Those who read only the introductory section of “Physician Obligation in Disaster Preparedness and Response,” the statement from the AMA's Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs,1
Morin K, Higginson D, Goldrich M. Physician obligation in disaster preparedness and response. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, this issue, 417–21.
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:417.
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:417.
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:418.
Similarly, those who leap from the introduction to the “Conclusion” will find another fitting declaration of a noble profession's obligations. There the authors declare that
when the health of large populations is threatened, society should expect that the medical profession will be prepared to provide medical care in a cohesive and comprehensive manner. To accomplish this goal, the obligation to provide care must reside not only with individual physicians, but with the profession as a whole (emphasis added).5
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:421.
Readers who focus on other selected lines toward the end of the recommendations will also be impressed with the profession's assessment of its members' personal obligations. The authors maintain that
[b]ecause of their commitment to care for the sick and injured, individual physicians have an obligation to provide urgent medical care during disasters. This ethical obligation holds even in the face of greater than usual risks to their own safety, health or life (emphasis added).6
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:421.
Unfortunately, these thoughtful and fitting statements of professional duty are corrupted by the polluting influence of the AMA Principle VI, which takes back with one hand what the statement appears to have given with the other. In the end, the AMA has promulgated a politically expedient compromise in the guise of a position on the ethics of medicine. Allow me to explain why I reach this conclusion.
The Problem
Because society has allowed medicine to develop its specialized domain of knowledge and skills and has given medicine a monopoly over medical practice, and because physicians have pledged themselves through oaths, codes, and licensing to uphold well-known standards of medical professionalism, and because patients and society rely upon physicians to uphold those standards, doctors have distinctive professional responsibilities. The core of those responsibilities, which have remained unchanged since at least the time of Hippocrates, is physicians' commitment to the well-being of patients. So, because medical needs following a mass casualty event can be anticipated, medical ethics requires the participation of physicians in planning for catastrophes and the responsiveness of physicians in the aftermath of disasters. This much should be straightforward and incontrovertible.
Nevertheless, the AMA statement shows its stripes as a political document of compromise, rather than an assertion of professional ideals and commitments, when it hedges on whether individual physicians actually have those obvious duties. Instead of explicitly outlining physician responsibilities in a disaster, the AMA emphasizes “limitations to the duty to treat.”7
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:420.
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:420.
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:420.
This position is a far cry from a statement of responsibility. When someone has a responsibility she is obliged, bound, required to act in a particular way. When someone has no responsibility she is free to do the thing or not, to volunteer or hold back, to accept the risks or decline them. They cannot both be true at once, in the same sense, about the same matter. An AMA Opinion that contains such a glaring contradiction amounts to saying that doctors may do whatever they choose in the face of a disaster because they have no responsibility to respond.
Medicine and Risks
Medicine's historical commitments make it clear that physicians accept responsibility to patients and society, and that part of being a doctor is acceptance of the concomitant role-related risk. Although self-preservation limits all responsibilities, the ethically crucial questions are: (1) How does medicine determine when a danger is great enough to overwhelm the default professional responsibility of responsiveness? (2) Who makes the call? The AMA suggests that these are matters of personal judgment. That answer, unfortunately, overlooks an important characteristic of medicine.
Through the ages, one distinguishing feature of medicine is its reliance on scientific evidence (broadly construed) and “the standard of care.” To explain very briefly, a gut feeling that something should or should not be done or that this is too little or too much is not enough to justify a medical decision. In medicine, hypotheses have to be supported by theory, judgments have to be supported by observation or data, and medical stands are acceptable positions when they are endorsed by a consensus of the profession. Even though Morin and her coauthors illustrate the scope of and the limitations on risk-related exemption from obligation by discussing the AMA's Opinions (2.23 and 9.131) that require doctors to provide treatment for patients with HIV or AIDS in their section on professional responsibility, they miss two significant points. (1) Those earlier Opinions rested on a theory of how the disease is transmitted and evidence of the low risk of transmission when precautions are taken. Also (2) those opinions reflected the position of the profession rather than the private judgment of individual risk-averse practitioners. In other words, in the face of risk to physicians, responsiveness should be the default presumption because that is the standard of care. A judgment that responding is too dangerous in a particular circumstance has to be left to the consensus of medical experts with the relevant specialized knowledge and experience. In our current age of speedy electronic communication, there is no justification for allowing decisions on recusal or response to turn on the personal fear, courage, or sense of duty of the individual physician.
By crafting a code and principles and by publishing opinions on controversial issues the AMA defines the standard of care for medical practice. As the authors elsewhere agree, the AMA's Code “is intended to put forth a uniform standard of conduct for individuals who belong to a profession.”10
See note 1, Morin et al. 2006:419.
