The American Medical Association's (AMA's) Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs' (CEJA's) new “Guidelines to Prevent the Malevolent Use of Biomedical Research” are both timely and appropriate. These guidelines are a product of the increasing realization of the “dual use” potential of life science discoveries. Although biomedical research usually aims at the development of new medicines, vaccines, diagnostics, and so on, the very same discoveries that could benefit humankind in these ways also often have implications for the development of biological weapons.1
U.S. National Research Council. Biotechnology Research in an Age of Terrorism. Washington, D.C.: The National Academies Press; 2004.
Green SK, Taub S, Morin K, Higginson D. Guidelines to Prevent Malevolent Use of Biomedical Research. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, this issue, 432–447.
See note 2, Green et al. 2006.
This CEJA should be praised for broadening the focus of research ethics guidelines, which have traditionally been primarily concerned with the protection of human participants in human experimentation,4
See note 2, Green et al. 2006.
Selgelid MJ. Smallpox revisited? American Journal of Bioethics 2003;3:W5–W11. Available at: http://www.bioethics.net/journal/j_articles.php?aid=91 (accessed Jul 19, 2005).
A panel of life sciences experts convened for the Strategic Assessments Group by the National Academy of Sciences concluded that advances in biotechnology … have the potential to create a much more dangerous biological warfare (BW) threat. The panel noted [that t]he effects of some of these engineered biological agents could be worse than any disease known to man.6
Central Intelligence Agency. The darker bioweapons future. November 2003. Available at: http://www.fas.org/irp/cia/product/bw1103.pdf (accessed Jul 19, 2005).
The kind of danger that the CEJA and CIA are concerned about is illustrated by the recent publication of two controversial studies (alluded to in the CEJA Guidelines). In one case, Australian researchers aiming to find a way to reduce mouse fertility as a means of pest control accidentally discovered that insertion of the IL-4 gene into the mousepox virus genome resulted in a superstrain of mousepox that killed mice that were naturally resistant to, and also mice that had been vaccinated against, the disease. The scientists proceeded to publish their findings—along with a description of their materials and methods—in 2001.7
Jackson RJ, Ramsay AJ, Christensen CD, Beaton S, Hall DF, Ramshaw IA. Expression of mouse interleukin-4 by a recombinant ectromelia virus suppresses cytolytic lymphocyte responses and overcomes genetic resistance to mousepox. Journal of Virology 2001;75:1205–10.
Cello J, Paul AV, Wimmer E. Chemical synthesis of poliovirus cDNA: Generation of infectious virus in the absence of natural template. Science 2002;297:1016–18. Available at: http://www.sciencemag.org/cgi/content/full/297/5583/1016 (accessed Jul 19, 2005).
Both of these studies have implications for smallpox—a disease that commonly tops lists of feared biological weapons agents. The polio study, for example, reveals that it might be possible to produce the smallpox virus through similar procedures. Although the smallpox virus is much larger than polio, the technical feasibility of artificially synthesizing smallpox is perhaps dubious. More fearsome is the possibility that the straightforward technique used on mousepox could allow the genetic engineering of vaccine-resistant smallpox. As there is no treatment for smallpox, vaccine is our only defense against this disease, which is believed to have killed more humans than any other infectious disease in history. Because routine vaccination ended more than 20 years ago, the world population now largely lacks immunity to smallpox, and modeling has shown that a smallpox attack could cause the devastation of nuclear attack(s).
Critics claim that neither of these discoveries should have been published. Their complaint is that publication of such studies both alerts would-be bioterrorists of possibilities and provides them with explicit instructions for producing potential weapons of mass destruction. The scientists and editors involved, however, claim that publication was warranted given the importance of alerting the scientific community to the kind of things we may need to prepare to defend ourselves against. These are clear examples of “dual use” discoveries: the same knowledge that may be harmfully used in weapons production has benefits with regard to biodefense.
Whether or not the mousepox and polio studies should have been conducted and/or published, the CEJA is right to draw the medical community's conscience to the potential dangers of both research and publication. It would be wrong to think that scientists should only be concerned with the generation of knowledge—which is often assumed to be inherently valuable for its own sake or, at worst, neutral. Because the misuse of knowledge would not be possible without its generation and dissemination in the first place, those who generate and disseminate potentially dangerous knowledge are ethically implicated in any misuse that occurs, especially when the harmful application of the knowledge in question is foreseeable.
This raises a difficult question left unanswered by the CEJA Guidelines. What should the process of censorship be? Given the importance of openness for scientific progress and the importance of transparency for public trust in science, the CEJA sounds generally (though not entirely) resistant to even self-censorship. For similar reasons, the U.S. National Research Council has explicitly argued against governmental censorship of “sensitive” information resulting from life science research, advocating “voluntary self-governance” of the scientific community as the preferred alternative.9
See note 1, U.S. National Research Council, 2004.
Though scientists should be encouraged to refrain from research with implications for weapons development and to voluntarily limit dissemination of research findings in cases where likely harms outweigh benefits, it is doubtful that the scientific community should be relied upon to regulate itself in such matters. This is simply because scientists will not always, contrary to what is said by the CEJA, be “in the best position to assess the potential for and the ramifications of misapplication of their research.”10
See note 2, Green et al. 2006.
Annas G. American Bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 2005:15.