner.Footnote 42

To resolve this difficulty, Weinrib, Benson, and Botterell adopt a Kantian conception of contractual right. This conception characterizes contractual rights as a form of ownership that turns on the distinction between in personam and in rem rights.Footnote 43 Contractual right, like property rights, is a form of ownership in the sense that it “entails a right against and exclusive of another to possess, to determine the use of, and to alienate an object that is external to the person.”Footnote 44 It is an in personam right distinct from an in rem right, such as a property right, in virtue of its distinctive mode of acquisition.

According to Kant,Footnote 45 property rights and contractual rights are acquired rights—as opposed to one’s innate right of freedom and bodily integrity—that enable one to own something that is external to one’s self. A person acquires a property right by coming into first occupancy of an object that is in the initial condition of being unowned. The person unilaterally and without anyone else’s consent acquires an entitlement to the object against all other persons.Footnote 46 By contrast, contractual rights do not give persons rights to external objects at the time of contract formation. The promisee later comes into possession of the object transferred under the contract only at the time of performance, until which time the object is in the initial condition of being owned by the promisor. Hence, the eventual acquisition of the object is derivative and bilateral in that it is made possible only by the consent of the promisor. Contractual right is therefore a right against only the promisor to have the promisor perform a specific act to provide the promisee with the object of the contract at some future time, only at which time the promisor acquires a property right to that object as against the world. The promisee acquires a right to “another’s choice to perform a specific deed”Footnote 47 and comes to own it. His ownership entails his exclusive authority to possess, determine the use of, and alienate it, when the promisor simultaneously alienates his own right to choose whether to perform that deed.Footnote 48

At the time of contract formation, a person acquires, not a right to the promised object that is proprietary and in rem in nature, but “an exclusive ownership right as against the defendant with respect to the latter’s promised performance.”Footnote 49 Thus, a defendant’s breaching the contract by failing to perform is a breach of duty because it deprives the plaintiff of something to which the plaintiff acquired a prior right. A contract remedy measured by reference to the plaintiff’s loss of this right—i.e., according to the value of the defendant’s promised act—corrects the defendant’s wrongful breach of duty by giving back to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff had a prior right. The Kantian conception of the nature of contractual right as a right not to a thing but to another’s act resolves the difficulty of explaining how contract damages that aim to compensate for a lost expectation are consistent with corrective justice.Footnote 50

C. The Puzzle of Disgorgement for Breach of Contract

The foregoing reconciliation of loss-based remedies for breach of contract and corrective justice generates a puzzle for reconciling the gain-based remedy of disgorgement of profits with corrective justice. To see why, we need to understand how corrective justice explains gain-based remedies for other private law wrongs, such as torts or trespass, as correcting a defendant’s violation of a plaintiff’s right and as restoring the plaintiff’s loss by requiring the defendant to give back to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff had an antecedent right.

The Kantian conception of contract regards contractual rights as in personam rather than in rem. But it regards both proprietary and contractual rights as entailing “exclusive authority to determine the purposes to which the object of the right is put.”Footnote 51 If a person has a property right to an object, he is entitled to possess the object and determine its use and alienation in virtue of her ownership. Crucially, she is also entitled to any profits that accrue from the object’s disposition; “the profits are the owner’s as surely as the object that produced them.”Footnote 52 All others are under a correlative private law duty to not receive this profit. If someone other than the owner converts and sells the object for profit, or trespasses on it to conduct a profitable venture, a remedial court order to disgorge those profits corrects an injustice perpetrated by the defendant. By profiting, the defendant infringed the plaintiff’s proprietary right. A disgorgement remedy responds to that infringement by giving back to the owner “the value of the defendant’s usurpation of the plaintiff’s exclusive authority to determine the uses to which his or her property is put.”Footnote 53

It might be thought that the same analysis applies where a promisor contracts to sell an object to a promisee, but, instead of delivering the object, fails to do so and sells the object to a third party at a profit. But what right of the promisee does the promisor infringe by, not only failing to deliver the object and exposing himself to damages measured by the promisee’s loss, but also selling the object at a profit? It is unclear how the promisee could have had a right to the gain accruing to the promisor through the sale of the object to the third party or how the promisor had a duty to not profit from the sale of the object. The profit “cannot be construed as in any way belonging to the plaintiff.”Footnote 54 It is, therefore, puzzling how a remedy of disgorging these profits can be consistent with corrective justice by compensating for the defendant’s deprivation of a prior right to the profits held by the plaintiff.Footnote 55

The puzzle could be resolved if, at the time of contract formation, a promisee acquires a property right to the object of a contract from the promisor, including a right to the profits from the object’s alienation. The promisor’s availing himself of those profits by selling the object to a third party and breaching the contract would therefore constitute a breach of a private law duty to not interfere with the promisee’s antecedent right to the profits. A disgorgement remedy requiring the promisor to give those profits back to the promisee would give to the promisee what the promisee had a right all along. But we cannot accept this line of argument. To show how loss-based expectation damages for breach of contract are consistent with corrective justice, we must posit that at the time of contract formation a promisee acquires a right to the promisor’s performance of delivering the subject matter of the contract, not a proprietary right to the subject matter of the contract itself, which the promisee acquires only at the time of delivery, and a fortiori not a proprietary right to the proceeds from the subject matter’s alienation.

Weinrib concludes from this puzzle that disgorgement for breach of contract is inconsistent with corrective justice. If the property rights, and rights to profit from property, of a plaintiff are not violated when a defendant profits from breach of contract by selling the promised object at a gain, the defendant’s gain is not something acquired in breach of a duty to not interfere with a correlative right of the plaintiff. Disgorgement of the gain thus does not “render unto to the promisee what was the promisee’s.”Footnote 56

III. Critique of Extant Attempts to Reconcile Disgorgement for Breach of Contract with Corrective Justice

In this Part, I describe the attempts to reconcile disgorgement for breach of contract with corrective justice that appeal to the nature of contractual rights offered by Benson and Botterell. I argue that these attempts fail. This suggests that it is worthwhile to investigate whether a reconciliation of corrective justice with disgorgement should proceed by appealing to something other than contractual rights.

A. Benson’s Attempted Reconciliation

Benson begins by emphasizing that, as a right of ownership, a promisee’s contractual right against the promisor gives the promisee a right to possess, use, or alienate the promisor’s performance of a specific act. The right is exercised at the time of performance, before which the promisee has the “authority to determine what is done with” the act, an authority that the promisor usurps by failing to perform.Footnote 57 Benson then introduces a factual distinction between contracts that give the promisee a right to what Botterell refers to as “generic performance” and those that give the promisee a right to “particular performance.”Footnote 58

In contracts for particular performance, but not in contracts for generic performance, the subject matter of the contract is a unique object for which no market substitute is available.Footnote 59 For example, if a plaintiff P and a defendant D contract for D to deliver some 10 widgets to P, the contract is for generic performance. D has a contractual duty to act so as to provide P with any 10 widgets (this or that group of widgets, or some other group), not any unique widget. P’s correlative contractual right is that D so act. By contrast, if P and D contract for D to deliver a unique widget w to P, the contract is for particular performance. D has a contractual duty to act so as to provide w, and not just any widget, to P. P’s correlative contractual right is that D so act.

Suppose that P and D contract for the sale of 10 widgets. Benson holds that P acquires the generic performance of act ϕi—“Deliver some 10 widgets.” D has a correlative duty to ϕi in that by failing to ϕi D withholds from P something that P owns. If D violates this duty, P can, as corrective justice requires, obtain a remedy measured by the value of what P lost, namely, the value of the act ϕi. But nothing changes depending on whether D violated his contractual duty by simply failing to ϕi for no reason or by failing to ϕi in order to sell the 10 widgets stored for delivery to P to a third party at a profit. P’s right to ϕi contained no right to the delivery of any particular 10 widgets such that D’s failure to deliver those particular 10 widgets by not ϕi-ing constituted a violation of a duty to provide any particular widgets to P. Because the failure to deliver any particular 10 widgets is not as such an act contrary to ϕi that deprives P of something that P owns through the contract, D’s sale of the widgets to a third party is not “a misappropriation of anything coming under the plaintiff’s exclusive rights as against the defendant.”Footnote 60

Now, suppose that P and D contract for the sale of widget w. P acquires the particular performance of act ϕii—“Deliver widget w.” Benson holds that ϕii exhibits greater determinacy than ϕi because it contains a specification for the delivery of a unique object w.Footnote 61 D has a correlative duty to ϕii such that D’s failure to ϕii withholds from P something over which P has exclusive authority. But, unlike ϕi, ϕii includes delivery of w to P. This entails that D is no longer able to sell w to a third party without breaching a contractual duty owed to P. For Benson, D’s sale of w to a third party at a profit constitutes a wrong to P because “[t]the act of selling to the third party is identical to the act which has already been transferred to the plaintiff,” and the sale “represents a misappropriation by the defendant of what belongs exclusively to the plaintiff.”Footnote 62

Benson concludes that in cases where a plaintiff acquires a right to the defendant’s particular performance due to the uniqueness of the object of the contract, the plaintiff acquires a right to the profits that might accrue to the defendant when the defendant breaches the contract to sell the object to a third party. Hence, disgorgement of those profits is reconcilable with corrective justice because it gives back to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff acquired a right at the time of contract formation.

B. Critique of Benson’s Attempt

I do not think that Benson’s reconciliation can be sustained. In assessing the attempt, it is key to keep in mind that on a Kantian conception a contractual right is a right of ownership entitling the owner to possession, use, and disposition, including an entitlement to the profits derived from disposition. Suppose that at contract formation a promisee acquires a right to the promisor’s performance of a specific act. It follows that, in contracts for particular performance involving delivery by the promisor of a unique object, the promisor’s breach of the contract to sell that object to a third party and obtain a profit amounts to a breach of the promisee’s contractual right—which a disgorgement remedy corrects by giving those profits back to the promisee—if and only if the promisor profits from the disposition of an act over which the promisee has exclusive ownership. The required sort of disposition will exist if and only if the act disposed of by the promisor to obtain a profit is, as Benson states, identical to the act of the promisor over which the promisee acquired ownership at the time the parties formed their contract for particular performance.

Benson argues that the identity of the act disposed of by the breaching promisor and the act acquired by the promisee is attributable to the two acts’ identical objects.Footnote 63 Weinrib comments on this argument as follows:

Once the specification of the required act is expanded to include all the terms of the respective transactions, the identity between the two acts disappears. The two transactions may call for acts of delivery at different times and places. Moreover, the specification of delivery will inevitably refer to different recipients. Accordingly, what was sold to the third party was not the act of delivery that belonged to the promisee, but a different act of delivery inconsistent with the first one. This new act of delivery made breach of the contract unavoidable … but it was not the misappropriation of an act of delivery identical to, and therefore owned by, the promisee. The effect of insisting on the importance of specification but confining this specification to the object of the contract … is to transform—inconsistently with the Kantian argument—the contractual right to performance into a right to the thing.Footnote 64

These are relatively terse remarks. But I think that, once they are more thoroughly fleshed out and clarified, they can form the basis of a decisive objection to Benson’s position.Footnote 65

Let us call the act of a promisor that is acquired by a promisee at the time of forming a contract for particular performance ϕii. And let us call the act of the promisor that the promisor alienates by profitably selling the object of that contract ϕiii. The promisee is entitled to the profits derived from the alienation of ϕii. Thus, for the promisor’s sale of the object to the third party to constitute a usurpation of the promisee’s ownership over ϕii so as to entitle him to the profits derived from the alienation of ϕiii, ϕii must be identical to ϕiii. Benson claims that ϕii and ϕiii are identical in virtue of their identical objects. Thus, he specifies both acts as follows: “Deliver object o.” But this mode of specification is not defensible.

First, while it may be justifiable to focus on the object to be delivered when specifying ϕii and ϕiii,Footnote 66 privileging such a focus at the expense of all other considerations is incongruous with the Kantian conception of contractual right, according to which all that a promisee acquires at contract formation is an act. Second, for ϕii and ϕiii to be truly identical, they must each mandate particular performances. Benson’s view is that ϕii must mandate particular performance. But it is only sufficient and not necessary for ϕiii to do so. A promisor who contracts to sell a unique object to a promisee need not also contract to sell that same unique object to a third party in order to sell that object to a third party at a profit; he need only contract to sell to the third party a generic object that falls in the same class of objects resembling the unique object and pick that unique object out of the class to sell. Third, Benson gives no justification for why the locations and times of performance for ϕii and ϕiii are not included in the acts’ specifications. If they are included, they must be identical for Benson’s argument to succeed. But they need not be for a promisor to profitably sell to a third party the unique object that he initially promised to sell to the promisee.

Most importantly, Benson’s specification of ϕii and ϕiii does not include the recipients of the objects delivered by these acts. This is problematic because through contract a person acquires an object only in the condition of it being owned by another person and hence acquires it only with the consent of the other. The creation of a contractual relationship between two persons “could only be consistent with the freedom of those persons if both of them participate in its creation.”Footnote 67 The fundamentally bilateral normative character of contractual acquisition, reflected in the doctrinal requirements of offer and acceptance, consensus ad item,Footnote 68 and privity,Footnote 69 suggests that one of the most important constraints on specifying ϕii and ϕiii is the specification of the deliveror and deliveree of the acts’ performances. Taking this constraint seriously yields the following reading of ϕii and ϕiii, respectively: “D delivers object o to P” and “D delivers object o to X”, where “D” and “P” are the defendant and plaintiff and “X” is a third party. The constraint of specifying the deliveror and deliveree of the object transferred by the performances of ϕii and ϕiii annihilates the identity of the two acts.

