Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-v2bm5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T14:54:35.451Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Addiction and Voluntariness: Five “Challenges” to Address in Moving the Discussion Forward

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 September 2019

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract:

The question as to whether people with an addiction have control (and to what extent) over their addiction, and voluntarily decide to use substances is an ongoing source of controversy in the context of research on addiction, health policy and clinical practice. We describe and discuss a set of five challenges for further research into voluntariness (definition[s], measurement and study tools, first person perspectives, contextual understandings, and connections to broader frameworks) based on our own research experiences and those of others.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019 

The question as to whether people with an addiction have control (and to what extent) over their addiction, and voluntarily decide to use substances is an ongoing source of controversy in the context of research on addiction, health policy and clinical practice.Footnote 1,Footnote 2,Footnote 3,Footnote 4 In the context of research, the ability for individuals with an addiction to consent to studies that involve decisions about their drug of use has led to heated debates about the voluntary nature of decisionmaking. Some scholars have emphasized the existence of impairments to voluntariness, noting that common understandings of addiction highlight these impairments.Footnote 5,Footnote 6 Accordingly, it could be unethical or contradictory to assume that people with addictions make autonomous, i.e., voluntary, decisions because they experience cravings and compulsions which overrule this aspect of their autonomous decisionmaking. Others have rejected these arguments and have restated the rather preserved autonomy of people with addictions,Footnote 7 such that their autonomy should not be considered lessened or refuted. Still, others have argued, in different ways, that decisionmaking capabilities, including the voluntariness of decisions, could be impeded to different degrees, in different situations, at different times, and in ways that call for nuanced and contextualized assessments of voluntariness.Footnote 8,Footnote 9,Footnote 10

The question of voluntariness in addiction, and the various perspectives to which it lends itself, is of direct relevance to health policy and healthcare practices. From a health policy perspective, whether addiction is a disease of choice or a conditionFootnote 11 over which one has no control matters.Footnote 12 This question has been at the core of the promotion of the brain-disease model of addiction,Footnote 13 which is often viewed as describing addiction as a biological condition for which control and voluntariness is impaired;Footnote 14 although stressing biological understandings of addiction does not necessarily lead to determinism.Footnote 15,Footnote 16 Indeed, lack of control can be associated with other accounts of addiction, including some which do not rely heavily on biological views.Footnote 17 Nonetheless, there remain controversies over the value of such biological accounts not only in terms of their descriptive adequacy, but also in terms of the promotion of more radical interventions such as neurostimulation and neurosurgery.Footnote 18,Footnote 19 Alternatively, emphasizing the chosen aspect of addiction can also lead to important implications. These are well exemplified in the repressive approaches adopted in some American states—and sometimes seducing the United Kingdom—toward women who drink while pregnant.Footnote 20,Footnote 21,Footnote 22,Footnote 23 Because of strong beliefs in individual autonomy and responsibility—to the detriment of more social analyses of addiction and alcohol use—some states have criminalized women who drink during pregnancy.Footnote 24,Footnote 25 Given that drinking during pregnancy is the cause of fetal alcohol spectrum disorder, the stakes are high for women who may be accused of not controlling themselves and of choosing to make the wrong decision, or of lacking the willpower to refrain from drinking.Footnote 26 This line of thinking, focused on the responsibility of women, can backlash into underuse of health services during pregnancy, which has severe implications for the health of both mother and child.Footnote 27,Footnote 28 In other clinical contexts, assessing the extent to which someone can take on treatment and be compliant is of crucial importance, since setting too high of a goal (e.g., complete abstinence) could be discouraging and impossible to meet, leading to counter-productive discouragement.Footnote 29 Accordingly, understanding the voluntary or involuntary nature of decisionmaking in the context of addiction has clear healthcare and ethical implications.

Voluntariness is crucial according to most accounts of ethics and of autonomyFootnote 30,Footnote 31,Footnote 32,Footnote 33 but it remains hard to assess and measure.Footnote 34 In fact, many research ethics, health policy and healthcare ethics debates could benefit from a greater conceptual and empirical understanding of voluntariness in the context of addiction. However, this type of research is challenging. To make headway in understanding the theoretical and methodological challenges of examining voluntariness, we pull from different traditions, some more quantitative coming mostly from psychology and cognitive science for example,Footnote 35 and others, more qualitative, coming mostly from the social sciences and humanities, notably via the influences of phenomenology and pragmatism.Footnote 36,Footnote 37,Footnote 38 We describe a set of five challenges for further research into this topic, based on our own research experiences and those of others. Our hope is to spark conversations about the future of interdisciplinary health ethics research on this topic.

Challenge 1: Definition(s)

One of the first challenges to reckon with is the plaguing problem of definitions and constructs used to capture voluntariness. Several different and somewhat neighboring concepts are used to examine voluntariness in the context of addiction (see Box 1). For example, the term “will” has important colloquial use. It is used when referring to freedom of the will, that is, the ability to make choices or act without restraint. It is also used when describing one’s capacity (or lack thereof) to carry out a specific task. For example, “I didn’t have the will to resist.” Other examples include “where there’s a will, there’s a way,” and “I willed it to happen.” Interestingly, discussions on addiction are sometimes situated within the context of an individual’s will. For example, addiction has been referred to as a “disease of the will,”Footnote 39 a “defect of the will,”Footnote 40 among other phrases related to the shortcomings or deficiencies of the will. In these instances, free will is the referent, but who is to say that a disease or defect of one’s willpower does not apply as well? Given the possible overlap between the two concepts, it is sometimes unclear which concept is being referred to in certain contexts. In fact, the use of “will” within the context of addiction can mean: (1) people with an addiction do not have the option to freely choose an alternative (free will), or (2) people with an addiction do not have the capacity to resist their drug of addiction (willpower). In the first scenario, will is situated within the context of choice; in the second, it is situated within the context of capability to act.Footnote 41

Box 1. Different concepts used to describe voluntariness in the context of addiction

* This list was generated using extensive key word searches with additional validation from expert reviewers with expertise in addiction, ethics, philosophy, and policy.

