Point:
Wars must be won if our country … is to be protected from unthinkable outcomes, as the events on September 11th most recently illustrated…. This best protection unequivocally requires armed forces having military physicians committed to doing what is required to secure victory…. As opposed to needing neutral physicians, we need military physicians who can and do identify as closely as possible with the military so that they, too, can carry out the vital part they play in meeting the needs of the mission.1
Howe EG. Point/Counterpoint—A response to Drs Sidel and Levy (Physician-Soldier: A Moral Dilemma). In: Beam TE, Spracino LR, eds. Military Medical Ethics, Volume 1. Falls Church, Va.: Office of the Surgeon General; 2003:312–20 at p. 320.
Counterpoint:
We believe the role of the “physician–soldier” to be an inherent moral impossibility because the military physician, in an environment of military control, is faced with the difficult problems of mixed agency that include obligations to the “fighting strength” and … “national security.”2
Sidel VW, Levy BS. Physician-Soldier: A Moral Dilemma. In: Beam TE, Spracino LR, eds. Military Medical Ethics, Volume 1. Falls Church, Va.: Office of the Surgeon General; 2003:293–312 at p. 296.
These two quotes typify the competing worldviews brought to bear on the ethical and human rights obligations of health professionals in the armed forces. Attention has focused increasingly on the role of health professionals in abuses of detainees in military custody3
Marshall T. Doctors at Guantanamo Bay are at risk of being accessories to torture. British Medical Journal 2002;324:235.
Miles SH. Abu Ghraib: Its legacy for military medicine. Lancet 2004;364:725–9; Lifton RJ. Doctors and torture. New England Journal of Medicine 2004;351:415–6; Anonymous. How complicit are doctors in abuse of detainees? Lancet 2004;364:637–8; Bloche MG, Marks JH. When doctors go to war. New England Journal of Medicine 2005;352:3–6.
Howe EG. Mixed agency in military medicine: Ethical roles in conflict. In: Beam TE, Spracino LR, eds. Military Medical Ethics, Volume 1. Falls Church, Va.: Office of the Surgeon General; 2003:331–65.
Dual Loyalty Working Group. Dual Loyalty and Human Rights in Health Professional Practice. Proposed Guidelines and Institutional Mechanisms. Washington: Physicians for Human Rights. Available at: http://www.phrusa.org/healthrights/dual_loyalty.html (accessed May 2005); Singh JA. Military tribunals at Guantanamo Bay: Dual loyalty conflicts. Lancet 2003;362:573.
Historically, ethical obligations of health professionals have privileged the need for loyalty to patients. In the modern world, however, health professionals are frequently placed in settings where they are asked to weigh their devotion to patients against service to the objectives of government or other third parties. Dual loyalty poses particular challenges for health professionals when the subordination of the patient's interests risks violating that patient's human rights. Thus it is critical that the problem of dual loyalty be addressed through recasting the dilemma not as health professional neutrality versus identification with military objectives, but rather as imposing a mandate to engage with the human rights laws and principles at stake. In other words, the inescapable “mixed agency” of health professionals serving in the military demands heightened attention to potential human rights pitfalls.
This paper attempts to reframe the current debates around health professional complicity in human rights violations during wartime in terms of dual loyalty. We analyze the spectrum of dual loyalty conflicts and explore ethical models developed to explain the role of health professionals in the military. Given their limited success in resolving dual loyalty conflicts, we turn to a human rights analysis of the problem through the example of medical involvement in interrogation during armed conflict. Drawing on the three-year project of an international working group on the question of dual loyalty,7
See note 6, Dual Loyalty Working Group 2005.
Definition of Dual Loyalty Conflict
Current international codes of ethics generally mandate complete loyalty to patients.8
World Medical Association. International Code of Medical Ethics: Declaration of Geneva. Adopted by the 3rd General Assembly of the World Medical Association. London, England, Oct 1949. Amended by the 22nd World Medical Assembly, Sydney, Australia, Aug 1968, and the 35th World Medical Assembly, Venice, Italy, Oct 1983. Available at: www.wma.net/e/policy/17-a_e.html.