Hence, the profit flowing from promisor’s disposition of ϕiii to a third party cannot be seen as owned by the promisee. Although the promisee has a right to the profit flowing from the disposition of ϕii, and although the disposition of ϕiii to a third party is inconsistent with the performance of ϕii, ϕii and ϕiii cannot be seen as identical. What a defendant in an action for disgorgement for breach of contract sells for profit to a third party is not the particular performance of the defendant’s specific act of delivering a unique object to the plaintiff. The third party does not acquire a right that the defendant performs this act of delivery to the plaintiff or the defendant’s contractual duty to perform this act for the plaintiff. But this is the only act which the plaintiff has ownership of, and the only profits to which the plaintiff has an entitlement are those flowing from the disposition of this act. Therefore, the defendant’s breach of contract “is not an alienation of something that the promisee owned.”Footnote 70

We are led to reject Benson’s attempted reconciliation of corrective justice with disgorgement for breach of contract. Let us move on now to consider Botterell’s attempt.

C. Botterell’s Attempted Reconciliation

Botterell’s attempt can be seen as a response to the problems facing Benson’s attempt. He adopts the distinction between contracts for generic performance, which give the promisee a contractual right to promisor’s act ϕi, “D delivers some objects to P”, and contracts for particular performance for delivery of a unique object, which give the promisee a contractual right to promisor’s act ϕii, “D delivers object o to P.” We have seen that, in cases of particular performance where the promisor breaches the contract in order to sell the object to be delivered to a third party at a profit, disgorgement of those profits and their transfer back to the promisee is explicable by corrective justice if and only if, in so doing, the promisor alienates an act to which the promisee has an ownership right, including ownership of the profits accruing from its alienation, such that disgorgement of those profits restores to the promisor’s something that was rightfully his. Benson’s strategy is to argue that the act that the promisor alienates in such circumstances, ϕiii, is something to which the promisee has a right because ϕii is identical to ϕiii. Botterell’s strategy is to acknowledge the distinctness of ϕii and ϕiii but to argue that, at contract formation, the promisee acquires ϕiii as an implication of his acquisition of ϕii.

For Botterell, ϕiii is sufficiently “nearby”Footnote 71 to ϕii to give the promisor a right to ϕiii in virtue of his acquisition of ϕii from the promisee at the time of forming the contract for particular performance of delivery of a unique object o. Suppose that ϕiii is interpreted as “D delivers object o to X.” The promisor’s performance of this act is incompatible with ϕii because the performance of ϕiii makes the performance of ϕii impossible. Botterell argues that at contract formation, when the promisee acquires a contractual right to the promisor’s performance of a specific act ϕii, an “implicit” or “subsidiary” promise by the promisor arises as a kind of negative covenant that the promisee will not perform an act that is incompatible with ϕii.Footnote 72 So, the implicit promise is that the promisee consents to not ϕiii. The connection between ϕii and this implicit promise establishes for the promisee, at the time of contract formation, a contractual right to the promisor’s performance of ϕiii such that the promisor has exclusive authority over the possession, use, and disposition of ϕiii as the owner of ϕiii.Footnote 73 Thus, if the promisor alienates ϕiii to a third party and realizes a profit, he “transfers something that was not [his] to transfer” and the promisee “can legitimately complain that the profit belongs to him.”Footnote 74

D. Critique of Botterell’s Attempt

There are two difficulties with Botterell’s attempted reconciliation of disgorgement for breach of contract with corrective justice. The first is conceptual and the second has to do with the attempt’s fit with contemporary private law doctrine. I discuss each in turn.

1. The Conceptual Difficulty

The conceptual difficulty is that the attempt entails that the availability of disgorgement for breach of contract is not limited to contracts for particular performance but for breach of any contract. It therefore fails at explaining the remedy’s exceptionality.

To see this, let us scrutinize Botterell’s claim that, in a contract for particular performance, the promisee acquires a right to ϕiii (D delivers o to X) and owns that act in addition to ϕii (D delivers o to P). For Botterell, this acquisition follows from the fact the promisor’s ϕiii-ing is incompatible with his ϕii-ing; delivery of o to X makes delivery of o to P impossible. The promisor’s ϕiii-ing amounts to what I will refer to as “auto-frustration” of the contract for particular performance with the promisee. The promise implied by ϕii is that the promisor will not auto-frustrate the contract and act incompatibly with his contractual obligation to ϕii by performing the act ϕiii. Botterell must make this claim because, again, it is this implied promise that gives the promisee ownership over ϕiii such that any gains realized by the promisor’s disposition of ϕiii are only accrued in violation of a right of the promisee. A disgorgement remedy then effectuates corrective justice by giving back to the promisee something that he always had a right to.

The difficulty is that every contract, and not just contracts for particular performance, must give rise to an implied promise by the promisor that the promisor will not auto-frustrate the contract. If a promisor has a contractual duty to perform a specific act that correlates with the promisee’s right to that act, the promisor always also has a implicit duty to not auto-frustrate by performing a separate act that makes the initial act impossible to perform. After all, the promisor’s performance of this separate act deprives the promisee of his right to and ownership of the initial act. Corrective justice requires that he be transferred the value of the initial act by way of an expectation remedy for breach of contract measured according to the promisee’s loss.

But if every contract brings into existence an implied promise by the promisor to not auto-frustrate the contract, every contract should, on Botterell’s argument, give the promisee a right to the promisor’s auto-frustrating act, which entitles the promisee to the profits flowing from that act. Botterell’s argument would therefore get us no closer to understanding why a disgorgement remedy may be available to a plaintiff for breach of some contracts but not others.

Consider an example. Suppose that two parties form a contract whereby the promisee acquires the promisor’s generic performance of the act of delivering some 10 widgets to the promisee. The promisor has only 15 widgets stored for sale at his warehouse. He then sells 10 widgets to a third party at a price greater than that agreed upon with the promisee. The act of selling the 10 widgets auto-frustrates the contract between promisor and promisee because, given the promisor’s stipulated inventory, it makes delivering some 10 widgets to the promisee impossible. When the promisor does not perform that now-impossible initial act, the promisee is deprived of his right to it and is entitled to receive loss-based damages equal to the act’s value.

But, on Botterell’s principles, the contract discussed here must have also incorporated an implied promise by the promisor to not auto-frustrate by acting inconsistently with the initial act of delivering some 10 widgets to the promisee. The promisee thus ought to have acquired a right to and ownership of the promisor’s act of selling 10 widgets to a third party the alienation of which at a profit deprives the promisee of this right and usurps this ownership. Transferring those profits back to the promisee restores the promisee’s right. Yet, this does not seem to be the type of case that Botterell envisions as making available disgorgement for breach of contract.

It also does not seem to be the type of case giving rise to the remedy envisioned in the leading decision of Blake. In the Court of Appeal judgement in this case, Lord Wolff suggested that disgorgement should be available “where the defendant has obtained his profit by doing the very thing which he contracted not to do.”Footnote 75 On appeal to the House of Lords, Lord Nicholls rejected this suggestion. He wrote that the category of cases where the defendant profits by doing the very thing he contracted not to do “is defined too widely to assist” and “is apt to embrace all express negative obligations” and that “something more is required than mere breach of such an obligation before an account of profits will be the appropriate remedy.”Footnote 76 The example of the contract for some 10 widgets discussed above shows that an implicit promise by the promisor in the form of a negative covenant that he will not auto-frustrate the contract can arise out of a contract for generic performance, not just a contract for particular performance. If, as Botterell argues, the existence of an implicit negative covenant grounds the availability of disgorgement, disgorgement should also be available wherever a promisor profits from the breach of a negative covenant.Footnote 77 But the House of Lords rejected this strict criterion.

As was discussed in Part II, above, it is a desideratum of a corrective justice account of a private law remedy that the account coheres with contemporary private law doctrine.Footnote 78 But my primary motive in examining the aspect of Lord Nicholls’ reasoning in Blake discussed in the previous paragraph is to show that Lord Nicholls appears to have recognized the conceptual difficulty with the position taken by Botterell’s that I have been attempting to highlight. That is, as I have been suggesting, Lord Nicholls reasoned that it would define the availability of disgorgement too widely to assert that the remedy’s availability hinges on the existence of a negative covenant on the part of a promisor to not act inconsistently with the act that the promisor initially promised to perform.

I return to discussing the Blake decision below. To pursue the argument under consideration here, the conceptual difficulty with Botterell’s attempted reconciliation of corrective justice and disgorgement for breach of contract is revealed no matter what we imagine the promisor’s auto-frustrating act to be, so long as the act is inconsistent with the initial act of delivering some 10 widgets to the promisee and the promisor profits from the act. The promisor might torch his warehouse, destroying all his widgets, to profit from insurance coverage. He might use all the widgets to build a machine whose operation allows him to earn more money than he would if he sold the widgets. Moreover, it is possible for any contract to be auto-frustrated by the promisor. Any promisor can always fail to perform the specific act acquired by the promisee by performing an inconsistent act, even if this inconsistent act is simply not performing the initial act. In other words, every contract gives rise to an implied promise by the promisor in the nature of a negative covenant that he will not fail to perform the specific act acquired by the promisee.Footnote 79 Auto-frustration thus understood, which is ubiquitously possible, would almost by definition entitle a promisee to the value of the initial act that the promisor failed to perform in violation of the promisee’s right to that act. It remains obscure why the implied negative covenant that the promisor not auto-frustrate by simply failing to perform the initial act gives the promisee a right to the auto-frustrating act that entitles him to any profits accruing from its use or disposition.

Botterell also seems to recognize this conceptual difficulty with his attempted reconciliation of disgorgement and corrective justice. But in my view his response to it is question begging. The question is why, as Botterell puts it, “should the particularity, or lack thereof, of the action contracted for make such a crucial remedial difference?”Footnote 80 I have argued that, on the principles endorsed by Botterell, disgorgement should be available in contracts for generic performance (and indeed in all contracts). So, why it is necessary for a contract to be for particular performance for disgorgement to be available? Botterell replies that “[t]he particularity of the action contracted for is important because it is only when an action is suitably particular that a promisee can be said to own the promisor’s contractual performance” and that “only particular actions contracted for can give rise to the appropriate normative entitlement.”Footnote 81 In contracts for generic performance, “disgorgement would not be available” because “in this sort of case there is no performance that the promisee can be said to own” and generic performance is “insufficient to give rise to the sort of normative entitlement that would make disgorgement appropriate.”Footnote 82 These remarks exhaust Botterell’s response. They would appear to amount to an assertion that it is necessary that a contract be for particular performance for disgorgement to be available. I have maintained that this assertion is false.

In Botterell’s defence, one might argue as follows. Suppose that every contract, whether for generic or particular performance, can be auto-frustrated by the promisor’s acting so as to make the contract impossible to perform. Every contract gives rise to an implicit promise by the promisor that he will not act inconsistently with the initial act acquired by the promisee through the contract. It might be argued that it does not follow that, in virtue of this implicit promise, the promisee in every contract acquires a right to the promisor’s auto-frustrating act in a way that entitles the promisee to disgorgement of any profits realized by the promisor due to performing the auto-frustrating act. The promisee acquires this subsidiary right only in contracts for particular performance. This is because, so the argument goes, the nature of contractual auto-frustration—or what it means for a promisor to act inconsistently with or make performance of his contractual duty impossible—in contracts for particular performance is fundamentally distinct from the nature of contractual auto-frustration in contracts for generic performance.

But it is hard to see how this distinction can be convincingly drawn. It might be drawn in the following manner. Consider a contract for generic performance for the delivery of some 10 widgets. The promisee acquires a contractual right to the promisor’s performance of act ϕi (D delivers 10 widgets to P). The promisor can auto-frustrate this contract by acting inconsistently with ϕi and making ϕi impossible to perform. He might destroy all his widgets, oversleep and fail to deliver the widgets at the agreed time of performance, or simply fail to deliver the widgets out of apathy or laziness. Most importantly for present purposes, the promisor might also auto-frustrate by selling the 10 widgets that were supposed to be sold to the promisee to a third party at a profit.

It might be argued that the sale of the 10 widgets to the third party at a profit cannot be characterized as making ϕi impossible to perform in the same way that it would make a contract for particular performance impossible to perform. In a contract for particular performance involving the delivery of a unique object o, the promisee acquires act ϕii (D delivers o to P). The promisee’s sale of o to a third party at a profit indeed makes performing ϕii impossible. But in this particular performance case, what the promisor cannot by definition do, after selling o to a third party, is purchase a market substitute for o and salvage his apparently auto-frustrating act by delivering o to the promisee at the time performance of ϕii is due. Contracts for particular performance by definition involve the delivery of a unique object for which no market substitute exists. The delivery of that object to a party other than the promisee makes delivery to the promisee in principle impossible. By contrast, the promisor in the generic performance case can in fact salvage his apparently auto-frustrating act after selling the 10 widgets to a third party at a profit by purchasing 10 new market substitutes for the widgets and delivering them to the promisee at the time performance of ϕi is due. It may be practically impossible for the promisor to salvage the auto-frustration by finding and purchasing appropriate market substitutes in time. But salvaging the auto-frustration is not precluded logically or tautologically, as it is in the particular performance case. Contracts for generic performance by definition involve the delivery of objects for which market substitutes in fact exist, however practically unlikely it is for a promisee to purchase them to avoid breaching his contractual duty.

Thus, it might be thought that there is a fundamental difference in the nature of contractual auto-frustration, where auto-frustration consists in the disposal of the objects to be delivered under the contract to a third party at a profit, between contracts for generic performance and contracts for particular performance. Perhaps the relevant auto-frustrating act in generic performance cases is in principle capable of being salvaged by the promisee’s purchase and delivery of market substitutes of the objects to be delivered, whereas the relevant auto-frustrating act in particular performance cases by definition cannot be salvaged in this way. This could be a way to construing the idea that “the particularity, or lack thereof, of the action contracted for makes a crucial remedial difference.”