Beyond free will and willpower, many other concepts are used to explain volition and its failures in addiction. Concepts such as autonomy, self-regulation, self-control and compulsion are commonly investigated; each appears to capture part of what seems to be the issue at stake. However, the subtle theoretical differences between these constructs could potentially have an effect on treatment practices and research directions. For example, treatments targeting a lack of willpower could require a potentially different management approach than treatments focused on restoring autonomy. Similarly, research on the attribution of free will may draw on different investigative approaches in comparison to research examining lack of self-control. Here, we differentiate between five key concepts (self-control, free will, self-efficacy, autonomy, and locus of control) to highlight subtle nuances in how these terms have been used in the addiction literature.

First, the construct of self-control focuses on one’s ability to regulate aspects of oneself (for example, behavior, thoughts, emotions) by resisting or altering natural compulsions, urges, or desires.Footnote 42 Self-control and free will both examine dimensions of individual constraint. However, one construct examines the ability to maintain constraint (self-control), while the other examines freedom from it and general resistance to it (free will). Self-control “focuses on a specific set of internal constraints (temptations, desires, urges, needs, etc.),” whereas free will, or a belief in it, is concerned with freedom from all forms of constraints.Footnote 43 Self-efficacy on the other hand, has been described as a core judgment or evaluation of one’s ability to perform and succeed at tasks.Footnote 44,Footnote 45,Footnote 46 Researchers argue that self-efficacy is different from free will in that self-efficacy is concerned with one’s personal evaluation of efficacy, whereas free will captures aspects of choice and agency.Footnote 47 The differences between the two constructs have been described as being centered on the fact that “one can perceive the self as incapable and still believe that self is free to choose whether to undertake the action or not.”Footnote 48,Footnote 49 Although they are described as conceptually different constructs, there are some conceptual links between the two.Footnote 50 These relate to the fact that “free will beliefs affect intentional effort through perceived control and self-efficacy.”Footnote 51,Footnote 52

As for autonomy, scholars describe it as focused on regulation of the self, by the self.Footnote 53,Footnote 54,Footnote 55,Footnote 56 Autonomy refers to “the self as maintaining a separate and independent self from other agents, without addressing the many other types of constraints to free will, either external or internal.”Footnote 57 Measures of autonomy typically relate to constructs such as self-awareness, sensitivity to others, and self-efficacy.

The construct of locus of control refers to the degree to which one attributes outcomes to external or internal causes.Footnote 58,Footnote 59,Footnote 60 Individuals with an internally focused locus of control attribute the self and their own efforts as the cause of an outcome. Individuals with an externally focused locus of control attribute the cause of events to outside sources or external factors (e.g., luck, fate or powerful others).Footnote 61 Researchers have argued that locus of control and free will, as measured by the belief in free will, are different constructs,Footnote 62,Footnote 63 which capture two distinct properties. For example, locus of control focuses on the distinction between internal and external attributions, whereas belief in free will examines the origins of action and perceived choice of enacting said action.Footnote 64 Belief in free will does not examine whether actions led to a desired result, whereas locus of control does. All these constructs point to different potential views on voluntariness and, furthermore, different kinds of tools to measure or assess voluntariness in the context of addiction, and beyond. They enrich but complicate the attainment of a more comprehensive point of view.

Challenge 2: Measurement and study tools

Given the broad diversity of constructs used to examine voluntariness, numerous tools (e.g., psychometric scales) have been developed to “measure” or assess the different aspects of voluntariness. Each of these scales bears specific features and speaks to different aspects of voluntariness. Table 1 below provides information on seven constructs related to voluntariness (psychometric scales and their dimensions) based on preliminary review data from our own research. Within the context of addiction, these scales have been used to assess notions of impulsivity, volition, self-control, self-efficacy, free will and self-regulation in a variety of settings. For example, they have been used among people in rehabilitation, adolescents with substance use disorders, undergraduate psychology students, recreational marijuana users, veterans in alcohol detox programs, adolescents in outpatient treatment programs and residential treatment centers, as well as residential nicotine dependence programs. Additionally, these scales have been used in a variety of addiction-related contexts in different countries; for example, in Iran, Spain, Germany, Nigeria, United States, United Arab Emirates, Oman, Indonesia, Malaysia, Iceland, Poland and Norway.Footnote 65,Footnote 66,Footnote 67,Footnote 68,Footnote 69,Footnote 70,Footnote 71,Footnote 72,Footnote 73,Footnote 74,Footnote 75,Footnote 76,Footnote 77,Footnote 78,Footnote 79,Footnote 80

Table 1. Tools used to measure constructs related to voluntariness

Exploring voluntariness as captured through FW

Within experimental philosophy and social psychology, researchers have become increasingly interested in investigating voluntariness as captured through the construct of free will. Through the specific example of free will (represented as beliefs in free will [BFW]), we can see that the quantitative measurement of this construct sheds light on the different dimensions associated with voluntary action. For example, studies have examined the impact of belief in free will on general attitudes and behaviors. Results of these studies suggest that belief in free will has important implications for behaviour.Footnote 108,Footnote 109 For example, studies have found that people who believe in free will have more positive attitudes toward decisionmaking,Footnote 110 report higher levels of autonomy and more willingness to exert effort to not conform to group norms,Footnote 111 as well as higher levels of self-efficacy and lower levels of helplessness.Footnote 112 Studies have also found that belief in free will has an effect on job and academic performance,Footnote 113,Footnote 114 whereby those who believe in free will performed better in the workplace,Footnote 115 and on academic tasks (achieved better grades throughout the semester).Footnote 116

Studies also show that fluctuations in BFW have serious behavioral consequences.Footnote 117 Researchers report associations between diminished beliefs in free will and cheating behavior (after being exposed to deterministic discourse prompts).Footnote 118 They found that weakening beliefs in free will (or encouraging a belief in determinism) influences cheating behavior, whereby those who were presented with text encouraging them not to believe in free will were more likely to cheat on a test. Variations in BFW also affect levels of helpfulness and general temperament.Footnote 119 For instance, after reading phrases that undermined free will, participants were found to be less helpful and more aggressive to others.Footnote 120 Through these quantitative based experimental studies, we are able to understand components of free will and hypothesize what this can tell us about the voluntary components of behavior within the context of addiction. However, this begs the question: Can quantitative scales on beliefs in free will tell us what we need to know about the nuances of voluntary action? What might we not be able to capture through these forms of assessments?