Bloche MG. Clinical loyalties and the social purposes of medicine. JAMA 1999;281:268–74; British Medical Association. Medical Ethics Today: Its Practice and Philosophy. London: BMJ Publishing Group; 1993.
Where dual loyalty exists, elevating state over individual interests may nevertheless serve justifiable social purposes,10
See note 9, Bloche 1999.
Dual loyalty conflicts can potentially give rise to human rights violations in all societies, even those thought to be the most open and free. However, they are likely to be greatest in societies that lack freedom of expression and association, for example, where state officials demand that health professionals contribute to the suppression of dissent. Dual loyalty conflicts also occur frequently in closed settings or total institutions characterized by secrecy and ambiguity about the health professional's role.
The Scope of Dual Loyalty Conflicts in Military Medical Services
Dual loyalty conflicts are therefore common in the military, occurring in a variety of situations. Involvement of military medical personnel in torture whereby medical skills have been used to inflict pain or physical or psychological harm on an individual that is not a legitimate part of medical treatment has been documented all too frequently. Uruguay,11
Bloche MG. Uruguay's military physicians: Cogs in a system of state terror. JAMA 1986;255:2788–93.
Stover E, Nightingale EO, eds. The Breaking of Bodies and Minds. New York: W.H. Freeman and Co; 1985:32; British Medical Association. Medicine Betrayed. London: Zed Books; 1992.
Brennan TA, Kirscher R. Medical ethics and human rights violations: The Iraqi occupation of Kuwait and its aftermath. Annals of Internal Medicine 1992;117:78–82.
Rayner M. Turning a Blind Eye: Medical Accountability for Torture in South Africa. Washington: American Association for the Advancement of Science; 1987.
Burger M, Gould C. Secrets and Lies. Wouter Basson and South Africa's Chemical and Biological Warfare Programme. Cape Town: Zebra Press; 2002.
Baldwin-Ragaven L, de Gruchy J, London L. An Ambulance of the Wrong Colour. Health Professionals, Human Rights and Ethics in South Africa. Cape Town: UCT Press; 1999.
See note 6, Dual Loyalty Working Group 2005.
Incidenten bij de medische hulpverlening aan burgers door de krijgsmacht hospitaal organisatie in voormalig Joegoslavië. [Incidents in medical care for civilians by the military medical organization in former Yugoslavia.] Rijswijk: Report of the Health Inspectorate, June 12, 1996; Siemons GHA. Medische Hulp aan burgerslachtoffers, Srebrenica, onder de loep. [Medical care for civilian casualties, Srebrenica investigated]. Medisch Contact 1996;51:1465.
See note 4, Miles 2004.
See note 6, Dual Loyalty Working Group 2005.
Another common type of dual loyalty conflict arises from the disclosure of confidential detainee medical information, as took place in military detention at Guantanamo Bay.21
Bloche MG, Marks J. Doctors and interrogators at Guantanamo Bay. New England Journal of Medicine 2005;353:1.
See note 5, Howe 2003.
Although strenuously denied by the Offices of the Armed Forces Medical Examiner23
Mallak CT. Doctors and torture. New England Journal of Medicine 2004;351:1572.
Winkenwerder W, Kiley KC, Arthur DC, Taylor GP, Porr DR. Doctors and torture. New England Journal of Medicine 2004; 351: 1573.
See note 4, Lifton 2004, and note 4, Miles 2004.
Finally, the silence of medical personnel in the face of human rights abuses remains one of the most striking features of the recent revelations of torture at Abu Ghraib and mistreatment of detainees at Guantanamo.26
See note 4, Lifton 2004, note 4, Miles 2004, note 4, Anonymous 2004, and note 6, Singh 2003.