The foregoing suggestion is, however, problematic. Despite the respective definitions of contracts for generic performance and contracts for particular performance based on the availability of market substitutes for objects delivered under them, when each type of contract is auto-frustrated by the promisor’s sale of the objects to be delivered to the promisee to a third party at profit, the promisor in each case can always salvage the auto-frustration and act consistently with the initial act of delivery acquired by the promisee at contract formation. It is clear how he can do so in the generic performance case. Consider then a case of particular performance where the promisor apparently auto-frustrates ϕii by selling the unique object o to a third party at a profit. It is in principle possible for the promisor to nevertheless act consistently with ϕii by the time performance of ϕii is due by re-purchasing o from the third party and delivering it to the promisee. It may no doubt be practically unlikely that he will be able to do so because the third party may be willing to part with o only at an extremely high price. But, as mentioned above, it may also be practically unlikely for a promisee in a generic performance case to find market substitutes for the non-unique objects promised under the contract but sold to a third party at a profit and deliver those objects to the promisee in satisfaction of the promisor’s contractual duty to ϕi. The point is that it does not follow logically or tautologically from the definition of a unique object in a contract for particular performance as lacking any market substitute that the ability of the promisor to salvage his auto-frustrating act after selling the object to be delivered under the contract to a third party at a profit is any different from the ability of the promisor to do so in a contract for generic performance. This point is tantamount to the conclusion that there is no difference between the nature of contractual auto-frustration in particular performance cases and that in generic performance cases which explains the availability of disgorgement in the former but not the latter.

How else might the particularity of an action contracted for make a crucial difference to the availability of a disgorgement remedy? Consider again the initial supposition that every contract, whether for generic or particular performance, is capable of being auto-frustrated by the promisor’s acting so as to make the contract impossible to perform. Every contract gives rise to an implicit promise by the promisor that he will not act inconsistently with the initial act acquired by the promisee through the contract. Now consider a contract that is auto-frustrated by the promisor through a sale of the object to be delivered under the contract to a third party at a profit, such that the promisor makes his contractual duty impossible to perform. It might be argued that only the promisee in a contract for particular performance acquires a right to the relevant auto-frustrating act, in virtue of the promisor’s implicit promise to not act inconsistently with his contractual duty, in a manner that entitles the promisee to disgorgement of any profits received by the promisor due to performing the auto-frustrating act.

In a contract for generic performance for the delivery of 10 widgets, the promisee acquires a right to the promisor’s performance of act ϕi (D delivers 10 widgets to P). If the promisor sells the widgets to a third party at a profit, he makes ϕi impossible to perform and auto-frustrates the contract. It might be said that, although the promisor makes an implicit promise to not act inconsistently with ϕi, the promisee acquires no right to the promisor’s act of selling the widgets to the third party and no right to any profits derived from the sale. This is because the act of sale to the third party is not the same act as ϕi; they are specified differently by referring to different recipients and perhaps different times for performance or generic objects to be delivered. By contrast, it might be said that an act of selling a unique object o to a third party by the promisor in a contract for particular performance is identical to the act acquired by the promisee in that contract, namely, ϕii (D delivers o to P). This act of sale to the third party makes performance of ϕii impossible and it auto-frustrates the contract. The promisor therefore implicitly promises not to perform it. But because it is identical to ϕii, an act to which the promisee acquired a right at the time of contract formation, its performance by the promisor constitutes misappropriation of something to which the promisee had a prior right. Thus, the promisee is entitled to any profits that the promisor received from the sale of o to the third party in the particular performance case. The entitlement arises in virtue of the identity of the act of selling o to the third party and ϕii, rather than in virtue of any kind of implicit promise by the promisor not to auto-frustrate the contract by making his contractual duty impossible to perform, which applies in all contracts.

It should be evident at this point why this argument cannot succeed. The argument rests on the distinction between the act of selling the widgets to a third party and ϕi in the generic performance case and the identity between the act of selling o to a third party and ϕii in the particular performance case. But, as we have seen in the critique of Benson’s attempted reconciliation of corrective justice and disgorgement for breach of contract, in contracts for particular performance, the promisor’s act ϕii cannot be interpreted as necessarily identical to the promisor’s act of selling the unique object to a third party, or ϕiii. The acts’ respective specifications refer to distinct recipients and may refer to distinct times for performance and distinct objects. As I read Botterell’s attempt, ϕii and ϕiii are distinct. But, because the performance of ϕiii is inconsistent with and makes ϕi impossible to perform, thereby auto-frustrating the contract for particular performance, ϕii gives rise to an implicit promise that promisor will not perform ϕiii. This implicit promise makes ϕiii sufficiently nearby to ϕii to give the promisor an acquired right to ϕiii in addition to ϕii, as well as to any profits derived from the alienation of ϕiii. What does the work of establishing the availability of disgorgement in Botterell’s attempt is not the identity of ϕii and ϕiii but the sufficient nearness of these acts that is grounded in the notion that ϕiii is what I have referred to as an auto-frustrating act that makes the promisor’s contractual duty to ϕii impossible to perform.

However, I have argued that all generic contracts give rise to an implicit promise by the promisor to not act so as to make his contractual duty impossible to perform by auto-frustrating the contract. The nature of contractual auto-frustration is no different in contracts for generic performance and contracts for particular performance. Thus, if Botterell’s attempt is correct, a promisee should acquire a right to any act of the promisor that is inconsistent with the act initially acquired from the promisor at contract formation, simply in virtue of an implicit promise by the promisor not to perform the inconsistent act, and a right to any profits derived from the promisor’s disposition of the inconsistent act. The conceptual difficulty is then that it remains unclear why disgorgement of profits for breach of contract is available in some cases but not in others.

2. Fit with Contemporary Private Law Doctrine

The second difficulty with Botterell’s attempt is that it sits uneasily with established private law doctrine. The attempt entails that the injustice perpetrated by a defendant who profits from breach of contract, which disgorgement for breach of contract corrects, is a wrong of what Peter Birks called “subtractive unjust enrichment.”Footnote 83 Suppose that, upon forming a contract for particular performance, a plaintiff acquires a right to the promisor’s performance of a specific act and, in virtue of an implicit promise to not act inconsistently with that act, a right to a separate act of the defendant that is inconsistent with the initial act. The defendant’s failure to perform the initial act in order to profit from performing the separate act is a breach of contractual duty only because it interferes with a right of the plaintiff. The defendant is unjustly enriched because he gained through the accrual of profits that are correlatively subtracted from the plaintiff’s entitlements. Disgorgement for breach of contract reverses this wrong by subtracting the profits from the defendant and giving them back to the plaintiff to replenish the defendant’s loss. The remedy is restitutionary because it makes the defendant give back something gained at the expense of the plaintiff’s right, but it compensates for the plaintiff’s loss of something to which he had a right.Footnote 84

As discussed above, in Botterell’s argument, the work to show how disgorgement is compensatory in this way is done by the notion that a contract for particular performance gives rise to an implicit promise by the defendant to not act inconsistently with the plaintiff’s contractual rights. The difficulty here is that in the jurisprudence it is well settled that gain-based restitutionary remedies for subtractive unjust enrichment are not rooted in notions of implied promise.

It was historically thought that where a plaintiff mistakenly confers a benefit on a defendant and no contract exists between the parties, or where the benefit is conferred pursuant to a contract that is ineffective because unenforceable, the plaintiff had an action premised on what was referred to as “quasi ex contractu,” and the law would imply a promise and a quasi-contractual obligation on the part of the defendant to reimburse the plaintiff for the benefit conferred.Footnote 85 Since the early 20th century, common law courts have rejected this notion of “quasi-contract” as the basis of restitution for subtractive unjust enrichment.Footnote 86 There grew increasing recognition that the law of restitution is an independent practice separate from and on equal footing with other fundamental areas of private law such as contract and tort that is based on the unjust enrichment principle.Footnote 87 As Lord Hope of Craighead wrote in Kleinwort Benson Ltd v Lincoln City Council, “[t]he essence of this principle is that it is unjust for a person to retain a benefit which he has received at the expense of another, without any legal ground to justify its retention, which that other person did not intend him to receive.”Footnote 88

Corrective justice theorists may be hesitant to accept this formulation of the unjust enrichment principle as the justification for restitution. It concentrates on the normative situation of the defendant rather than normative considerations that apply equally to both plaintiff and defendant in their correlative situation.Footnote 89 Still, the jurisprudence indicates that any attempted reconciliation of disgorgement for breach of contract and corrective justice that construes the remedy as effectuating restitution for subtractive unjust enrichment should, as far as possible, avoid drawing upon what corrective justice theorists have referred to as “the pernicious view that a claim in unjust enrichment is based on an implied contract”Footnote 90 or “the fiction and the attendant confusion of understanding the law of unjust enrichment as the law of quasi-contract.”Footnote 91

In fairness, it may be argued that Botterell’s attempt, in resting on the notion of an implicit promise by the defendant to not act inconsistently with the plaintiff’s contractual rights, does not exactly replicate the defunct quasi-contractual doctrine. That doctrine presumes a defendant to impliedly promise to return non-consensually transferred benefits to the plaintiff. However, Botterell’s attempt still seems to come too close for comfort to quasi-contract. Even if there is a distance to travel, it is only a short step from a promise to not act inconsistently with the plaintiff’s contractual rights to a promise to return any gains derived from so acting.

It may also be argued that Botterell’s attempt is not inconsistent with contemporary private law doctrine in the manner I have suggested it is because the attempt does purport to explain the entire field of the law of unjust enrichment or restitution in terms of notions of quasi-contract. Certainly, the attempt does not have such a broad scope. But I have not claimed that it does. As I discussed earlier, Botterell’s account of disgorgement maintains that disgorgement for breach of contract is compensatory in nature. This characterization of the account naturally follows from the fact that it adheres to the basic tenet of corrective justice that a private law remedy restores to a plaintiff something to which a plaintiff has a prior right that the defendant breached by gaining that thing. For Botterell, the profit that a defendant receives by breaching a contract for particular performance after selling the unique object to be transferred to the plaintiff is something to which the plaintiff has an antecedent right. Disgorgement is compensatory because it gives back the profit to the plaintiff. Hence, it is a remedy for subtractive unjust enrichment that makes the defendant gives back something that he unjustly gained and that was subtracted from the plaintiff’s rightful holdings. My argument has been that the practice of contemporary private law and doctrine is unequivocal in holding that restitutionary remedies for canonical instances of subtractive unjust enrichment (such as situations where a plaintiff mistakenly confers a benefit on a defendant or does so under an unenforceable contract) are not based on quasi-contract, as I have argued that Botterell’s account of disgorgement for breach of contract is.

IV. Blake and Contractual Relationships that Resemble Fiduciary Relationships

The difficulties with Benson’s and Botterell’s attempts to reconcile disgorgement for breach of contract and corrective justice suggest that basing such an attempt on the rectification of a defendant’s violation of the plaintiff’s contractual rights by profiting from breach of contract may be misguided. But what other right of the plaintiff might a defendant violate by profiting from the breach? In what follows, I offer an interpretation of the Blake case that provides a clue to answering this question. Doing so accords with corrective justice’s aspiration to take private law doctrine at face value and understand it on its own terms as a distinctive normative practice whose immanent theoretical presuppositions must be uncovered.

The defendant in Blake, George Blake, was a former employee of the British intelligence service. Under his employment contract, he agreed not to divulge any official information he gained as a result of his employment.Footnote 92 He became an agent for the Soviet Union and remained so for ten years during his employment with the British government. During this time, he disclosed secret information to the Soviet Union. His treachery was uncovered, and he was sentenced to imprisonment in Britain. He then escaped from prison and fled to Moscow. In Moscow, he published his memoirs, which contained secret information related to his activities in the British intelligence service. That information was already public and its disclosure could not amount to a breach of confidence, and Blake’s employment as an intelligence officer did not impose a fiduciary duty on him. In a civil proceeding, the Crown sought disgorgement of the profits that Blake earned from the sale of his memoirs in breach of his employment contract.Footnote 93

Lord Nicholls reviewed past cases where courts awarded gain-based damages for private law wrongs ranging from tort to breach of contract, breach of fiduciary duty, and breach of confidence. He concluded that disgorgement for breach of contract should be available in exceptional cases where “the remedies of damages, specific performance and injunction, coupled with the characterisation of some contractual obligations as fiduciary,” do not provide an adequate response to the plaintiff’s loss of contractual rights.Footnote 94 He added:

No fixed rules can be prescribed. The court will have regard to all the circumstances, including the subject matter of the contract, the purpose of the contractual provision which has been breached, the circumstances in which the breach occurred, the consequences of the breach and the circumstances in which relief is being sought. A useful general guide, although not exhaustive, is whether the plaintiff had a legitimate interest in preventing the defendant’s profit-making activity and, hence, in depriving him of his profit.Footnote 95

He rejected the suggestions that disgorgement should be available in every case where the defendant skimps on performance and saves expenditures by failing to provide the full extent of services promised to the plaintiff or where the defendant does the very thing he contracted not to do.Footnote 96 He stated that “the fact that the breach was cynical and deliberate; the fact that the breach enabled the defendant to enter into a more profitable contract elsewhere; and the fact that by entering into a new and more profitable contract the defendant put it out of his power to perform his contract with the plaintiff” do not themselves provide a sufficient basis to award disgorgement for breach of contract.Footnote 97