Principle VI
In reaching their peculiarly inconsistent position, the authors invoke Principle VI of the AMA Code of Medical Ethics, which was only added to the code in 1957.11
This was Section 5 in the 1957 version of the Principles of Medical Ethics. It is Principle VI in the 1980 and 2001 versions.
Although it is easy to understand why AMA members have repeatedly decided to keep Principle VI in their code and why they feel comforted by the license it allows them, it is legitimate to ask whether that provision is consistent with the ethical responsibilities of being a physician. It is hard to see how Principle VI can be reconciled with the commitments espoused elsewhere in the AMA Code (or in the Hippocratic Oath or in the Oath of Maimonides or in the Geneva Code) without either eviscerating the concept of physician professional responsibility or contorting and deflating the meaning of Principle VI. For that reason, it is surprising that the authors embraced the Principle in their reasoning. In light of its untoward implications that counter the positions they espoused in both their introductory and concluding remarks, a more appropriate response would have been to debunk its inclusion in the AMA Code.
Culpability
In discussing the importance of knowledge in these decisions, the authors refer to a study by Alexander and Wynia on the relationship between physicians' disaster response preparation and their willingness to respond. They note that those who felt “prepared to play a role in responding to a bioterror attack [were more] willing to work under conditions of personal risk.”12
Alexander GC, Wynia MK. Ready and willing? Physicians' sense of preparedness for bioterrorism. Health Affairs 2003;22:189–97.
It should be noted that allowing the fearful to exempt themselves from treating patients who pose a risk also leaves those physicians who feel duty bound to provide treatment with an undue share of the risk burden.
If there are particular things that every responsible physician should know in order to effectively respond during disasters, then continuing in ignorance is culpable. Instead of excusing physicians from an important component of their professional responsibility, the AMA should be taking steps to assure that every physician is prepared. Courses should be designed and required to update physicians in what they need to know and medical school curriculums should be adjusted to plug the gaps. After 9/11 and after Hurricane Katrina, no physician and no organization of medical professionals can legitimately turn a blind eye to this crucial aspect of medical responsibility.
Society's Responsibilities
The AMA's statement on “Physician Responsibilities in Disaster Preparedness and Response” mentions some areas where society has significant responsibilities. This important topic deserves further elaboration, and the AMA should be investing significant effort in advocating for the needed changes.
Medicine has the expertise that is crucial for useful and effective preparation for disasters. For that reason, medicine must be critically involved in planning and must be given the authority for implementing required preparatory measures. Medical experts in areas such as infectious disease, public health, emergency medicine, and toxicology can envision the kinds of health problems and medical needs that can arise in the aftermath of a disaster. Planning and preparation require their input along with the collaboration of police, fire departments, transportation departments, utilities, communications, and numerous other local, regional, and national agencies and institutions.
Furthermore, in many circumstances, some portion of the response to a disaster should be decided by medical experts. For example, determination of when it is safe to breath the air or drink the water requires medical expertise. Decisions on when an area must be quarantined because of the threat of infection require medical expertise. Decisions about when a population should or should not be vaccinated should turn on medical expertise. The authority for such decisions should, therefore, be left to medicine and not politics. Other related decisions, such as when to declare a state of emergency or evacuate an area, may require medical input along with the expertise of other agencies. Social measures should be taken to ensure an improved alignment of responsibility and expertise with authority.
In disasters, medicine and medical institutions are called on to do all that they can to address the medical needs of victims as well as the ongoing medical needs of patients. Under these remarkable conditions, some of the everyday rules that govern usual medical practice should be suspended. As part of disaster preparation, society owes healthcare providers and medical institutions legislation that makes the relaxation of rules legally explicit so that responders are not burdened by worries of legal liability as they try to meet pressing medical needs. In this regard, legislatures need to address questions such as the relaxation of rules governing credentialing, licensing, negligence, documentation, and reimbursement. In the same vein, medical institutions should not be called upon to bear an undue share of the expense for disaster response. As part of disaster preparations, legislatures should also set policies that make reimbursement for such expenses an explicit social responsibility, perhaps by extending Medicaid benefits to all disaster victims.
Principles of using what you already use frequently and investing in resources that have multiple uses are important concepts in disaster preparedness. That said, society has to accept responsibility for investments in planning, equipment, and training. Even though we hope to never have a disaster, and even though it is hard to divert resources to projects that may never be used when faced with immediately pressing needs, because they can help avert horrific outcomes, the investment in disaster preparedness must be made. We should keep in mind that the extensive advance planning and training in New York City made for an efficient and effective response to the 9/11 attacks on the World Trade Center even though the command center was destroyed in the first hours after the attack. Although the Department of Homeland Security has recently begun to make some effort toward preparation,14
AHRQ Publications No. 05-0043, Bioterrorism and other public health emergencies: Altered standards of care in mass casualty event, April 2005.