Qualitative studies on voluntariness in addiction

In addition to more quantitative, scale-based studies of voluntariness, qualitative methods have been used and have yielded results which are sometimes compatible, and sometimes incompatible with scale-based assessments. Qualitative studies tend to offer more insights on how certain ways of thinking are inherently tied to personal narratives or specific contexts, often highlighting the limitations of scale based research into such an abstract topic. Interestingly, qualitative studies on voluntariness in addiction are perhaps less widespread than quantitative studies, but reveal just as much information, on the different dimensions of voluntary behavior. One particular dimension that tends to be ignored in quantitative assessments is the contextual or environmental aspect. In the context of addiction, as Neil Levy notes, one’s environment is of utmost importance, as social context has an impact on how one exercises self-control.Footnote 121 He notes that the social context is almost always missing from quantitative evaluations and argues that focusing on the experience of the person with an addiction outside of their immediate environment is misleading. Qualitative or ethnographic research that draws on the lived experience of the person can shed light on the impact of environmental or contextual factors on voluntary behavior.

In addition to the environmental/social context, other factors reportedly impact levels of self-control experienced. For example, the pursuit of strategies to mitigate one’s urges plays a very important role in maintaining control in addiction treatment.Footnote 122 A qualitative study exploring evaluations of the strength of one’s will among those who are substance dependent or in recovery found those who implemented strategies to be more successful in their recovery than those who did not.Footnote 123 Strategies included: changing one’s environment, controlling one’s emotions, counselling, eating well, occupying one’s mind and body, losing the victim mentality, and positive thinking. Anke Snoek, et al found that regardless of one’s recovery status, and despite levels of self-control reported, the majority of participants described themselves as strong-willed.Footnote 124 Their findings suggest that despite engaging in strategies to address one’s will, or even perceiving oneself as strong-willed, one can still struggle with substance abuse.

Furthermore, as it relates to volition and addiction, Mutsumi Karaski et al., describe two main arguments concerning voluntary behavior, that is: (1) people with addictions are lacking in volition, and (2) people with addictions have some level of control.Footnote 125 Their qualitative study examined how Australian service providers and policy makers discuss the role of volition in addiction. The authors cite differences in understandings of addiction and the role of volition in relation to four main factors: cravings, susceptibility, psychosocial factors, and self-concept. As it relates to the first factor (i.e., cravings), some participants believed that addicts have no control, and therefore, viewed cravings as impairing one’s sense of rationality. Others believed that addicts have some level of control, and thus viewed cravings as a stimulus that one becomes conditioned to respond to. The second factor, susceptibility, is more complex; participants perceived certain individuals as being more susceptible to addiction due to a range of risk factors. These included: genetics, environmental factors, and a lack of protective buffers. Some suggested that without protective factors, susceptible individuals would be more at risk; however, others noted that choice still plays a major role (regardless of susceptibility).

Participants also understood addiction in terms of psychosocial factors and viewed those with an addiction as having no control due to specific personality traits, such as, self-centeredness, self-obsession and emotional immaturity. However, others understood addiction through this lens, yet still attributed some amount of control to the person. In this regard, they understood addiction as resulting from psychological trauma which may have been exacerbated by social processes. Lastly, in understanding addiction through the lens of self-concept, some perceived addiction as limiting the control one has over one’s life, such that one’s personal development and self-actualization is compromised. On the other hand, it was also argued that labelling individuals as ‘addicts’ causes harm, as it has been found to have a self-fulfilling effect. These types of qualitative studies provide pertinent information on different understandings of volition, and the varying ways in which people think about control in the context of addiction. Such reports illustrate the subjective aspects of voluntariness and underscore the importance of unearthing them.

Challenge 3: First person perspectives

Yet another challenge of studying voluntariness is the inescapable allusion to the internal or subjective states and capacities of agents to act upon their situation and have control over their choices and actions. At least from the standpoint of more positivistic understandings of behavioral and social sciences, this is a problem because voluntariness can hardly be observed or measured without relying on self-reported measures. If this is the case, one might ask whether these measures can ever be objective and reliable, since an agent may have a self-interested tendency to diminish his or her ability for voluntary action. For a long time, this issue meant that voluntariness constructs had to be rooted out of psychological science and the social sciences more generally. However, explaining human behavior without appealing to the agent’s interpretation of his or her situation can become extremely complex and counterintuitive. For example, the desire of the person with an addiction to forget painful events, or self-medicate, may be put aside, diminishing the ability to understand the rationality of human behavior and the conflicting values and principles guiding one’s behavior. This is implicitly or explicitly the premise of much of contemporary humanities and social science research, in so far as economics, marketing sciences, psychology, etc., presume that individuals have the ability to undertake or refuse to undertake actions, although this ability may be diminished and influenced in all kinds of ways. These limitations are often the focus of research, since it is now well recognized that the exercise of one’s autonomy can be a significant source of well-being and human flourishing.Footnote 126,Footnote 127,Footnote 128 To the contrary, being prevented from acting voluntarily (or losing this ability), is a negative condition associated with states of despair, depression, apathy, and learned hopelessness.Footnote 129,Footnote 130

Given that the subjective aspect of voluntariness exists and needs to be understood, what strategies could be used to capture this feature of human behavior in credible and reliable ways? Qualitative research on decisionmaking in the context of addiction points to the importance of narratives to supplement more positivist third-person approaches. For example, May Tod Gray has investigated voluntariness from the point of view of those with an addiction, to explain how, in their own words, addiction is a challenge to the ability to make voluntary decisions.Footnote 131,Footnote 132 That being said, first-person accounts and subjective aspects of voluntariness in addiction are sometimes ill-captured and obfuscated by current quantitative measures.Footnote 133

Challenge 4: Contextual understandings

Voluntariness is typically measured through constructs which relate to (more or less stable) traits of the individual. But is it really possible to understand voluntariness in controlled experimental settings, or do we need to take into account the actual options offered to a person, his or her background, and the kind of substance at stake? Sometimes, voluntariness is abstracted from the situation as a form of disposition; in other instances, the agent’s capabilities are inherently tied to the situation. Regardless, we know that voluntariness is affected by situational factors, as shown by recent literature on belief in free will.Footnote 134 The contextual cues which can evoke memories of drug use are powerful forces against which the person with an addiction can be confronted. Odors, music, the presence of certain persons, the familiarity of certain places; all these features can lead to recall and potentially relapse. Accordingly, dispositional understandings of voluntariness—as measured by scales such as locus of control scales, or free will scales—may not tell the entire story about situational voluntariness, which could vary in time and space.Footnote 135 This observation is consistent with a vast literature on the ways in which agents act in context, and experience contexts as lived situations.Footnote 136,Footnote 137,Footnote 138,Footnote 139

To better account for the varying levels of voluntariness within persons with an addiction, repeated measures of will, control, and so on should be administered out across time to better investigate the fluctuating nature of voluntariness in the context of addiction. Furthermore, the qualitative methods described in the previous section can also be relevant for the study of situational factors which influence the agent’s situational voluntariness. Qualitative data can be a rich source of insight into the factors that affect a person’s ability to make voluntary decisions. Here, the use of ethnographic methods could be ideally suited to capture how different physical and interpersonal contexts (and variations therein) could impact voluntary abilities. Ethnographic methods often rely on the triangulation of different data gathering methods such as (direct or participant) observation, interviews, and document review.Footnote 140,Footnote 141,Footnote 142 They allow studying of institutional norms, structures and practices, in addition to the experiences of those living with addiction.