The approach that emerges from Lord Nicholls’s opinion is open textured and fact specific. It is his analysis of the facts of Blake to which I wish to draw attention. He emphasized that the acts from which Blake profited by disclosing secret information in breach of his employment contract jeopardized the effectiveness of the British intelligence service by undermining its members’ morale and trust. He thereby “caused untold and immeasurable damage to the public interest he had committed himself to serve.”Footnote 98 This view of the wrong committed by Blake mirrors what is often thought to be the wrong committed by a fiduciary who breaches his duty of loyalty to a beneficiary by profiting from a fiduciary relationship. The protection of this relationship is seen to be necessary to promote values integral to public life, such as trust and confidence, and to protect human vulnerability and interdependence.Footnote 99 Indeed, Lord Nicholls went on to write that Blake’s contractual undertaking, “if not a fiduciary obligation, was closely akin to a fiduciary obligation, where an account of profits is a standard remedy in the event of breach.”Footnote 100 Lord Steyn echoed this statement in a separate opinion, noting that “the present case is closely analogous to that of fiduciaries.”Footnote 101

In concluding that disgorgement of Blake’s profits should be available to the Crown, Lord Nicholls drew a parallel between Blake and the United States Supreme Court decision in Snepp v United States.Footnote 102 In Snepp, a former member of the Central Intelligence Agency, Frank Snepp, published a book about the agency’s activities in South Vietnam. In so doing, he received a profit by breaching a term of his employment contract according to which he promised not to divulge any information about the agency without pre-publication clearance.Footnote 103 Emphasizing the high degree of trust involved between Snepp and the US government, the Supreme Court found that Snepp violated a fiduciary duty owed to the government. It ordered that a constructive trust be impressed on his profits in favour of the government as an “equitable and effective means of protecting intelligence that may contribute to national security.”Footnote 104 In Blake, Lord Nicholls stated that a remedy requiring Blake to disgorge his profits “is a different means to the same end” as that achieved by the United States Supreme Court in Snepp.Footnote 105

Thus, for Lord Nicholls, the open textured test for whether disgorgement for breach of contract ought to be available was satisfied in Blake because the facts of the case were such that the contractual relationship between Blake and the Crown was “akin to” or “closely analogous to” a fiduciary relationship. Blake’s receipt of profits by breaching the contract attracted disgorgement because it resembled a breach of fiduciary duty of loyalty to refrain from profiting from the fiduciary relationship. As John McCamus has observed,

It may well be, therefore, that a critical indicator of the appropriateness of disgorgement relief will be the extent to which the breach of contract in question engages the kinds of policy considerations that have traditionally provided the foundation for the development of the law of fiduciary obligation and its associated remedies. Broadly speaking, the law of fiduciary relations has as its purpose the facilitation and protection of relationships of trust and confidence, based in part on the assumption that the promotion of such relationships serves legitimate social ends. Though technically not a breach of fiduciary obligation, Blake’s wrongdoing does appear to be of a very similar kind.Footnote 106

Support for this reading of Blake can also be found in the decision of the Court of Queen’s Bench of Alberta in Indutech Canada Ltd v Gibbs Pipe Distributors Ltd,Footnote 107 one of the few Canadian decisions to feature an analysis of Lord Nicholls’s reasons in Blake.Footnote 108 The defendants were agents of the plaintiff principal. They were found to have profited from a breach of a fiduciary duty by competing with the plaintiff and accepting secret commissions in sales entered into on the plaintiff’s behalf. Justice Romaine also considered whether the defendants’ actions constituted a breach of contract with the plaintiff. She concluded that, if she were mistaken to find a breach of fiduciary duty, disgorgement of profits for breach of contract would have been available to the plaintiff. After reviewing the relevant jurisprudence, including Blake, she stated that disgorgement should be available if a contractual relationship, “while not amounting to a fiduciary relationship, is akin to a fiduciary relationship.”Footnote 109 In the case at bar, although the relationship between the parties “did not give rise to fiduciary obligations, it was so close and the breaches so broad, deliberate and immediate to the execution of the [contract] that they were … as offensive and wrongful as many breaches of fiduciary obligations.”Footnote 110

A form of the reasoning found in Blake, according to which disgorgement is appropriate where a contractual relationship is closely akin to a fiduciary relationship and where the breach of contract engages the kinds of normative considerations that ground fiduciary obligations, is even discernible in the decision of the Supreme Court of Israel in Adras.Footnote 111 As mentioned at the outset of this paper, Adras involved a contract for the sale of steel, and when the price of steel rose the defendant sold the steel it promised to sell to the defendant to a third party at a higher price and realized a profit. Justice Barak wrote the Supreme Court’s leading opinion. He ordered that the defendant’s breach of contract be remedied by awarding the plaintiff the profits realized by the defendant on the sale of the steel to the third party. He recognized that the defendant’s breach was economically efficient in the sense that it enabled it to realize a greater economic gain by breaching and giving the plaintiff the monetary value of the steel than it would have realized by performing its contractual duty, while leaving the plaintiff in a position that was no worse off than it would have been had the contract been performed.Footnote 112 However, he rejected the idea that the plaintiff should not be awarded the defendant’s wrongful gain on this basis. He wrote as follows:

Moreover, it seems to me that the economic approach does not give enough weight to considerations which cannot be measured in economic terms. The law of contract is not only meant to increase economic efficiency but also to enable society to lead a proper life. Contracts are there to be performed, whether or not damages to be payable on breach, an approach by which we encourage people to keep their promises. Promise keeping is the basis of our life as a society and a nation.Footnote 113

Thus, for Justice Barak, it was appropriate to award disgorgement for breach of contract in Adras because doing so vindicated the social morality of promise keeping.Footnote 114 This approach parallels that taken in Blake, which suggests that disgorgement should be available if a breach of contract engages the need to promote the social values of trust, confidence, and the protection of human vulnerability and interdependence that ground recognition of fiduciary obligations.

I submit that the lesson to learn from Blake, Snepp, and Indutech, and even Adras, is that the remedy of disgorgement of profits for breach of contract is appropriate in cases where a contractual relationship between plaintiff and defendant overlaps with a concurrent fiduciary-like relationship existing between the parties. None of these cases supports the contention, made by Benson and Botterell, that disgorgement is appropriate where a contract is for particular performance involving the transfer of a unique object from promisor to promisee. The project of developing a corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract would therefore be well served by clarifying how corrective justice is consistent with disgorgement for breach of fiduciary duty. Thus, in the next Part, I will discuss Paul Miller’s approach to this issue.

V. Miller’s Corrective Justice Account of Disgorgement for Breach of Fiduciary Duty

According to Miller, the starting point for understanding disgorgement for breach of a fiduciary’s duty of loyalty is to recognize that fiduciary duties arise out of a special and distinctive kind of legal relationship.Footnote 115 The canonical definition of a fiduciary relationship is that the fiduciary exercises discretionary power over the practical interests of the beneficiary.Footnote 116 This definition reveals that the relationship has certain “definitive properties”Footnote 117 that establish what kind of legal relationship it is and entail essential “structural properties”Footnote 118 of the relationship.

For Miller, the basic definitive property of a fiduciary relationship concerns the nature of the discretionary power exercised by the fiduciary. That power is a form of authority to exercise discretion, i.e., to use judgment in determining whether or how it should be exercised, that is derived from the legal personality, i.e., the “individual legal capacities,” of the beneficiary.Footnote 119 It is wielded relative to the practical interests of the beneficiary, including “matters of personality, welfare, or right susceptible to the exercise of legal capacity.”Footnote 120 The structural properties entailed by these definitive properties are that the fiduciary is in an unequal position of dominance relative to the beneficiary, who is dependent on the fiduciary’s power. The fiduciary “exercises a capacity for and on behalf of the beneficiary and the latter, by virtue of this substitution, becomes subject to the will of the fiduciary.”Footnote 121 That the authority wielded by the fiduciary is over the beneficiary’s practical interests entails that the fiduciary is vulnerable to have his interests set back or adversely influenced by the fiduciary’s power.Footnote 122

These properties of fiduciary relationships in turn entail that the fiduciary is under a duty of loyalty to avoid conflict between the interests of the beneficiary and his own interests or the interests of third parties. The correlative right of the beneficiary is that the fiduciary must avoid conflicts of interest. Fiduciary disloyalty consists in violating this right by entering into conflicts.Footnote 123 Miller claims that the features of a fiduciary relationship and the rights and duties it contains means that “what the fiduciary is to do, loyally, is to act on the legal capacity of another in setting and pursuing certain practical interests of the beneficiary.”Footnote 124

Because the fiduciary’s power is a form of authority derived from the legal personality of the beneficiary, it amounts to the beneficiary’s investment of his legal capacity in the fiduciary, who correlatively assumes that capacity. It changes the normative situation between the parties by imposing new rights and duties of loyalty because it involves “a form of substitution of legal personality. Fiduciary powers are legal capacities of other persons. In wielding them, fiduciaries stand in as substitutes for those persons within the ambit of their power(s).”Footnote 125 Miller therefore holds that fiduciary power is “a means belonging rightfully to [the beneficiary] for it is but an extension of her legal personality.”Footnote 126

A person’s legal capacity—such as his exercise of rights and powers, his ability to be placed under obligations, or susceptibility to liability—is a tool that, like property, enables him to pursue his practical interests.Footnote 127 When a beneficiary’s legal capacity is invested in the fiduciary, the fiduciary’s capacity to exercise discretion in a way that affects the beneficiary’s practical interests is substituted for that of the beneficiary. To say that the fiduciary has a duty of loyalty to exercise his discretion in the best interests of the beneficiary is to say that the fiduciary must do so as the beneficiary’s “alter ego.”Footnote 128 The beneficiary thus acquires an ownership right to the beneficiary’s loyal exercise of discretionary power. The fiduciary violates this right, and breaches a correlative duty of loyalty, by misappropriating the power and using it as a means to achieve ends that conflict with the beneficiary’s practical interests. The beneficiary’s right to the fiduciary’s power “is like the right to exclusive possession and use enjoyed by an owner in that it has the effect of excluding competing claims on a means.”Footnote 129

So, upon the creation of a fiduciary relationship, a beneficiary substitutes his legal capacity in relation to the pursuit of his practical interests with that of the fiduciary. He acquires a right of ownership to the fiduciary’s exercise of discretion in the interests of the beneficiary, and the fiduciary is placed under a correlative obligation to refrain from using that discretionary power to advance other interests. Miller argues that if the fiduciary breaches the duty of loyalty by entering in to a conflict of interest and “receives an unauthorized profit from the exercise of fiduciary power, she treats the power as a means of her own.”Footnote 130 He usurps that power, which rightfully belongs to the beneficiary. The beneficiary therefore must be understood as acquiring a right or “an entitlement to profits realized through the exercise of fiduciary power” and, to the extent that the fiduciary realizes profits by exercising his power, the fiduciary has a correlative duty “to see to it that the beneficiary alone receives [the profits].”Footnote 131

A court order requiring the fiduciary to disgorge those profits to the beneficiary is consistent with corrective justice because it corrects the defendant’s violation of the beneficiary’s right to the profits. The beneficiary has a right to the profits that accrue from the fiduciary’s disloyal exercise of discretion in conflict with the beneficiary’s interests because he has an ownership right to that power in virtue of having invested his legal capacity in the fiduciary. Miller therefore maintains that disgorgement for breach of the fiduciary duty effectuates corrective justice because it restores to the beneficiary something to which he had an antecedent right.Footnote 132

VI. A Corrective Justice Account of Disgorgement for Breach of Contract by Analogy to Fiduciary Remedies

Learning from the Blake decision that disgorgement of profits for breach of contract is appropriate when contractual relationships are analogous to fiduciary relationships, and adopting Miller’s corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of fiduciary duty, I will now propose a corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract by analogy with fiduciary remedies. The account makes the following assertions.

Some contractual relationships establish a concurrent fiduciary-like relationship between plaintiff and defendant. They establish in the plaintiff a right to the defendant’s exercise of discretionary power in virtue of the investment of the plaintiff’s legal capacity in the defendant. This right correlates with the defendant’s duty to refrain from disloyally engaging in conflicts of interest and misappropriating the plaintiff’s right to the loyal exercise of discretion in the plaintiff’s interests. The defendant’s duty includes a duty to refrain from profiting from the disloyal exercise of discretionary power and correlates with a right of the plaintiff to those profits. In these cases, disgorgement of profits for failure to discharge the duty corrects a wrong done to the plaintiff by giving back to the plaintiff something to which he had a prior right.

Before developing the account, I will make some preliminary remarks that are designed to anticipate and preempt objections. These remarks set the stage for the claim that a contractual relationship can be accompanied by a fiduciary-like relationship that brings into existence rights and duties of loyalty and that a breach of a contractual duty can amount to a concurrent breach of a fiduciary-like duty.

A. Preliminary Remarks

On a corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract by analogy with fiduciary remedies, a contractual relationship must be construed as distinct from any fiduciary-like relationship arising between the contracting parties, yet still influencing that relationship. The rights and duties created by the fiduciary-like relationship are separate from the parties’ contractual rights and duties, even if the violation of the plaintiff’s contractual right can amount to a violation of his separate right to the defendant’s loyal exercise of discretionary power.

Fiduciary rights and duties arise when a fiduciary relationship exists. A fiduciary relationship is a distinctive kind of legal relationship. So is a contractual relationship. A person’s acquisition of contractual rights is normatively justified by the bilateral consent of the parties to the relationship. When a person incurs a contractual obligation to perform a specific act, he does so only because he consents to perform that act. He puts himself under the obligation. The requirement to perform is not a limitation but an expression of his freedom because it derives from his consent.Footnote 133

By contrast, a fiduciary relationship is based on the relative status of the parties to the relationship. It is asymmetrical and unequal. When the beneficiary invests legal capacity in the fiduciary and acquires a right to the fiduciary’s discretionary power, the fiduciary holds a position of dominance over a beneficiary, whose practical interests’ advancement depends on and is vulnerable to the fiduciary’s discretion. The fiduciary’s authority to exercise discretion in relation to the beneficiary’s interests is an authority to judge whether and how this discretion should be exercised. It follows, contrary to what some have argued,Footnote 134 that fiduciary relationships are not justified by the consent of the beneficiary. After investing legal capacity in the fiduciary, the beneficiary cannot consent to the manner in which the fiduciary exercises discretionary power because the exercise of this power is dependent on the fiduciary’s judgment. Arthur Ripstein writes that “the beneficiary is not in a position to consent or decline to consent,” and that “the inherent inequality or vulnerability of the relationship makes consent necessarily problematic.”Footnote 135 In short, whereas the bilateral normativity of contractual relationships is marked by the parties’ consensual independence, that of fiduciary relationships is marked by the parties’ interdependence.