Ethical Analyses Related to Dual Loyalty in the Military
Ethical analyses related to dual loyalty in the military context struggle to resolve these conflicts satisfactorily. First, because “there has been no formal ethical theory specific to military physicians,” the notion that responsibility “to reflect on how … personal values relate to being a physician in the military” falls to the individual physician soldier27
Madden W, Carter BS. Physician-soldier: A moral profession. In: Beam TE, Spracino LR, eds. Military Medical Ethics, Volume 1. Falls Church, Va.: Office of the Surgeon General; 2003:269–91 at p. 285.
See note 5, Howe 2003:341.
World Medical Association. World Medical Association Regulations in Time of Armed Conflict. Adopted by the 10th World Medical Assembly, Havana, Cuba, Oct 1956. Edited by the 11th World Medical Assembly, Istanbul, Turkey, Oct 1957. Amended by the 35th World Medical Assembly, Venice, Italy, Oct 1983. Available at: www.wma.net/e/policy/17-50_e.html; Baccino-Astrada, A. Manual on the Rights and Duties of Medical Personnel in Armed Conflicts. Geneva: International Committee of the Red Cross; 1982.
Military necessity has been justified by the argument that in wartime the physician–soldier “is not violating his (sic) professional responsibility to relieve pain and suffering; rather it is being met in a special way.”30
See note 27, Madden, Carter 2003:282.
Howe offers a different approach to resolving the mixed agency argument.31
See note 5, Howe 2003.
See note 5, Howe 2003:335.
However, Howe's analysis is of limited helpfulness. By what mechanisms should the individual health professional decide when to apply a military-specific ethic and when can the situation be dealt with from a medical-specific ethical perspective? Is the military health professional bound by a commander's assertion of military necessity? If not, how is the health professional supposed to evaluate such a claim, the veracity of which is presumably beyond his or her competence to determine?33
Rubenstein LR. Medicine and war. Hastings Center Report 2004;34:3.
Beam T, Howe EG. A proposed ethic for military medicine. In: Beam TE, Spracino LR, eds. Military Medical Ethics, Volume 2. Falls Church, Va.: Office of the Surgeon General; 2003:851–65.
Moreover, there is little evidence elsewhere in medicine that exceptions to the general principles of ethical rules actually justify creating new role-specific ethics, for example, in occupational medicine35
London L. Dual loyalties and the ethical and human rights obligations of occupational health professionals. American Journal of Industrial Medicine 2005;47:322–32.
See note 6, Dual Loyalty Working Group 2005.
Are there arguments to be made that the military is special and therefore merits such ethical exceptionalism? In wartime, the exigencies of battle pose unique challenges incomparable to the civilian context because of the scale of the threats to life, unpredictability, and the levels of violence.37
Beam T. Military ethics on the battlefield: The crucible of military medical ethics. In: Beam TE, Spracino LR, eds. Military Medical Ethics, Volume 2. Falls Church, Va.: Office of the Surgeon General; 2003:369–402.
Moskop JC. Ethics and military medicine: New developments and perennial questions. Ethics and Health Care 1998;7. Available at: http://www.edu.edu/medhum/newsletter/spring2004_pl.htm.
However, it seems to us that even such a tacit agreement does not waive all of a military patient's human rights nor relieve healthcare providers of their ethical obligations. Further, if these “high stakes” justify unique approaches to ethical frameworks, the consequences of these approaches must be addressed. In particular, medical personnel must also be able to anticipate and prevent the threat of violation of human rights, which, as we have illustrated, occur more in the military than in other contexts.
What about checks and balances in the “exceptional” model? At the moment, the only permissible reason for a military health professional to exercise independent judgment by refusing to follow a command is in the “clear case of an unethical or illegal order.”39
See note 5, Howe 2003:341.
See note 1, Howe 2003.
Another approach, asserted by the U.S. military, is that ethical obligations only apply to those providing clinical treatment, not to medical personnel who occupy other roles such as advising commanders or interrogators. But this fails to recognize that ethical obligations adhere because of authority, training, and social expectation related to health professionals who do not have narrowly defined roles.41
See note 4, Bloche, Marks 2005.