Overall, paying homage to the contextual effects implies adopting a concept of free will which grants the existence of its dynamic properties: that is, voluntariness can fluctuate like other components of autonomous choices (e.g., level of information).Footnote 143,Footnote 144,Footnote 145 A dynamic approach to free will sees voluntary action as represented by varying levels of voluntariness influenced by internal and external factors. Scholars have started to promote this more dynamic interpretation of free willFootnote 146 based on experimental findings.Footnote 147,Footnote 148,Footnote 149,Footnote 150 Appreciating and understanding voluntariness in contextual ways calls for a deepening of our views on human psychology and welcomes the incorporation of contexts (and their derived meanings) into our understanding of why people use or decide not to use certain addictive substances.

Challenge 5: Connections to broader frameworks

Finally, we want to put forth the idea that certain understandings of voluntariness (e.g., as an attribute solely of the individual) are embedded in broader epistemologies about the role of individuals in society (and the role of society toward individuals). For example, highlighting the individual nature of voluntary capabilities is consistent with broader political neoliberal assumptions which tend to individualize responsibility for health (including brain health, as in the case of neuro neoliberalism).Footnote 151,Footnote 152 Furthermore, the effect of discourses on biological, individual, and social causes of addiction is potentially a cause of stigmatization.Footnote 153,Footnote 154,Footnote 155

Other strategies that are more sensitive to the relational self could call for reformulations on how we view the role of agents within situations, and how we view the impact of socially-created situations (e.g., poverty, unemployment) on voluntariness in the context of addiction.Footnote 156 There is now clear evidence showing, for example, how level of education (higher education) leads to psychological profiles where autonomous choice, self-control, are not only present but valued.Footnote 157,Footnote 158,Footnote 159 Understanding how this highly valued trait is embedded in broader narratives that intersect with other categories such as gender, race, language, and so on, helps to highlight that the categories used in research and their intended role in broader discourse are anything but neutral. Accordingly, researchers need to reflect on their work because the epistemologies upon which they rely can be extended to contribute to broader social, political, and regulatory discourse about addiction.

The so-called “brain-hijack” theory of addiction is a clear example of how hyperbolic biological discourse can be used to discount voluntariness and lead to medicalized models of care and intervention.Footnote 160 The “brain-hijack theory” is at the core of the brain disease model of addiction, and is supported by neuroscience research.Footnote 161, Footnote 162 It posits that addiction is a brain disease caused by a dysfunction of brain systems involved in reward and pleasure seeking. According to this view, a greater emphasis on the biological aspects of addiction is a gateway to greater social acceptance of people with an addiction and destigmatization.Footnote 163,Footnote 164

Greater emphasis on the biological underpinnings of addiction may lead to the belief, in the eyes of those with more neuroscience knowledge, that one has less control over one’s addiction, as predicted by proponents of the brain-disease model of addiction.Footnote 165 However, this possibility is also the basis of the worries captured by critiques of the brain-disease model of addiction: namely, that neuroscience information about addiction can actually exacerbate blame and stigma because the person with an addiction is seen as less able to take care of him/herself.Footnote 166,Footnote 167 As a result of such beliefs, the person with an addiction may be considered passive and powerless, and relinquish his/her decisionmaking capacity to others such as healthcare professionals or state authorities.Footnote 168,Footnote 169 For example, a recent qualitative study found that the brain disease model risks downplaying the autonomy of those with an addiction.Footnote 170 This observation is made in the context of widespread dissemination of tangential deterministic interpretations of neuroscienceFootnote 171 undermining the existence of free will.Footnote 172

Such deterministic interpretations are not without consequence. Discussions about the “brain disease model” of addiction and the effects of neuroscience information on belief in free will have implications for treatment, policy and practice. Neuroscience information has been claimed to reduce the stigma associated with addictionFootnote 173 because they reduce beliefs about the free will of people with addiction as well as associated attributions of blame and personal responsibility.Footnote 174 On the other hand, neuroscience information has also been claimed to increase stigma because lessened attributions of free will infantilize individuals with an addiction and portray them as dangerous individuals lacking some basic requirement for decisionmaking and self-control.Footnote 175,Footnote 176 These are examples of the complex implications created by the connections between individual research studies and publications, broader epistemologies of addiction, and the need for greater clarity and reflexivity.

Conclusion

In this discussion paper, we explained how impaired voluntariness is not only a key aspect of addiction, but also an aspect which is of utmost importance for a series of ethical questions related to clinical care, research ethics and health policy practices and programs. We drew on work from cognitive science, neuroscience, experimental philosophy and social psychology to bridge current disciplinary divides. Based on our preliminary findings on the socio-ethical aspects of addiction as well as other scholarly work, we reviewed five important challenges emerging in the context of better understanding and appreciating voluntariness. We hope that this discussion will help broaden visions about voluntariness and the methodologies which can be used to better understand it. Furthermore, we hope that different quantitatively and qualitatively-oriented traditions will be taken up and put in dialogue to avoid bracketing voluntariness as a completely objective or a completely subjective phenomenon. Instead, we show how voluntariness is a complex intersubjective phenomenon with both individual and social dimensions. It is our conviction that both qualitative and quantitative methods are needed for a more comprehensive understanding of voluntariness in the context of addiction, and beyond.