Fiduciary relationships can be, and frequently are, created by contract, and the parties can consent ex ante to adjust the terms of fiduciary rights and duties. But the normative justification of fiduciary relationships is not reducible to consent or capable of being understood in terms of contract. For one thing, it is not necessary for a fiduciary relationship to be founded on consent—the parent-child fiduciary relationship provides an example.Footnote 136 More fundamentally, once a person invests legal capacity in another, even by contract or consent, the bilateral norms implicated in the parties’ interaction change, are imposed objectively by law, and outrun the parties’ voluntary expressions of their wills.

The nature of contractual obligation presupposes the independence of the parties, who interact at arm’s length and mutually disinterestedly.Footnote 137 When a person consents to put himself under a contractual obligation, his obligation expresses his freedom in that it constrains him to behave only as he dictated ex ante at contract formation. He need not go any further than performing the specific act that he consented to perform (subject only to a requirement of good faith performanceFootnote 138). Other than looking to the terms of the specific act he initially consented to perform as a self-imposed limit on the pursuit of his own interests, the promisor need not altruistically promote the interests of the promisee as they develop ex post. Because contractual obligations are fixed ex ante by consent at contract formation in this way, the parties, as Daniel Markovits observes, “engage each other only through the medium and on the terms of their contracts,” and a promisor “takes her promisee’s intentions, as expressed in the contract, at face value. She need not … engage her promisee in any other respect, including altruistically, in respect of her ex post beliefs about his interests.”Footnote 139

A promisee’s investment of his legal capacity in the promisor, even if by consent, alters the promisor’s duties in giving the promisor discretionary power to affect the promisee’s practical interests. The parties now interact, not simply through the medium of a contract, but through their interdependence. The promisee—now a beneficiary—is vulnerable to and dependent on the promisor’s—now the fiduciary’s—exercise of discretionary power in respect of his practical interests. The fiduciary’s duty is now to exercise his discretion in way that avoids bringing himself into a conflict of interest. His pursuit of others’ interests is not now limited only by the ex ante consensual terms of his contract with the beneficiary, but also by the ex post and variable interests of the beneficiary, which he cannot now ignore and must take into account. The fiduciary must take an open-ended initiative in pursuing the interests of the beneficiary as a surrogate for the legal capacity of the beneficiary and exercise discretion, not in a self-interested or disinterested fashion, but in an other-regarding fashion that is shaped by the beneficiary’s interests. The open-endedness of the fiduciary’s mandate requires him to judge how to he must sometimes go further than what is consented to ex ante in any contract to secure the beneficiary’s ex post interests. He must make his determination independently of the beneficiary’s consent, subject not to the will expressed in the contract but to the legal regime regulating fiduciaries and enforceable by courts.Footnote 140

A corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract by analogy to fiduciary remedies must preserve the irreducibility of the fiduciary-like relationships it posits to those contractual relationships with which they overlap. Fiduciary and contractual relationships must be treated as distinctive, yet interrelated. The former are consent-based while latter are status-based.

B. Developing the Account

Two questions must now be answered. First, how can a contract sometimes give rise to a distinct fiduciary-like relationship between plaintiff and defendant and impart to the plaintiff a right to the defendant’s loyal exercise of discretionary power? Second, how can a profitable breach of the contract constitute a breach of this right of the plaintiff such that disgorgement of profits restores to the plaintiff something that he had an antecedent right to?

To soften the reader, at the outset I note that the cohabitation or overlapping of a contractual and a fiduciary-like relationship is not a phenomenon that is foreign to private law. It is a familiar feature of employment contracts. Employment contracts are created voluntarily by employer and employee. But, unlike contracts for services, they incorporate a certain amount of indefiniteness in that the employee consents to open-endedly perform a set of tasks for and receive direction from the employer in exchange for wages.Footnote 141 The employee incurs a duty of loyalty to act in the best interests of the employer in carrying out his job responsibilities that the employee breaches by, for example, appropriating the employer’s confidential trade secrets learned in the course of work and using them to assist a competitor’s business.Footnote 142 He also incurs a duty to obey reasonable orders issued by the employer.Footnote 143 The control exerted over the employee by the employer entails that the employee sometimes acts as a surrogate for the employer’s legal capacity, such as when he enters into contracts on behalf of the employer or commits a tort for which the employer is held vicariously liable.Footnote 144 The economic dependence of the employee on the employer also imposes on the employer a duty to give reasonable notice of termination of the employment contract and a duty of good faith in the manner of termination.Footnote 145 These features of employment contracts indicate that they are characterized by the cohabitation of a consensual relationship and elements of a kind of status relationship between the parties.

In general, a fiduciary-like relationship is superimposed over a contractual relationship between promisor and promisee in cases where the factual circumstances gathered together and encompassed by the parties’ transaction, including the subject matter of the contract and the specific acts acquired by the parties, are such as to bring into existence, in addition to contractual rights and obligations, the definitive and structural properties of fiduciary relationships identified by Miller. In such cases, the promisor’s exercise of discretionary power has the potential to affect the promisee’s practical interests. The promisor’s authority to do this displaces the parties’ ex ante independence in that the promisee becomes dependent on and vulnerable to the promisor’s exercise of discretion ex post.

An example is where the facts encompassed by the parties’ transaction include the promisor’s receipt of confidential information of the promisee such that the promisor’s discretionary power to disclose that information can set back the promisee’s practical interests. For example, as in Blake and in other employment contracts, the promisor may exchange services for wages and, in the course of his service, gain access to confidential information. Or, the promisee may share confidential information, such as architectural blueprints or the location of valuable resources, with the promisor as part of a joint business venture.Footnote 146 In these cases, the discretionary power of the promisor to disclose the confidential information would adversely affect the promisee’s interests, such as his interests in competitive or financial advantage (or, where the promisee is a government entity as in Blake, the public interest). Therefore, under Miller’s principles, a kind of status relationship characterized by the promisee’s dependence and vulnerability to the promisor’s discretionary power comes to cohabit with the parties’ consent-based contractual relationship.

To be sure, in many ordinary contractual relationships, the promisor’s failure to perform the act he consented to perform can set back the practical interests of the promisee. The promisee then becomes vulnerable to and dependent on the promisor’s choice to perform his contractual duty. This will occur, of course, only if completion of the relevant transaction is beneficial to the promisee. However, setting this point aside, it does not follow from the possibility of any breach of contract setting back a party’s practical interests that every contract gives rise to an overlapping status relationship that requires the promisor to adjust his pursuit of his own interests to safeguard the promisee’s ex post interests. In ordinary contractual relationships, the promisee may have the factual ability to choose whether to advance the promisee’s practical interests by performing his contractual duty. But he lacks the rightful power to exercise discretion over whether to do so. Indeed, he is rightfully constrained to perform the act he consented to perform. By his consent he puts himself under a juridical obligation to perform that act. Hence, the definitive and structural properties of fiduciary relationships identified by Miller do not materialize.

A status relationship comes to be superimposed over the parties’ consent-based contractual relationship only where it can be said that the promisor has the rightful power, rather than a mere factual ability, to exercise discretion in a manner that affects the promisee’s practical interests. This power exists only where the objective circumstances are such that, irrespective of what the parties consented to, the private law regime sees fit to impose on the promisor a duty of loyalty to exercise this discretionary power in the promisee’s best interests in virtue of the promisee’s investment of legal capacity in the promisor. In these special contractual relationships where the promisor’s discretionary power can affect the promisee’s interests, the promisee’s legal capacity—a tool used to advance the promisee’s interests—is invested in the promisor. Because the promisee has a right to and ownership of his legal capacity, he retains a right to it when it is invested in the promisor in the form of the promisor’s discretionary power to affect the promisee’s interests. He thus has a right, added to his contractual right, that the promisor exercise discretion loyally and not in conflict with the promisee’s interests. This right correlates with the promisor’s duty to avoid disloyal conflicts of interest. It adds to but outruns his ex ante-consented-to contractual duty to perform the act alienated through the contract and requires him to tailor his exercise of discretion in accordance with the promisee’s ex post interests.

Now, there is an important caveat to note. The kind of status relationship superimposed over but distinct from the parties’ contractual relationship on the account of disgorgement for breach of contract developed here is, as suggested by the Lord Nicholls and Lord Steyn in Blake, not a fully-fledged fiduciary relationship, but “akin to” or “closely analogous to” a fiduciary relationship. This is because the scope of the promisor’s duty of loyalty is circumscribed by the factual circumstances encompassed by the parties’ transaction, and, more precisely, the particular practical interests of the promisee that are potentially affected by the promisor’s exercise of discretionary power as defined by those circumstances. The duty owes its existence to the status of interdependence and vulnerability set up by the facts immediately surrounding the contract, which include but are not exhausted by the contractual obligations the parties consensually impose on themselves ex ante. The contract brings together facts that establish the interests that the promisor must loyally avoid coming into conflict with. It is only these interests to which the promisor must adjust his ex post exercise of discretion to in order to avoid a conflict of interest.

To illustrate, consider the contract discussed above involving the transfer of confidential information about the location of a valuable resource between promisor and promisee as part of a joint venture. The promisor’s duty of loyalty arising out of the facts of this contractual relationship is circumscribed. It requires avoiding conflict with only those practical interests of the promisee, such as the interest in financial gain from the joint venture, that are implicated in the facts encompassed by the contract. The promisor need not, pursuant to this specific duty of loyalty, avoid conflicts with the promisee’s interest in, say, competent litigation in a civil proceeding, as he would if he were the promisee’s solicitor and therefore a fully-fledged fiduciary.Footnote 147

So, on the account of disgorgement for breach of contract developed here, the facts immediately surrounding the contractual relationship between the promisor and promisee anchor the right to the promisor’s loyal exercise of discretionary power that the promisee acquires in cases where a kind of status relationship additionally obtains between the parties. That status relationship cohabiting with the contract, therefore, does not rise to the level of a fully-fledged fiduciary relationship. A fiduciary relationship, as we have seen, does not necessarily arise out of a contractual relationship between fiduciary and beneficiary. Rather, it requires the fiduciary to exercise discretion in relation to the beneficiary’s ex post interests in a more open-ended way that is defined by the totality of the facts constituting the parties’ interdependence and vulnerability, including those facts not gathered together by any contract.

Consider an example of a contractual agreement that creates a status relationship between the parties that does amount to a fiduciary relationship, such as a contract for the transfer of antibiotics from doctor to patient. The fiduciary doctor’s duty of loyalty requires him to avoid conflict with the beneficiary patient’s interest in receiving medical services by, say, giving the patient drugs from whose distribution the doctor receives profit from a pharmaceutical company. But this duty is not circumscribed by the facts of the parties’ contract for the transfer of drugs. It requires the doctor to avoid conflicting with other interests of the patient that are defined by the totality of facts constituting the parties’ interdependence and vulnerability without regard to the contract. Thus, the doctor breaches the fiduciary duty of loyalty (while committing criminal and other private law wrongs) by sexually exploiting the patient.Footnote 148

Let us now turn to the second question—concerning how the promisor’s breach of contract in order to receive profit from a third party constitutes a breach of the promisee’s right to the promisor’s loyal exercise of discretionary power. It must be emphasized that, on the account of disgorgement for breach of contract developed here, a contractual relationship with which a fiduciary-like relationship overlaps is distinct from but influences the fiduciary-like relationship because its normative character is grounded in consent rather than status. Through it, the promisee acquires the promisor’s performance of a specific act, which the promisor consensually alienates. He does not acquire a contractual right to the promisor’s open-ended exercise of discretion. It is only through the concurrent status relationship that the promisee invests his legal capacity in the promisor and acquires a right to the promisor’s discretionary power. Hence, the account developed here contrasts with Benson’s and Botterell’s accounts of disgorgement for breach of contract. Benson and Botterell maintain that disgorgement is appropriate in cases of contracts for particular performance where the promisor profits from the alienation of something that the promisee owns as part of the promisee’s contractual rights.

Yet, on the account developed here, profitable breach of a contract that is concurrent with but distinct from a fiduciary-like relationship can cause a breach of the duty of loyalty entailed by the latter relationship. The contractual breach, to use a phrase coined by Birks, can function as a “causative event”Footnote 149 of the breach of duties entailed by the concurrent fiduciary-like relationship on this account. But it does not at the same time function as the normative wrong that the latter breach represents and that the private law remedy of disgorgement corrects. The relevant normative wrong instead consists in a breach of a concurrent duty of loyalty. This breach stems from the investment of legal capacity in the promisor by the promisee that gives the promisee ownership of the promisor’s discretionary power. In turn, it constitutes a causative event that gives rise to the central reason for imposing liability to the promisee on the promisor.Footnote 150 In this respect, a profitable breach of contract can give rise to liability to disgorge those profits even though it does so only by causing a profitable breach of the terms of an overlapping status-based relationship.