Thus, despite the existence of ethical codes and attempts to develop heuristics for ethical analysis specific to the military context, such approaches have not appeared to resolve adequately the dilemmas inherent in the dual loyalty conflict. Indeed, the prevailing view within the military is that uncertainty in moral choices is inherent to the work of military doctors.
The Contribution of a Rights-Based Approach to Resolving Dual Loyalty Conflicts in the Military
Arguing from the perspective of human rights offers a powerful and complementary approach to addressing the kinds of moral dilemmas outlined in the preceding discussion. Whereas ethical discourse provides tools for applying philosophical reasoning to moral dilemmas, an understanding of human rights protections and the obligations of health professionals to uphold human rights offers a different strategy for resolving these dilemmas, one we believe is more explicit both about processes to resolve dilemmas and about the fundamental justice of the outcomes achieved.
A rights-based approach identifies the potential for violation of clear standards that are not subject to reinterpretation based on one's personal values or military objectives. This approach also locates accountability in one or more duty-bearers. Unlike ethical principles that have to be balanced, human rights cannot be traded off, except under very limited circumstances permitted under international human rights law.42
Gruskin S, Tarantola D. Health and human rights. In: Last J, ed. Oxford Textbook of Public Health. New York: Oxford University Press; 2002:311–35; UNECOSOC (United Nations Economic and Social Council). The Siracusa Principles on the limitations and derogation provisions in the international covenant on civil and political rights. UN Document E/CN.4/1985/4, Annex. Geneva: UN; 1985.
We now apply this approach to the question of interrogation and military necessity.
Torture, Interrogation and Military Necessity
In 1985, a global compact reaffirmed every person's right to be free from torture as a nonderogable right in international human rights law regardless of the purpose for which torture is intended. The recent upsurge of global terrorist activities has prompted some to rethink this absolute prohibition.43
Bowden M. The dark art of interrogation: The most effective way to gather intelligence and thwart terrorism can also be a direct route into morally repugnant terrain. A survey of the landscape of persuasion. The Atlantic Monthly 2003;292(3):51–76; see note 38, Moskop 1998.
Gross M. Bioethics and armed conflict: Mapping the moral dimensions of medicine and war. Hastings Center Report 2004;34:22–30.
Human rights, however, are not like philosophical theories or bioethical constructs that require mediating in an ethical analysis. Nonderogable human rights are precisely nonderogable because they signal universally adopted commitments to core beliefs such as freedom, dignity, and equality of individuals that not only reflect shared moral consensus but self-imposed binding legal treaty commitments. They are fundamental to every human being—no matter how heinous—and abandoning such rights on the basis of utilitarian assumptions obscures the fact that the decisionmaking that determines utilitarian outcomes is entirely value based and fails to protect the most vulnerable in any society. Moreover, even where utilitarian arguments to justify torture on the basis of protection of innocent victims have been previously advanced, they have been rebutted by careful utilitarian analysis that arrives at the same conclusion as a rights-based analysis.45
See note 12, Stover, Nightingale 1985.
Asking health professionals to balance the nonderogable human right to be free from torture against “reasons of the state” on a case-by-case basis46
See note 44, Gross 2004.
Nathanson V. Doctors and torture. British Medical Journal 1999;319:397–8; Pellegrino E. Medical ethics subordinated by tyranny and war. JAMA 2004;291:1505–6.
Second, even when rights are in conflict or can be restricted, determining whose rights should be privileged over others requires consideration of principles of freedom, equality, and dignity, the needs of socially vulnerable and marginalized individuals and groups, and transparency and fairness in the process by which such a decision is reached.
The perils of abridging human rights are also apparent in “lesser forms” of coercive interrogation. For example, a 1987 Commission permitted Israeli authorities to use “a moderate measure of physical pressure” during interrogation of Palestinian prisoners.48
Amnesty International. High Court should end the shame of torture. AI INDEX: MDE 15/05/98. Jan 12, 1999. Available at: http://web.amnesty.org/library/Index/engMDE150051999 (accessed May 7, 2005).