Footnotes

Acknowledgement: Writing of this paper was supported by the Fonds de recherche du Québec – Santé and the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. We would like to thank Marianne Rochette, Sara Ferwati and Corinne Lajoie for assistance. This paper expands a previous blog post: Barned C, Racine E. Is the concept of “will” useful in explaining addictive behaviour? http://www.theneuroethicsblog.com/2018/08/is-concept-of-will-useful-in-explaining.html

References

Notes

1. Carter, A, Hall, W. Addiction Neuroethics: The Promises and Perils of Neuroscience Research on Addiction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 2012.Google Scholar

2. Levy, N. Addiction and Self-Control . New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3. Hart, CL. Viewing addiction as a brain disease promotes social injustice. Nature Human Behaviour 2017;1:0055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4. Leshner, A. Addiction is a brain disease, and it matters. Science 1997;278(5335):45–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

5. Charland, LC. Heroin addicts and consent to heroin therapy: A comment on Hall et al. (2003). Addiction 2003;98(11):1634–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

6. Charland, LC. Cynthia’s dilemma: Consenting to heroin prescription. The American Journal of Bioethics 2002;2(2):3747.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

7. Foddy, B, Savulescu, J. Addiction and autonomy: Can addicted people consent to the prescription of their drug of addiction? Bioethics 2006;20(1):115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8. Racine, E, Rousseau-Lesage, S. The voluntary nature of decision-making in addiction: Static metaphysical views versus epistemologically dynamic views. Bioethics 2017;31(5):349–59.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

9. Levy, N. Addiction, autonomy and ego-depletion: A response to Bennett Foddy and Julian Savulescu. Bioethics 2006;20(1):1620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10. Hall, W, Carter, L, Morley, K. Heroin addiction and the capacity for consent: A reply to Charland. Addiction 2003;98(12):1775–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

11. Holton, R, Berridge, K. Addiction between compulsion and choice. In: Levy, N, eds. Addiction and Self-control: Perspectives from Philosophy, Psychology, and Neuroscience . New York, NY: Oxford University Press; 2013:239–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12. Dackis, C, O’Brien, C. Neurobiology of addiction: Treatment and public policy ramifications. Nature Neuroscience 2005;8(11):1431–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

13. See note 4, Leshner 1997.

14. Hall, W, Carter, A, Forlini, C. The brain disease model of addiction: Is it supported by the evidence and has it delivered on its promises? Lancet Psychiatry 2015;2(1):105–10.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

15. See note 8, Racine, Rousseau-Lesage 2017.

16. See note 9, Levy 2006.

17. Caplan, A. Denying autonomy in order to create it: The paradox of forcing treatment upon addicts. Addiction 2008;103(12):1919–21.Google ScholarPubMed

18. Hall, W. Stereotactic neurosurgical treatment of addiction: Minimizing the chances of another ’great and desperate cure’. Addiction 2006;101(1):13.Google ScholarPubMed

19. Carter, A, Bell, E, Racine, E, Hall, W. Ethical issues raised by proposals to treat addiction using deep brain stimulation. Neuroethics 2011;4(2):129–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20. Drabble, L, Thomas, S, O’Connor, L, Roberts, SC. State responses to alcohol use and pregnancy: Findings from the alcohol policy information system (APIS). Journal of Social Work Practice 2014;14(2):191206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21. Leppo, A. The emergence of the foetus: Discourses on foetal alcohol syndrome prevention and compulsory treatment in Finland. Critical Public Health 2012;22(2):179–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22. Chavkin, W, Wise, PH, Elman, D. Policies towards pregnancy and addiction. Sticks without carrots. The Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1998;846(1):335–40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

23. Racine, E, Bell, E, Zizzo, N, Green, C. Public discourse on the biology of alcohol addiction: Implications for stigma, self-control, essentialism, and coercive policies in pregnancy. Neuroethics 2015;8(2):177–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

24. See note 20, Drabble et al. 2014.

25. See note 23, Racine et al. 2015.

26. See note 23, Racine et al. 2015.

27. Bell, E, Andrew, G, Di Pietro, N, Chudley, AE, Reynolds, J, Racine, E. It’s a shame! Stigma against fetal alcohol spectrum disorder: Examining the ethical implications for public health practices and policies. Public Health Ethics 2015;9(1):6577.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28. Eggertson, L. Stigma a major barrier to treatment for pregnant women with addictions. The Canadian Medical Association Journal 2013;185(18):1562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29. See note 8, Racine, Rousseau-Lesage 2017.

30. Dworkin, R. Liberalism. In: Hampshire S, eds. Public and Private Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1978, at 113–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

31. Dworkin, G. The Theory and Practice of Autonomy . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

32. Beauchamp, T, Childress, J. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 6th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 2009.Google Scholar

33. Grisso, T, Appelbaum, P. Assessing Competence to Consent to Treatment: A Guide for Physicians and Other Healthcare Professionals . New York: Oxford University Press; 1998.Google Scholar

34. Mamotte, N, Wassenaar, D. Measuring voluntariness of consent to research: An instrument review. The Journal of Empirical Research on Human Research Ethics 2015;10(2):121–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

35. Vohs, KD, Baumeister, RF. Addiction and free will. Addiction Research and Theory 2009;17(3):231–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

36. Gray, MT. Freedom and resistance: The phenomenal will in addiction. Nursing Philosophy 2007;8(1):315.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

37. Gray, MT. William James’s radical empiricism and the phenomenology of addiction: A philosophical inquiry [dissertation]. New York University;2003.Google Scholar

38. Nahmias, E, Morris, S, Nadelhoffer, T, Turner, J. The phenomenology of free will. Journal of Consciousness Studies 2004;11(7–8):162–79.Google Scholar

39. Volkow, N. Addiction is a disease of free will. 2015 June 12. In: National Institute on Drug Abuse Blog [Internet]; available at https://www.drugabuse.gov/about-nida/noras-blog/2015/06/addiction-disease-free-will (last accessed Mar 14 2019).Google Scholar

40. Wallace, RJ. Addiction as defect of the will: Some philosophical reflections. Law and Philosophy 1999;18(6):621–54.Google Scholar

41. Barned C, Racine E. Is the concept of “will” useful in explaining addictive behaviour? 2018 Aug 07. In: The Neuroethics Blog [Internet]. Atlanta, GA: The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience; available at http://www.theneuroethicsblog.com/2018/08/is-concept-of-will-useful-in-explaining.html (last accessed 14 Mar 2019).