Thus, just as the movement of a puppeteer’s hand can pull strings to cause movement in a marionette puppet without the puppeteer being identical to the puppet, the promisor’s failure to perform the act that he has a contractual duty to perform, in violation of the promisee’s correlative contractual right to that act’s performance, in order to gain a profit from a third party can cause the promisor to come into conflict with the practical interests of the promisee as defined by the facts encompassed by the parties’ contractual relationship. Recall that it is these interests, as argued above, that are affected by the promisor’s exercise of discretionary power. They define the scope of the promisor’s fiduciary-like duty to exercise discretion loyally and without conflict with others’ interests, including the promisor’s own interests.

Because the concurrent status relationship between the parties invests the promisee’s legal capacity in the promisor, the promisee acquires an ownership right to the promisor’s discretionary power. The promisor misappropriates this right, and he treats it as his own to use to pursue his own interests, when he enters into a conflict with the promisee’s interests by failing to perform the act acquired by the promisor through the parties’ contractual relationship in order to pursue his own interest in profit. The promisee had a right to the profits as surely as he had ownership of his own legal capacity when substituted with the promisor’s discretionary power. The promisor violates this right by receiving the profits in his capacity as a surrogate for the promisee’s legal capacity through the exercise of his discretion in conflict with the promisee’s interests. A court order in a civil proceeding that requires the promisor to give the profits back to the promisee therefore restores to the promisee something to which he had a prior right that was infringed by the promisor, as is mandated by the normative principles of corrective justice.

This completes the development of the corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract by analogy to fiduciary remedies. Before concluding, it may prove helpful to illustrate the account using an example.

Suppose that a plaintiff and a defendant enter into a contractual relationship whereby the plaintiff agrees to share confidential architectural blueprints with the defendant as part of a joint venture. Suppose also that the plaintiff acquires a right to the defendant’s performance of the specific act of constructing a building to be used to operate the joint venture. The defendant’s power to exercise discretion as to whether to disclose the blueprints to a competitor can set back the plaintiff’s interest in financial gain from the joint venture. It creates a status relationship between the parties, with the plaintiff now vulnerable to and dependent on the defendant’s exercise of discretionary power, that cohabits with their contractual relationship. Suppose that the defendant breaches the contract by failing to perform the act of construction in order to save on expenditures and sell the blueprints to the plaintiff’s competitor and gain a profit. Corrective justice stipulates that this infringement of the plaintiff’s contractual right entitles him to the value of the defendant’s performance.

However, concurrent with this liability to pay expectation damages, the defendant has put his own interest in profit into conflict with the plaintiff’s interest in financial gain or competitive advantage from the joint venture. The fiduciary-like relationship overlapping with the parties’ contractual relationship invests the plaintiff’s legal capacity to pursue his financial and competitive interests in the defendant and gives the plaintiff an ownership right to the defendant’s loyal exercise of discretionary power in matters affecting these particular interests of the plaintiff. It also gave him a right to the profits accruing from the exercise of this power in conflict with these interests. The defendant had a correlative duty to avoid coming into conflict with the plaintiff’s financial and competitive interests, as those interests are defined by the factual circumstances encompassed and gathered together by the parties’ contract, and profiting as a result. The defendant’s failure to perform his contractual obligation therefore caused him to violate this duty and the plaintiff’s correlative right. Corrective justice stipulates that the defendant must disgorge the profits he received and restore them to the plaintiff. This remedy corrects the defendant’s violation of the plaintiff’s right to the profits and gives back something to which the plaintiff had a right to all along.

VII. Conclusion

In this paper, I have attempted to reconcile the private law remedy of disgorgement of profits for breach of contract with the normative principles of corrective justice by developing an account of the remedy by analogy to fiduciary remedies. The principles of corrective justice hold that a private law remedy corrects an injustice suffered by a plaintiff at the defendant’s hands by giving back to the plaintiff something to which the plaintiff had a right that the defendant infringed by breaching a duty not to interfere with that right.

I have argued that extant attempts by Benson and Botterell to reconcile disgorgement with corrective justice, which appeal to cases in which disgorgement of profits received by the defendant from a third party by breaching a contract restores to the plaintiff something to which he was entitled in virtue of his contractual rights, are unsuccessful. But I have not reached the conclusion reached by Weinrib that disgorgement is irreconcilable with corrective justice.

Drawing on the insight of the House of Lords decision in Blake, and from recent scholarship on the compatibility of disgorgement for profits for breach of fiduciary duty and corrective justice, the corrective justice account of disgorgement for breach of contract by analogy to fiduciary remedies developed in this paper holds that the right of the plaintiff that a disgorgement remedy is responsive to is not a contractual right but a right to the defendant’s exercise of discretionary power. The factual circumstances surrounding some contractual relationships give rise to a separate status-based fiduciary-like relationship that cohabits or overlaps with the contractual relationship. In such circumstances, the plaintiff’s legal capacity is invested in the defendant and the plaintiff acquires an ownership right to the defendant’s loyal exercise of discretionary power. The defendant comes under a correlative duty to avoid conflict with the interests of the plaintiff that are defined by the parties’ contractual relationship. Because the plaintiff owns his legal capacity, he retains this ownership when it is substituted for the defendant’s discretionary power, and he acquires a right to the profits accruing from the exercise of this power. The defendant’s breach of the contract between the parties to receive a profit from a third party causes his exercise of discretionary power to be disloyal because it causes it to conflict with the plaintiff’s interests, as they are defined by the factual circumstances surrounding the contract. He thereby breaches a fiduciary-like duty to refrain from interfering with the plaintiff’s right to the loyal exercise of the defendant’s discretionary power. Disgorgement of these profits to the plaintiff is therefore consistent with corrective justice because it restores to the plaintiff something to which he had a right all along.

References

1. For early cases suggesting the availability of the remedy, see, e.g., Reid-Newfoundland Company v Anglo-American Telegraph Company, [1912] AC 555 (PC); British Motor Trade Association v Gilbert, [1951] 2 All ER 641, 2 TLR 514 (Ch); Lake v Bayliss, [1974] 2 All ER 1114, [1974] 1 WLR 1073 (Ch); Wrotham Park Estate Co Ltd v Parkside Homes Ltd, [1974] 2 All ER 321, [1974] 1 WLR 798 (Ch).

2. Adras Building Material Ltd v Harlow & Jones Gmbh, [1995] 3 RLR 235 (Supreme Court of Israel, 1988) [Adras].

3. Robinson v Harmon (1848), 1 Exch 850, 154 ER 363; Wertheim v Chicoutimi Pulp Co, [1911] AC 301 (PC); Asamera Oil Corporation Ltd v Sea Oil & General Corporation et al, [1979] 1 SCR 633 at 645, 89 DLR (3d) 1; Keneric Tractor Sales Ltd v Langille, [1987] 2 SCR 440 at 456, 43 DLR (4th) 171.

4. For a comparative discussion, see Roberts, Caprice L, “A Commonwealth of Perspective on Restitutionary Disgorgement for Breach of Contract” (2008) 65:3Google Scholar Wash & Lee L Rev 945 at 953-61.

5. [2001], 4 All ER 385, 1 AC 268 (HL) [Blake HL, cited to All ER].

6. IBM Canada Limited v Waterman, 2013 SCC 70 at para 36, 3 SCR 985. See also Bank of America Canada v Mutual Trust Co, 2002 SCC 43 at paras 30-31, 2 SCR 601 (stating only that awards of contract damages based on the defendant’s gain might sometimes conflict with the desirability of permitting efficient breach).

7. Phillips v Homfray (1883), 24 Ch D 439, 52 LJ Ch 833 (CA); Edwards v Lee’s Administrator, 265 Ky 418, 96 SW 2d 1028 (CA, 1936); United Australia Ltd v Barclays Bank Ltd, [1940] 4 All ER 20, [1941] AC 1 (HL); Olwell v Nye and Nissen, 26 Wn2d 282, 173 P2d 652 (Sup Ct, 1946).

8. Keech v Sanford, [1726] All ER Rep 230, 25 ER 223; Boardman v Phipps, [1967] 2 AC 46, 3 All ER 721 (HL); Strother v 3464920 Canada Inc, 2007 SCC 24, 2 SCR 177 [Strother].

9. Lac Minerals Ltd v International Corona Resources Ltd, [1989] 2 SCR 574, 61 DLR (4th) 14 [Lac Minerals]; Cadbury Schweppes Inc v FBI Foods Ltd, [1999] 1 SCR 142, 167 DLR (4th) 577.

10. Andrew Botterell, Book Review of Accounting for Breach of Contract: Theory and Practice by Katy Barnett (2013) 54:1 Can Bus LJ 99 at 99 (“This is a welcome publication, as disgorgement damages continue to present both theoretical and practical puzzles for the law of contract”).

11. See, e.g., Friedmann, Daniel, “Restitution of Benefits Obtained through the Appropriation of Property or the Commission of a Wrong” (1980) 80:3Google Scholar Colum L Rev 504 [Friedman, “Restitution of Benefits”]; Jones, Gareth, “The Recovery of Benefits Gained from a Breach of Contract” (1983) 99:3Google Scholar Law Q Rev 443; Farnsworth, Allan E, “Your Loss or My Gain? The Dilemma of the Disgorgement Principle in Breach of Contract” (1985) 94:6Google Scholar Yale LJ 1339; Birks, Peter, “Restitutionary damages for breach of contract: Snepp and the fusion of law and equity” [1987]Google Scholar LMCLQ 421 [Birks, “Restitutionary Damages”]; Beatson, Jack, The Use and Abuse of Unjust Enrichment (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991) at 15-17Google Scholar; Waddams, SM, “Restitution as Part of Contract Law” in Burrows, Andrew, ed, Essays on the Law of Restitution (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991) 197Google Scholar; Burrows, Andrew, “No restitutionary damages for breach of contract” [1993]Google Scholar LMCLQ 453; Smith, Lionel D, “Disgorgement of the Profits of Breach of Contract: Property, Contract and ‘Efficient Breach’” (1994) 24:1Google Scholar Can Bus LJ 121; Jaffey, Peter, “Restitutionary Damages and Disgorgement” (1995) 3Google Scholar RLR 30; Chen-Wishart, Mindy, “Restitutionary Damages for Breach of Contract” (1998) 114:3Google Scholar Law Q Rev 363; McInnes, Mitchell, “Gain-Based Relief for Breach of Contract: Attorney General v. Blake (2001) 35:1Google Scholar Can Bus LJ 72; Kull, Andrew, “Disgorgement for Breach, the ‘Restitution Interest,’ and the Restatement of Contracts” (2001) 79:9Google Scholar Tex L Rev 2021; Edelman, James, Gain-Based Damages: Contract, Tort, Equity, and Intellectual Property (Portland, OR: Hart, 2002); John D McCamus, “Disgorgement for Breach of Contract: A Comparative Perspective” (2003) 36:2Google Scholar Loy LA L Rev 943 [McCamus, “Disgorgement”]; Roberts, Caprice L, “Restitutionary Disgorgement as a Moral Compass for Breach of Contract” (2009) 77:3Google Scholar U Cin L Rev 991; Roberts, Caprice L, “Restitutionary Disgorgement for Opportunistic Breach of Contract and Mitigation of Damages” (2008) 42:1Google Scholar Loy LA L Rev 131; Barnett, Katy, Accounting for Breach of Contract: Theory and Practice (Oxford: Hart, 2012).Google Scholar

12. Palsgraf v The Long Island Railway Company, 248 NY 339 at 344-45, 162 NE 99 (CA, 1928).

13. Ibid at 345.

14. Weinrib, Ernest J, Corrective Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar at ch 5 [Weinrib, Corrective Justice]; Weinrib, Ernest, “Punishment and Disgorgement as Contract Remedies” (2003) 78:1Google Scholar Chicago-Kent L Rev 55 [Weinrib, “Punishment and Disgorgement”].

15. See, e.g., Weinrib, Ernest J, “Restitutionary Damages as Corrective Justice” (2000) 1:1Google Scholar Theor Inq L 1 [Weinrib, “Restitutionary Damages”]; Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at ch 6; Mitchell McInnes, “The Measure of Restitution” (2002) 52:2 UTLJ 163; Smith, Lionel, “Restitution: The Heart of Corrective Justice” (2001) 79:7Google Scholar Tex L Rev 2115 [L Smith, “Heart of Corrective Justice”]. But see Smith, Stephen A, “Justifying the Law of Unjust Enrichment” 79:7Google Scholar Tex L Rev 2177 at 2190; Klimchuk, Dennis, “Unjust Enrichment and Corrective Justice” in Nyers, Jason W, McInnes, Mitchell & Stephan, GA Pitel, eds, Understanding Unjust Enrichment (Portland, OR: Hart, 2004)Google Scholar [Nyers, McInnes & Pitel, Understanding Unjust Enrichment] 110; Priel, Dan, “The Justice in Unjust Enrichment” (2014) 51:3Google Scholar Osgoode Hall LJ 813 [Priel, “Justice in Unjust Enrichment”].

16. See, e.g., Weinrib, Ernest J, “The Gains and Losses of Corrective Justice” (1994) 44:2Google Scholar Duke LJ 277; Weinrib, “Restitutionary Damages,” supra note 15; Weinrib, “Punishment and Disgorgement,” supra note 14; Peter Benson, “Disgorgement for Breach of Contract and Corrective Justice: An Analysis in Outline” in Nyers, McInnes & Pitel, Understanding Unjust Enrichment, supra note 15, 311 at 313-20 [Benson, “Disgorgement”]; Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at ch 4.

17. Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16.

18. “Contractual Performance, Corrective Justice, and Disgorgement for Breach of Contract” (2010) 16:3 Legal Theory 135 [Botterell, “Disgorgement”].