Hall P. Doctors and the war of terrorism. British Medical Journal 2004;329:66; Bygrave H. Medical education should include human rights component. British Medical Journal 2004;329:1103.
Amnesty International. The Israeli Government should implement the High Court decision making torture illegal. AI INDEX: MDE 15/68/99. Sep 6, 1999. Available at: http://web.amnesty.org/library/Index/ENGMDE150681999?open&of=ENG-ISR A (accessed May 7, 2005).
In sum, the human rights framework represents a priori moral reasoning that privileges the protection of vulnerable people from state-sponsored harm, no matter the alleged justification. Health professionals are thus implicated as duty-bearers in ensuring that the interests of justice, equality, and dignity are upheld. Invoking human rights is not meant to block critical dialogue; instead it provides a call to responsibility that cannot be easily overstepped.
Guidelines and Institutional Mechanisms to Prevent Human Rights Violations in Dual Loyalty Conflicts in the Military
Because of the pervasiveness of dual loyalty conflicts and their potential for giving rise to human rights violations in military settings, an International Working Group developed guidelines for physicians working in this context (Table 1). These guidelines draw on existing national and international ethical codes but locate their perspective firmly within international human rights law. Unlike the oft-quoted maxim “You are first and foremost soldiers, and only after that, doctors,”51
Cilasun U. Torture and the participation of doctors. Journal of Medical Ethics 1991;17(Suppl.):S21–2.
Guidelines for the Military on Dual Loyalties—Summary

Because individual health professionals in any dual loyalty situation are vulnerable to pressure to conform to state expectations, particularly in the military context, guidelines alone will be meaningless unless coupled with strategies to support health professionals and address the systemic forces that affect how medicine is practiced in a particular setting.52
See note 6, Dual Loyalty Working Group 2005.
Schwapowal AG, Baer H. Medical ethics in peace and in the armed conflict. Military Medicine 2002;167(8 Suppl.):26–31.
Those who propose a separate ethics for military medicine54
See note 34, Beam, Howe 2003.
See note 27, Madden, Carter 2003.
Rascona DR. Point/counterpoint—A response to Drs Sidel and Levy (Physician-Soldier: A Moral Dilemma). In: Beam TE, Spracino LR, eds. Military Medical Ethics, Volume 1. Falls Church, Va.: Office of the Surgeon General; 2003:320–5.
Such institutional mechanisms aim both to prevent the dual loyalty conflict in the first place and to resolve and redress conflicts that do arise. Recommended strategies include education, professional support, restructuring of contractual obligations, monitoring, victim redress, and holding professionals accountable for violations. It is especially important to enable medical personnel to seek sources of support, both internal and external, where commanders decline to respect either human rights or ethical obligations. The protection of whistle-blowers is exceptionally fraught in the military context57
Jones JJ, McCullogh LB, Richman BW. The military physician's ethical response to evidence of torture. Surgery 2004;136:1090–3.
Jacoby D. Doctors and torture. New England Journal of Medicine 2004;351:1572.
It is precisely the secrecy of total institutions that fosters practices inimical to human rights and antithetical to ethical guidelines. Health professionals therefore have a duty to speak out, not just to meet their own standards of professionalism, but because exposing such violations is most likely to prevent their recurrence.59
See note 4, Miles 2004.
Conclusion
The dual loyalty guidelines hold that medical ethics during wartime are not fundamentally different from those applicable in peace, and that the processes and mechanisms required to determine permitted deviations from the norm are not particular to the military context. Rather than generating a new paradigm for ethical practice, which is based on the creation of what is essentially a nonpractice model of undivided loyalty to a military commander, resolving the ethical dilemmas of dual loyalty during armed conflict is better served by an approach grounded in human rights, which ensures that the duties to respect and protect human dignity remain at the core of health professional practice.