42. Feldman, G, Chandrashekar, SP, Wong, KFE. The freedom to excel: Belief in free will predicts better academic performance. Personality and Individual Differences 2016;90:377–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

43. See note 42, Feldman et al. 2016.

44. Feldman, G. Making sense of agency: Belief in free will as a unique and important construct. Social and Personality Psychology Compass 2017;11(1):115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

45. Judge, TA, Locke, EA, Durham, CC. The dispositional causes of job satisfaction: A core evaluations approach. Research in Organizational Behavior 1997;19:151–88.Google Scholar

46. Bandura, A, Ramachaudran, VS. Self-efficacy. In: Corsini, RJ, eds. Encyclopedia of Psychology , 2nd ed. New York, NY: Wiley; 1994:368–9.Google Scholar

47. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

48. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

49. Sappington, A. Recent psychological approaches to the free will versus determinism issue. Psychological Bulletin 1990;108(1):1929.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

50. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

51. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

52. Rigoni, D, Kuhn, S, Sartori, G, Brass, M. Inducing disbelief in free will alters brain correlates of preconscious motor preparation: The brain minds whether we believe in free will or not. Psychological Science 2011;22(5):613–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

53. See note 31, Dworkin 1988.

54. Frankfurt, HG. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 1971;68(1):520.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

55. Felsen, G, Reiner, PB. How the neuroscience of decision making informs our conception of autonomy. The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 2011;2(3):314.Google Scholar

56. Friedrich O, Racine E, Steinert S, Pömsl J, Jox, RJ. An analysis of the impact of brain-computer interfaces on autonomy. Neuroethics 2018;113.Google Scholar

57. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

58. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

59. Rotter, JB. Generalized expectancies for internal versus external control of reinforcement. Psychological Monographs: General and Applied 1966;80(1):128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

60. Sheffer, C, MacKillop, J, McGeary, J, Landes, R, Carter, L, Yi, R, et al. Delay discounting, locus of control, and cognitive impulsiveness independently predict tobacco dependence treatment outcomes in a highly dependent, lower socioeconomic group of smokers. The American Journal on Addictions 2012;21(3):221–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

61. See note 60, Sheffer et al. 2012.

62. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

63. Stillman, TF, Baumeister, RF, Mele, AR. Free will in everyday life: Autobiographical accounts of free and unfree action. Philosophical Psychology 2011;24(3):381–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

64. See note 44, Feldman 2017.

65. Fernández-Serrano, MJ, Perales, JC, Moreno-López, L, Pérez-García, M, Verdejo-García, A. Neuropsychological profiling of impulsivity and compulsivity in cocaine dependent individuals. Psychopharmacology 2012;219(2):673–83.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

66. Harrison, EL, Coppola, S, McKee, SA. Nicotine deprivation and trait impulsivity affect smokers’ performance on cognitive tasks of inhibition and attention. Experimental and Clinical Psychopharmacology 2009;17(2):91–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

67. Ansell, EB, Laws, HB, Roche, MJ, Sinha, R. Effects of marijuana use on impulsivity and hostility in daily life. Drug and Alcohol Dependence 2015;148:136–42.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

68. Blanchard, BE, Stevens, AK, Littlefield, AK, Talley, AE, Brown, JL. Examining the link between nonmedical use of sedatives, tranquilizers, and pain relievers with dispositions toward impulsivity among college students. Addictive Behaviors 2017;69:813.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

69. Torres, A, Catena, A, Megías, A, Maldonado, A, Cándido, A, Verdejo-García, A, et al. Emotional and non-emotional pathways to impulsive behavior and addiction. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 2013;7:43.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

70. Abbott, MW. Locus of control and treatment outcome in alcoholics. Journal of Studies on Alcohol 1984;45(1):4652.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

71. Bunch, J, Schneider, H. Smoking-specific locus of control. Psychological Reports 1991;69(3_suppl):1075–81.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

72. Abikoye, G, Fusigboye, A. Gender, locus of control and smoking habits of undergraduate students. African Journal of Drug and Alcohol Studies 2010;9(2):7180.Google Scholar

73. Johnson, EE, Nora, RM, Tan, B, Bustos, N. Comparison of two locus of control scales in predicting relapse in an alcoholic population. Perceptual and Motor Skills 1991;72(1):4350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

74. Natera, G, Herrejon, M, Casco, M. Locus of control in couples with different patterns of alcohol consumption. Drug and Alcohol Dependence 1988;22(3):179–86.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

75. Oswald, LM, Walker, GC, Reilly, EL, Krajewski, KJ, Parker, CA. Measurement of locus of control in cocaine abusers. Issues in Mental Health Nursing 1992;13(2):8194.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

76. Adalbjarnardottir, S, Rafnsson, FD. Perceived control in adolescent substance use: Concurrent and longitudinal analyses. Psychology of Addictive Behaviors 2001;15(1):2532.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

77. Bamford, Z, Booth, PG, McGuire, J, Salmon, P. Minimal intervention as a preparation for the treatment of alcohol dependency. British Journal of Clinical Psychology 2005;44(2):289–94.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

78. Asselmann, E, Hilbert, K, Hoyer, J, Wittchen, HU, Lieb, R, Bühringer, G, et al. Self-reported volitional control in adolescents and young adults from a community cohort: Associations with current, past and future mental disorders. Psychiatry Research 2018;260:292–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

79. Bakhshani, NM, Hossienbor, M. A comparative study of self-regulation in substance dependent and non-dependent individuals. Global Journal of Health Science 2013;5(6):40–5.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

80. Baer, JS, Lichtenstein, E. Classification and prediction of smoking relapse episodes: An exploration of individual differences. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 1988;56(1):104–10.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

81. Whiteside, SP, Lynam, DR. The five factor model and impulsivity: Using a structural model of personality to understand impulsivity. Personality and Individual Differences 2001;30(4):669–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

82. Patton, JH, Stanford, MS, Barratt, ES. Factor structure of the Barratt impulsiveness scale. Journal of Clinical Psychology 1995;51(6):768–74.3.0.CO;2-1>CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

83. Rakos, RF, Steyer, KR, Skala, S, Slane, S. Belief in free will: Measurement and conceptualization innovations. Behavior and Social Issues 2008;17(1):2039.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

84. Rotter, JB. Some problems and misconceptions related to the construct of internal versus external control of reinforcement. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 1975;43(1):56–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