19. Miller, Paul B, “Justifying Fiduciary Remedies” (2013) 63:4Google Scholar UTLJ 570 [Miller, “Fiduciary Remedies”]. See also Miller, Paul B, “A Theory of Fiduciary Liability” (2011) 56:2Google Scholar McGill LJ 235 [Miller, “Theory of Fiduciary Liability”]; Miller, Paul B, “Justifying Fiduciary Duties” (2013) 58:4Google Scholar McGill LJ 969 [Miller, “Fiduciary Duties”]; Miller, Paul B, “The Fiduciary Relationship” in Gold, Andrew S & Miller, Paul B, Philosophical Foundations of Fiduciary Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014) [Google Scholar Gold & Miller, Fiduciary Law] 63.

20. See generally Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, translated by Roger Crisp (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), Book V, ch 4.

21. On the significance of court orders to understanding the normative structure of private law, see Stephen A Smith, “Why Courts Make Orders (and What This Tells Us about Damages)” (2011) 64:1 Curr Legal Probs 51 [S Smith, “Court Orders”].

22. See generally Weinrib, Ernest J, “Corrective Justice in a Nutshell” (2002) 52:4Google Scholar UTLJ 349.

23. Benson and Botterell each adopt Weinrib’s understanding of corrective justice to offer their reconciliations of corrective justice with the remedy of disgorgement for breach of contract See Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 318, n 11; Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 138, n 9. As will be seen in Part II.A, below, I briefly describe a corrective justice view of the normative structure of private law remedies that draws on the work of corrective justice theorists other than Weinrib. This alternative view reaches roughly the same conclusion about remedies as Weinrib’s conclusion, but I sketch it in recognition of the fact that not all adherents of corrective justice may accept some of the metaphysical claims about persons and the normative claims about the justifications for private law’s structural features that Weinrib accepts. For examples of these different conceptions of the underlying metaphysical and normative claims of corrective justice, see Dagan, Hanoch, “The Distributive Foundations of Corrective Justice” (1999) 98:1Google Scholar Mich L Rev 138; Coleman, Jules, The Practice of Principle: In Defence of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001);Google Scholar Arthur Ripstein, “Authority and Coercion” (2004) 32:1 Phil & Pub Affairs 2; Arthur Ripstein, “As If It Had Never Happened” (2007) 48:5 Wm & Mary L Rev 1957 [Ripstein, “As If”]; John Gardner, “What is Tort Law For? Part 1. The Place of Corrective Justice” (2011) 30:1 L & Phil 1.

24. See also Ripstein, Arthur, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009)CrossRefGoogle Scholar ch 2 [Ripstein, Force and Freedom]; Thompson, Michael, “What is it to Wrong Someone? A Puzzle about Justice” in Wallace, R Jay et al. , eds, Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (New York: Oxford University Press, 2006) 333.Google Scholar

25. The Supreme Court of Canada has articulated a test for a cause of action in unjust enrichment that tracks this understanding of private law injustice as involving a benefit to the defendant and a corresponding deprivation of the plaintiff for which there is no juristic reason. See, e.g., Pettkus v Becker, [1980] 2 SCR 834 at 848, 117 DLR (3d) 257 [Pettkus]; Garland v Consumers’ Gas Co, 2004 SCC 25 at para 30, 1 SCR 629.

26. See also Klimchuk, supra note 15 at 114-15; Zoë Sinel, “Through Thick and Thin: The Place of Corrective Justice in Unjust Enrichment” (2011) 31:3 Oxford J Legal Stud 551.

27. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 17.

28. See also Weinrib, Ernest J, “Correlativity, Personality and the Emerging Consensus on Corrective Justice” (2001) 2:1Google Scholar Theor Inq L 107.

29. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 17.

30. Ibid at 20.

31. Miller, “Fiduciary Remedies,” supra note 19 at 582.

32. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 159.

33. Birks, Peter, “Rights, Wrongs, and Remedies” (2000) 20:1Google Scholar Oxford J Legal Stud 1.

34. For discussion, see ibid; S Smith, “Court Orders,” supra note 20.

35. Civil recourse theorists have interpreted this secondary right not as a right at all, and thus as not entailing a correlative secondary duty of redress on the part of the defendant, but a power to seek redress through a civil proceeding. See, e.g., Zipursky, Benjamin, “Civil Recourse, Not Corrective Justice” (2003) 91:3Google Scholar Geo LJ 695; Hershovitz, Scott, “Corrective Justice for Civil Recourse Theorists” (2011) 39:1Google Scholar Fla St UL Rev 107; Goldberg, John CP & Zipursky, Benjamin C, “Civil Recourse Revisited” (2011) 39:1Google Scholar Fla St UL Rev 341.

36. Ripstein, “As If,” supra note 23.

37. Miller, “Fiduciary Remedies,” supra note 19 at 582.

38. Gardner, supra note 23 at 33.

39. Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 141.

40. Arthur Ripstein, “Editor’s Note” (2011) 61:2 UTLJ i at ii-iii.

41. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 13. Dan Priel, however, argues that corrective justice’s distinctive “doctrinalist” approach is misguided, at least in the context of explaining unjust enrichment in private law. In his critique, Priel usefully explains the different ways in which the doctrinalism of corrective justice manifests in the writings of several leading scholars on the subject. See Priel, “Justice in Unjust Enrichment,” supra note 15 at 817-21.

42. It has been famously said that, by awarding the remedy, “we ‘compensate’ the plaintiff by giving him something he never had,” which seems to be “a queer kind of ‘compensation.’” Fuller, LL & Perdue, William R Jr, “The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages” (1936) 36:1Google Scholar Yale LJ 52 at 53. See also Friedmann, Daniel, “The Performance Interest in Contract Damages” (1995) 111:4Google Scholar Law Q Rev 628. We also seem to impose a kind of positive obligation on the defendant to provide a benefit to the plaintiff to which the plaintiff has no right, which conflicts with private law’s typical reluctance to impose liability for nonfeasance. See Bohlen, Francis H, “The Moral Duty to Aid Others as a Basis of Tort Liability” (1908) 56:4Google Scholar U Pa L Rev 217 at 219; Benson, Peter, “Philosophy of Property Law” in Coleman, Jules L, Himma, Kenneth Einar & Shapiro, Scott J, eds, The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004) 753 at 782Google Scholar [Benson, “Philosophy of Property Law”]; Home Office v Dorset Yacht, [1970] AC 1004, 2 All ER 294 (HL), Diplock LJ.

43. This conception is also known as the “transfer theory of contract.” For discussion, see Stephen A Smith, Contract Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004); Ripstein, Force and Freedom, supra note 24 at 5; Peter Benson, “External Freedom According to Kant” (1987) 87:3 Colum L Rev 559; Peter Benson, “Contract” in Dennis Patterson, ed, A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 1996); Peter Benson, “The Unity of Contract Law” in Peter Benson, ed, The Theory of Contract Law: New Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001) 118 [Benson, “Unity of Contract Law”]; Peter Jaffey, “Restitutionary Claims Arising on Contractual Termination” in EJH Schrage, ed, Unjust Enrichment and the Law of Contract (New York: Kluwer Law, 2001) 243; Benson, “Philosophy of Property Law,” supra note 42. That a contractual right enforceable in personam against the promisor is a something capable of being owned in the traditional sense of being constituted by a bundle of rights to exclusive possession, use, and disposition is illustrated by the fact that a contractual right can be classified and assigned as a chose in action. For discussion, see Arthur L Corbin, “Assignment of Contract Rights” (1926) 74:3 U Pa L Rev 207.

44. Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 313.

45. See Kant, Immanuel, The Metaphysics of Morals, in Practical Philosophy, translated by Gregor, Mary J (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) at 401-44.Google Scholar

46. See Sage, NW, “Original Acquisition and Unilateralism: Kant, Hegel, and Corrective Justice” (2012) 25:1Google Scholar Can JL & Juris 119.

47. See Kant, supra note 45 at 421.

48. See Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 152-53; Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 313-24; Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 146-48; B Sharon Byrd & Joachim Hruschka, “Kant on ‘Why Must I Keep My Promise?’” (2006) 81:1 Chicago-Kent L Rev 47. Benson does describe a Hegelian view of contractual right according to which the promisee does come to own the object of a contract at the time of contract formation, although his writing elsewhere suggests that he prefers the view according to which what the promisee acquires is a personal right to another’s choice to perform a specific deed. See Benson, “Unity of Contract Law,” supra note 43 at 135-37.

49. Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 322.

50. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 153-54.

51. Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 318 [emphasis removed].

52. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 162. See also ibid at 165.

53. Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 319. See also ibid at 316-21.

54. Ibid at 327.

55. The puzzle of disgorgement from the perspective of corrective justice is that the remedy “seems to remedy without compensating.” Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 141. Before the decision of the House of Lords in Blake, the law recognized this puzzle. For example, in Tito v Waddell (No 2), the plaintiffs contracted to allow the defendant to conduct mining operations on their island under the agreement that the defendant would replant the island afterwards. The defendant breached by failing to replant and accordingly saved money. The plaintiffs suffered no loss because they no longer lived on the island and the difference in the island’s value was negligible, so they sued to recover the money the defendant saved. The claim was denied, and Vice Chancellor Megarry stated that “if the defendant has saved himself money, as by not doing what he has contracted to do, that does not of itself entitle the plaintiff to recover the saving as damages; for it by no means necessarily follows that what the defendant has saved the plaintiff has lost.” See Tito v Waddell No 2, [1977] Ch D 106 at 332, 3 All ER 129.

56. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 159.

57. Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 326.

58. Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 145.

59. Ibid at 152; Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 326-27.

60. Ibid at 328.

61. Ibid at 329.

62. Ibid.

63. Benson claims that the need to specify a contractual performance and render it fully determinate by reference to the object that the performance delivers derives from the need to give the performance a cognizable legal reality that is expressed in the common law doctrine of consideration. See ibid at 329, n 28. See also Peter Benson, “The Idea of Consideration” (2011) 61:2 UTLJ 241.

64. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 165.

65. I signal here that the interpretation I give to Weinrib’s comment on Benson’s attempted reconciliation constitutes my contribution to the scholarly response to Benson. I do not mean to suggest that Weinrib himself would endorse this interpretation, and, setting his comment aside, I think that my interpretation can stand alone as a critique of Benson’s view. Still, it might be thought that it is implausible to suppose that Weinrib could dismiss Benson’s detailed argument in a single paragraph, and that something other than the argument in the excerpt is required before Benson’s argument can be tenably rejected. In response, I agree that Weinrib’s comment, taken alone, is much too perfunctory to be thoroughly convincing. I think that there is, however, the kernel of a convincing reply in it that I attempt to draw out and elaborate on in the text that follows. This kind of extended interpretation is important given the dialectic that has played out between Weinrib and Benson. Weinrib made the comment after Benson published his corrective justice account of disgorgement and it did not appear in his earlier treatment of disgorgement that was published before Benson’s account was published. See Weinrib, “Punishment and Disgorgement,” supra note 14. Given his initial stance on the incompatibility of disgorgement and corrective justice, and his pedigree as a prominent contemporary expositor of corrective justice, it is an illuminating exercise to come to full grips with why Weinrib was not shaken from his position by Benson’s account. I am unaware of any attempt to undertake this exercise in the literature. Furthermore, in my view it can be seen as a worthwhile endeavor to provide a critique of Benson’s account by means of an interpretation of Weinrib’s work in a way that adds to the literature on the topic with which this paper is concerned, in the same way that an interpretation of sometimes-obscure writings of a historical philosopher (such as Kant or Aristotle) on a particular topic can genuinely add to the contemporary literature on that topic.

66. See supra note 61.

67. Ripstein, Force and Freedom, supra note 24 at 115.

68. See Smith v Hughes, [1871] All ER Rep 632, LR 6 QB 597; Carlill v Carbolic Smoke Ball Co, [1893] 1 QB 256, All ER Rep 127 (CA).

69. See Dunlop Pneumatic Tyre Co Ltd v Selfridge & Co Ltd, [1915] AC 847, All ER Rep 333; London Drugs Ltd v Kuehne & Nagel Int Ltd, [1992] 3 SCR 299, 97 DLR (4th) 261. Benson seems to accept that these contract law doctrines express the fundamentally bilateral normativity of contractual acquisition. See Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 323, n 19.

70. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 164.

71. Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 150.

72. Ibid at 151.

73. Botterell also claims that the establishment of the promisor’s right to ϕiii need not even arise from implicit consent but could also arise out of the promisee’s explicit consent to not ϕiii. He claims that there was such explicit consent in the Federal Court of Australia case of Hospitality Group Pty Ltd v Australian Rugby Union Ltd ([2001] FCA 1040). In that case, the plaintiff rugby association sold tickets to a third party who then sold them to the defendant company. The contract for the sale of tickets contained an explicit condition that they were not to be resold for profit. The defendant in fact resold the tickets to customers at a profit. The court found that the defendant was not precluded from contractual liability by the doctrine of privity of contract but that disgorgement of the defendant’s profits was not available to the plaintiff because contract damages must always be compensatory. For Botterell, this case was wrongly decided because the contract between the plaintiff and defendant contains an explicit subsidiary promise that the defendant would not resell the tickets a profit. Therefore, the plaintiff had an ownership right in the plaintiff’s performance of the specific act of selling the tickets, which the defendant wrongfully alienated to produce a profit to which the plaintiff ought to have been entitled via the remedy of disgorgement. Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 156. Botterell quite clearly states that a consequence of his view is that “where what is contracted for is that the promisor not do something, then where that thing is done, the promisee is entitled by way of right to any profits realized by the promisor as a result of her breach.” Ibid at 155, n 61.

74. Ibid at 150.

75. Attorney General v Blake, [1998] 1 All ER 833 at 846, 2 WLR 805 (CA), citing Birks, “Restitutionary Damages,” supra note 11 at 434 (“If you promise not to pursue a particular profit-making activity and then you do pursue it, nothing is more apt than that you should make restitution of your profits”).