85. Donovan, DM, O’Leary, MR. The Drinking-Related Locus of Control Scale. Reliability, factor structure and validity. Journal of Studies on Alcohol 1978;39(5):759–84.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

86. Craig, AR, Franklin, JA, Andrews, G. A scale to measure locus of control of behaviour. British Journal of Medical Psychology 1984;57(2):173–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

87. See note 59, Rotter 1966.

88. Worell, L, Tumilty, TN. The measurement of locus of control among alcoholics. In: Lefcourt, HM, ed. Research with the Locus of Control. New York, NY: Acadamic Press; 1981:1321.Google Scholar

89. Grasmick, HG, Tittle, CR, Bursik, RJ Jr, Arneklev, BJ. Testing the core empirical implications of Gottfredson and Hirschi’s general theory of crime. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 1993;30(1):529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

90. Tangney, JP, Baumeister, RF, Boone, AL. High self-control predicts good adjustment, less pathology, better grades, and interpersonal success. Journal of Personality 2004;72(2):271324.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

91. Kendall, PC, Wilcox, LE. Self-control in children: Development of a rating scale. Journal of Consulting and Clinical psychology 1979;47(6):1020–9.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

92. de Vries, H, Dijkstra, M, Kuhlman, P. Self-efficacy: The third factor besides attitude and subjective norm as a predictor of behavioural intentions. Health Education Research 1988;3(3):273–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

93. Schwarzer, R, Jerusalem M. Generalized self-efficacy scale. In: Weinman, J, Wright, S, Johnston, M, eds. Measures in Health Psychology: A User’s Portfolio. Causal and Control Belief . Windsor: NFER-NELSON; 1995:35–7.Google Scholar

94. Breslin, FC, Sobell, LC, Sobell, MB, Agrawal, S. A comparison of a brief and long version of the Situational Confidence Questionnaire. Behaviour Research and Therapy 2000;38(12):1211–20.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

95. Ilfeld, FW. Psychologic status of community residents along major demographic dimensions. Archives of General Psychiatry 1978;35(6):716–24.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

96. Annis, HM, Davis, CS. Assessment of expectancies. In: Donovan, DM, Marlatt, GA, eds. The Guilford Behavioral Assessment Sesies. Assessment of Addictive Behaviors. New York, NY: The Guilford Press; 1988:84111Google Scholar

97. Young, RM, Oei, TP, Crook, G. Development of a drinking self-efficacy questionnaire. Journal of Psychopathology and Behavioral Assessment 1991;13(1):115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

98. Gwaltney, CJ, Shiffman, S, Normal, GJ, Paty, JA, Kassel, JD, Gnys, M, et al. Does smoking abstinence self-efficacy vary across situations? Identifying context-specificity within the Relapse Situation Efficacy Questionnaire. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 2001;69(3):516–27.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

99. Oei, TP, Hasking, PA, Young, RM. Drinking refusal self-efficacy questionnaire-revised (DRSEQ-R): A new factor structure with confirmatory factor analysis. Drug and Alcohol Dependence 2005;78(3):297307.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

100. DiClemente, CC, Carbonari, JP, Montgomery, R, Hughes, SO. The alcohol abstinence self-efficacy scale. Journal of Studies on Alcohol 1994;55(2):141–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

101. Velicer, WF, Diclemente, CC, Rossi, JS, Prochaska, JO. Relapse situations and self-efficacy: An integrative model. Addictive Behaviors 1990;15(3):271–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

102. Conners, NA, Bradley, RH, Whiteside-Mansell, L, Crone, CC. A comprehensive substance abuse treatment program for women and their children: An initial evaluation. Journal of Substance Abuse Treatment 2001;21(2):6775.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

103. Condiotte, MM, Lichtenstein, E. Self-efficacy and relapse in smoking cessation programs. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 1981;49(5):648–58.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

104. Brown, JM, Miller, WR, Lawendowski, LA. The self-regulation questionnaire. In: VandeCreek, L, Jackson, TL, eds. Innovation in Clinical Practice: A Sourcebook. Sarasota, FL: Professional Resource Press/Professional Resource Exchange; 1999:281–92.Google Scholar

105. Carey, KB, Neal, DJ, Collins, SE. A psychometric analysis of the self-regulation questionnaire. Addictive Behaviors 2004;29(2):253–60.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

106. Ibánez, MI, Ruipérez, MA, Moya, J, Marqués, MJ, Ortet, G. A short version of the self-regulation inventory (SRI-S). Personality and Individual Differences 2005;39(6):1055–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

107. Kuhl, J, Fuhrmann, A. Decomposing self-regulation and self-control: The volitional components inventory. In: Heckhausen, J, Dweck, CS, eds. Motivation and Self-Regulation Across the Life Span. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press; 1998:1449.Google Scholar

108. See note 42, Feldman et al. 2016.

109. Brass, M, Lynn, MT, Demanet, J, Rigoni, D. Imaging volition: What the brain can tell us about the will. Experimental Brain Research 2013;229(3):301–12.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

110. Feldman, G, Baumeister, RF, Wong, KFE. Free will is about choosing: The link between choice and the belief in free will. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 2014;55:239–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

111. Alquist, JL, Ainsworth, SE, Baumeister, RF. Determined to conform: Disbelief in free will increases conformity. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 2013;49(1):80–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

112. Baumeister, RF, Brewer, LE. Believing versus disbelieving in free will: Correlates and consequences. Social and Personality Psychology Compass 2012;6(10):736–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

113. See note 42, Feldman et al. 2016.

114. Stillman, TF, Baumeister, RF, Vohs, KD, Lambert, NM, Fincham, FD, Brewer, LE. Personal philosophy and personnel achievement: Belief in free will predicts better job performance. Social Psychological and Personality Science 2010;1(1):4350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

115. See note 114, Stillman 2010.

116. See note 42, Feldman et al. 2016.

117. Crescioni, AW, Baumeister, RF, Ainsworth, SE, Ent, MR, Lambert, NM. Subjective correlates and consequences of belief in free wil. Philosophical Psychology 2016;29(1):4163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

118. Vohs, KD, Schooler, JW. The value of believing in free will: Encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating. Psychological Science 2008;19(1):4954.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

119. Baumeister, RF, Masicampo, EJ, DeWall, CN. Prosocial benefits of feeling free: Disbelief in free will increases aggression and reduces helpfulness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 2009;35(2):260–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