76. Blake HL, supra note 5 at 398.

77. Botterell does hold this view. See the discussion in note 73.

78. Botterell also seems to accept this desideratum. He writes that “the law of contract must have the resources available to draw a distinction between actions contracted for that are particular and actions contracted for that are generic; otherwise, certain remedial features of contract law become mysterious.” Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 152.

79. The promisor might profit from violating the supposed implied negative covenant to not act inconsistently with the act initially acquired by the promisee at the time of contract formation. For example, he might be earning passive income, such as interest or investment returns, on the object to be transferred to the promisee the total of which is higher than the amount that he agreed to sell the object to the defendant for. Failing to transfer the object in order to continue to earn this passive income would be a profitable breach of contract.

80. Ibid at 152.

81. Ibid at 152-53.

82. Ibid at 153.

83. Birks, Peter, An Introduction to the Law of Restitution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1985) at 24Google Scholar [Birks, Law of Restitution]. For further discussion, see Smith, Lionel D, “The Province of the Law of Restitution” (1992) 71:4Google Scholar Can Bar Rev 672; Mitchell McInnes, “Disgorgement for Breach of Contract: The Search for a Principled Relationship” in Schrage, supra note 43, 225.

84. Botterell, “Disgorgement,” supra note 18 at 157-58. Benson also states that his account construes disgorgement for breach of contract as compensatory in nature. See Benson, “Disgorgement,” supra note 16 at 320.

85. See, e.g., Chandler v Webster, [1994] KB 493, 52 WR 290 (CA); Sinclair v Brougham, [1914] AC 398, All ER Rep 622 (HL); Royal Bank of Canada v The King, [1913] AC 283, All ER Rep 846 (PC). For further discussion, see Westdeutsche Landesbank Girozentrale v Islington London Borough Council, [1994] 4 All ER 890 at 912, 1 WLR 938, Hobhouse J (“Up until even the second decade of this century and the decision in Sinclair v Brougham it was normal to categorise the remedy of restitution under the common law as an aspect of quasi contract depending upon implied contract. This approach … meant that if there was some objection to the implication of a promise by the recipient of a benefit to reimburse the party at whose expense that benefit had been enjoyed then, because no contract could be implied, no remedy was given by the common law” [citation omitted]).

86. See, e.g., Fibrosa Spolka Akcyjna v Fairbairn Lawson Combe Barbour Ltd, [1943] AC 32, 2 All ER 122 (HL) [Fibrosa]; Woolwich Equitable Building Society v Inland Revenue Commissioners, [1993] AC 70, [1992] 3 WLR 366; Westdeutsche Landesbank Girozentrale v Islington London Borough Council, [1996] AC 669, 2 All ER 961 (HL); Banque Financière de la Cité v Parc (Battersea) Ltd, [1999] AC 221, 1 All ER 737 (HL); For the rejection of quasi-contract in Canada, see Deglman v The Guaranty Trust Co of Canada, [1954] SCR 725, 3 DLR 785, Cartwright J [Deglman]; Pettkus, supra note 25. For the same rejection in Australia and New Zealand, see David Securities Pty Ltd v Commonwealth Bank of Australia [1992] HCA 48; National Bank of New Zealand Ltd v Waitaki, [1999] 2 NZLR 211 (CA). See also Birks, Law of Restitution, supra note 83 at 22; Peter Birks, Unjust Enrichment, 2d ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005) at 271 [Birks, Unjust Enrichment]; Graham Virgo, The Principles of the Law of Restitution, 2d ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006) at 21; Andrew Burrows, The Law or Restitution, 3d ed (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011) 28. But see Dan Priel, “In Defence of Quasi-Contract” (2012) 75:1 Md L Rev 54 (arguing that the language of quasi-contract can play an illuminating role in the analysis of some topics in the law of restitution).

87. See, e.g., Fibrosa, supra note 86; Deglman, supra note 86. See also Warren A Seavey & Austin W Scott, “Restitution” (1938) 54:1 Law Q Rev 29; Andrew Kull, “James Barr Ames and the Early Modern History of Unjust Enrichment” (2005) 25:2 Oxford J Legal Stud 297.

88. Kleinwort Benson Ltd v Lincoln City Council, [1999] 2 AC 349 at 408, [1998] 3 WLR 1095.

89. For discussion of this constraint on the justification of private law doctrine from the perspective of corrective justice, see Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 17-18.

90. Ibid at 189.

91. Sinel, supra note 26 at 559.

92. Blake HL, supra note 5 at 390.

93. Ibid at 388-90.

94. Ibid at 398.

95. Ibid.

96. Ibid at 398-99.

97. Ibid at 399.

98. Ibid.

99. See Frame v Smith, [1987] 2 SCR 99, 42 DLR (4th) 81 at para 60 [Frame]; Soulos v Korkontzilas, [1997] 2 SCR 217, 146 DLR (4th) 214 at para 34 (the objective of imposing fiduciary duties is to “maintain the integrity of institutions dependent on trust-like relationships”); Strother, supra note 8 at paras 74-77; Friedman, “Restitution of Benefits,” supra note 11; Richard Holton, “Fiduciary Relations and the Nature of Trust” (2011) 91:3 BUL Rev 991. Miller argues against this view of the wrong of breach of fiduciary duty, holding that it is at bottom not illuminating and leaves several questions open. See Miller, “Fiduciary Remedies,” supra note 19 at 594-98.

100. Blake HL, supra note 5 at 400.

101. Ibid at 404.

102. 444 US 507, 100 S Ct 763 [cited to US].

103. Ibid at 507-08.

104. Ibid at 516.

105. Blake HL, supra note 5 at 400.

106. McCamus, “Disgorgement,” supra note 11 at 967. See also Peter D Maddaugh & John D McCamus, The Law of Restitution, student ed (Toronto: Thomson Reuters, 2014) at 25:400.

107. 2011 ABQB 38, 43 Alta LR (5th) 83 [Indutech, cited to ABQB].

108. See also Smith v Landstar Properties Inc, 2011 BCCA 44, 14 BCLR (5th) 48; Inuit of Nunavut v Canada (Attorney General), 2014 NUCA 2, 242 ACWS (3d) 829.

109. Indutech, supra note 107 at para 522.

110. Ibid at para 524.

111. Supra note 2.

112. Ibid at 271-72. What Justice Barak recognized was, of course, that some have advocated for the “efficient breach” theory of contract remedies. See, e.g., Richard A Posner, Economic Analysis of Law, 8th ed (New York: Aspen, 2011) at 2.

113. Adras, supra note 2 at 272.

114. Weinrib interprets Justice Barak’s opinion in Adras in the same way. However, he is critical of Justice Barak’s approach because, according to corrective justice, a private law remedy cannot be grounded in normative considerations, such as the social value of promise keeping, that are external to the bilateral relationship between the parties to a private transaction, which is defined by the parties correlative relationship to each other through the juridical concepts of correlative rights and duties. Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at 161. It might be thought that because, as I claim, the approach to disgorgement discernible in Adras parallels that in Blake, and, as Weinrib claims, the approach in Adras is inconsistent with corrective justice, then a fortiori the notion articulated in Blake that disgorgement should be available where a breach of contract is closely akin to a breach of a fiduciary duty that engages important social values external to the bilateral relationship between parties to a private transactions is also inconsistent with corrective justice. However, I do not hold the view that remedies for breach of fiduciary are incapable of being explained in terms of corrective justice. Indeed, I adopt the corrective justice account of fiduciary relationships developed recently by Paul Miller. I explain this account momentarily, in Part V, below.

115. See also Securities and Exchange Commission v Chenery Corporation et al, 318 US 80 at 85-86, 63 S Ct 454 (1943); Canadian Aero Service Ltd v O’Malley, [1974] SCR 592 at 605, 40 DLR (3d) 371; Guerin v The Queen, [1984] 2 SCR 335 at 384, 13 DLR (4th) 321; Galambos v Perez, 2009 SCC 48 at para 70, 3 SCR 247 [Galambos].

116. See, e.g., Frame, supra note 99 at para 60; Galambos, supra note 115 at para 70; Wewaykam Indian Band v Canada, 2002 SCC 79 at para 79, 4 SCR 245; Alberta v Elder Advocates of Alberta Society, 2011 SCC 24 at para 27, 2 SCR 261. See also Miller, “A Theory of Fiduciary Liability,” supra note 19 at 262; Weinrib, “The Fiduciary Obligation” (1975) 25:1 UTLJ 1.

117. Miller, “Fiduciary Remedies,” supra note 19 at 602.

118. Ibid at 604.

119. Ibid at 603.

120. Ibid.

121. Ibid at 604.

122. Ibid.

123. Ibid at 604-06.

124. Ibid at 607 [emphasis in original].

125. Ibid at 608-09.

126. Ibid at 610.

127. Ibid at 615, 617.

128. See United States v Dial, 757 F (2d) 163 at 168 (7th Cir 1985) (“The essence of a fiduciary relationship is that the fiduciary agrees to act as his principal’s alter ego rather than to assume the standard arm’s length stance of traders in a market.”).

129. Miller, “Fiduciary Remedies,” supra note 19 at 611. Miller thus sees the right to the fiduciary’s exercise of discretionary decision making power in matters that affect the beneficiary’s practical interests as akin to a property right; it a right of ownership entailing exclusive possession, use, and alienation. Cf Weinrib, “Restitutionary Damages,” supra note 15 at 33-34; Weinrib, “Corrective Justice,” supra note 14 at 143 ([a]lthough gain-based damages do not … respond to the violation of what is strictly speaking a proprietary right, the relationship between the parties can give rise to an interest that is sufficiently property-like to allow this kind of award”).

130. Miller, “Fiduciary Remedies,” supra note 19 at 615.

131. Ibid.

132. Ibid at 617.

133. For discussion, see Shiffrin, Seana Valentine, “Promising, Intimate Relationships, and Conventionalism” (2008) 117:4Google Scholar Philosophical Rev 481; Pallikkathayil, Japa, “The Possibility of Choice: Three Accounts of the Problem of Coercion” (2011) 11:16Google Scholar Philosopher’s Imprint 1.

134. See, e.g., Easterbrook, Frank H & Fischel, Daniel R, “Contract and Fiduciary Duty” (1993) 36:1Google Scholar JL & Econ 425.

135. Ripstein, Force and Freedom, supra note 24 at 73.

136. See, e.g., M(K) v M(H), [1992] 3 SCR 6, 96 DLR (4th) 289; KLB v British Columbia, 2003 SCC 51, 2 SCR 403. See also Ripstein, Force and Freedom, supra note 24 at 71-72.

137. Miller, “Fiduciary Duties,” supra note 19 at 983.

138. For a recent discussion, see Bhasin v Hrynew, 2014 SCC 71 at para 70, 3 SCR 495 (“The principle of good faith must be applied in a manner that is consistent with the fundamental commitments of the common law of contract which generally places great weight on the freedom of contracting parties to pursue their individual self-interest”).

139. Markovits, Daniel, “Sharing Ex Ante and Sharing Ex Post: The Non-Contractual Basis of Fiduciary Relations”Google Scholar in Gold & Miller, Fiduciary Law, supra note 19, 209 at 214 [Markovits, “Sharing”]. See also Daniel Markovits, “Contract and Collaboration” (2004) 113:7 Yale LJ 1417; Farnsworth, supra note 11 at 1354-60 (“However appropriate such rules may be for fiduciary relations, they seem oversolicitous of your interests when applied to our contract for the sale of a widget. The rules that limit the discretion of the trustee are intended to protect both the beneficiary and the public in ways inappropriate to ordinary commercial dealings”).

140. Markovits, “Sharing,” supra note 139 at 216-18; Miller, “Fiduciary Duties,” supra note 19 at 983.

141. It is thus said that an employee is under the control of the employer and is integrated into and must advance the employer’s business. See Montreal (City) v Montreal Locomotive Works, [1947] 1 DLR 161 at 169, 3 WWR 748 (PC); Stevenson Jordan & Harrison Ltd v MacDonald and Evans, [1952] 1 TLR 101 at 111 (CA). See also Ripstein, Force and Freedom, supra note 24 at 75-76.

142. Robb v Green, [1895] 2 QB 315; Hivac Ltd v Park Royal Scientific Instruments Ltd, [1946] Ch 169, 1 All ER 350 (CA); RBC Dominion Securities Ltd v Merill Lynch Inc, 2008 SCC 54, 3 SCR 79; Geoffrey England, Individual Employment Law (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2008) at 58-59.

143. Laws v London Chronicle (Indicator Newspapers) Ltd, [1959] 2 All ER 285, 1 WLR 698 (CA).

144. 671122 Ontario Ltd v Sagaz Industries Canada Inc, 2001 SCC 59, 2 SCR 983.

145. Wallace v United Grain Growers (cob Public Press), [1997] 3 SCR 701, 152 DLR (4th) 1; Honda Canada Inc v Keays, 2008 SCC 39, 2 SCR 362.

146. For the cases from which these examples are drawn, see, e.g., Holiday Pacific Ltd v Valhalla Custom Homes Ltd (1990), 29 CPR (3d) 1, 19 ACWS (3d) 1231 (Ont H Ct J); Lac Minerals, supra note 9; McCleod v Sweezey, [1944] SCR 111, 2 DLR 145.

147. For recognition of the fiduciary relationship between solicitors and clients, see Nocton v Lord Ashubrn, [1914] AC 932, All ER Rep 45; Strother, supra note 8.

148. For similar factual circumstances and recognition of the fiduciary relationship between doctor and patient, see Norberg v Wynrib, [1992] 2 SCR 226, 92 DLR (4th) 449.

149. Birks, Unjust Enrichment, supra note 86 at 21.

150. For discussion of the distinction between the cause of a breach of a right and normative justification for a remedial response to it, see Weinrib, Corrective Justice, supra note 14 at ch 3.