120. See note 119, Baumeister et al. 2009.

121. Levy, N. The social: A missing term in the debate over addiction and voluntary control. The American Journal of Bioethics 2007;7(1):35–6.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

122. Snoek, A, Levy, N, Kennett, J. Strong-willed but not successful: The importance of strategies in recovery from addiction. Addictive Behaviors Reports 2016;4:102–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

123. See note 122, Snoek et al. 2016.

124. See note 122, Snoek et al. 2016.

125. Karasaki, M, Fraser, S, Moore, D, Dietze, P. The place of volition in addiction: Differing approaches and their implications for policy and service provision. Drug and Alcohol Review 2013;32(2):195204.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

126. Ryff, CD. Psychological well-being revisited: Advances in the science and practice of eudaimonia. Psychotherapy and Psychosomatics 2014;83(1):1028.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

127. Ryff, CD. Happiness is everything, or is it? Explorations on the meaning of psychological well-being. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 1989;57(6):1069–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

128. Ryan, RM, Deci, EL. Self-determination theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation, social development, and well-being. American Psychologist 2000;55(1):6878.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

129. Wegener, JR, Ludlow, Clark E., Olsen, Ammon J., Tortosa, Marta, Wintch, Philip H. Ego depletion: A contributing factor of hopelessness depression. Intuition 2007;3(1):12–7.Google Scholar

130. Seligman, MEP. Helplessness: On Depression, Development, and Death. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman; 1975.Google Scholar

131. See note 36, Gray 2007.

132. See note 37, Gray 2004.

133. Racine, E. A proposal for a scientifically-informed and instrumentalist account of free will and voluntary action. Frontiers in Psychology 2017;8:754.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

134. Ewusi-Boisvert, E, Racine, E. A critical review of methodologies and results in recent research on belief in free will. Neuroethics 2018;11(1):97110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

135. See note 9, Levy 2006.

136. See note 133, Racine 2017.

137. Rauthmann, JF, Sherman, RA, Funder, DC. Principles of situation research: Towards a better understanding of psychological situations. European Journal of Personality 2015;29(3):363–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

138. Racine E, Saigle V. Static and dynamic metaphysics of free will: A pragmatic perspective. 2014 Jan 14. In: The Neuroethics Blog [Internet]. Atlanta, GA: The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience; available at http://www.theneuroethicsblog.com/2014/01/static-and-dynamic-metaphysics-of-free.html (last accessed 14 Mar 2019).

139. Dewey, J. Human Nature and Conduct: An Introduction to Social Psychology . New York, NY: Holt; 1922.Google Scholar

140. Hammersley, M, Atkinson, P. Ethnography: Principles in Practice . London: Routledge; 2007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

141. Knoblauch, H. Focused ethnography. Forum Qualitative Sozialforschung/Forum: Qualitative Social Research 2005;6(3):44.Google Scholar

142. Hoffmaster, B. Can ethnography save the life of medical ethics? Social Science & Medicine 1992; 35(12):1421–31.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

143. See note 133, Racine 2017.

144. See note 134, Ewusi-Boisvert, Racine 2018.

145. See note 138, Racine, Saigle 2014.

146. See note 8, Racine, Rousseau-Lesage 2017.

147. See note 129, Wegener et al. 2007.

148. See note 118, Vohs, Schooler 2008.

149. See note 138, Racine, Saigle 2014.

150. Racine, E, Sattler, S, Escande, A. Free will and the brain disease model of addiction: The not so seductive allure of neuroscience and its modest impact on the attribution of free will to people with an addiction. Frontiers in Psychology 2017;8:1850.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

151. Pitts-Taylor, V. The plastic brain: Neoliberalism and the neuronal self. Health 2010;14(6):635–52.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

152. Racine, E, Aspler, J, Forlini, C, Chandler, J. Contextualized autonomy and liberalism: Broadening the lenses on complementary and alternative medicines in preclinical Alzheimer’s disease. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 2017;27(1):141CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

153. See note 23, Racine et al. 2015.

154. Aspler, J, Zizzo, N, Di Pietro, N, Racine, E. Stereotyping and stigmatising disability: A content analysis of canadian print news media about fetal alcohol spectrum disorder. Canadian Journal of Disability Studies 2018;7(3):89121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

155. Sattler, S, Escande, A, Racine, E, Göritz, AS. Public stigma toward people with drug addiction: A factorial survey. Journal of Studies on Alcohol and Drugs 2017;78(3):415–25.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

156. See note 8, Racine, Rousseau-Lesage 2017.

157. See note 128, Ryan and Deci 2000.

158. Say, R, Murtagh, M, Thomson, R. Patients’ preference for involvement in medical decision making: A narrative review. Patient Education and Counseling 2006;60(2):102–14.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

159. Zizzo, N, Bell, E, Lafontaine, A-L, Racine, E. Examining chronic care patient preferences for involvement in healthcare decision making: The case of early stage Parkinson’s disease patients in a patient-centred clinic. Health Expectations 2016;20(4):655–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

160. Harvard Mental Health Letter. How addiction hijacks the brain. Desire initiates the process, but learning sustains it. The Harvard Mental Health Letter 2011;28(1):13.Google Scholar

161. See note 4, Leshner 1997.

162. Volkow, ND, Li, TK. Drugs and alcohol: Treating and preventing abuse, addiction and their medical consequences. Pharmacology and Therapeutics 2005;108(1):317.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

163. See note 12, Dackis, O’Brien 2005.

164. Hyman, SE. The neurobiology of addiction: Implications for voluntary control of behavior. The American Journal of Bioethics 2007;7(1):811.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

165. See note 12, Dackis, O’Brien 2005.

166. Hammer, R, Dingel, M, Ostergren, J, Partridge, B, McCormick, J, Koenig, BA. Addiction: Current criticism of the brain disease paradigm. The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 2013;4(3):2732.Google ScholarPubMed

167. Szott, K. Contingencies of the will: Uses of harm reduction and the disease model of addiction among health care practitioners. Health 2015;19(5):507–22.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed

168. See note 23, Racine et al. 2015.

169. Gartner, CE, Carter, A, Partridge, B. What are the public policy implications of a neurobiological view of addiction? Addiction 2012;107(7):1199–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

170. See note 167, Szott 2015.

171. Racine, E, Nguyen, V, Saigle, V, Dubljevic, V. Media portrayal of a landmark neuroscience experiment on free will. Science and Engineering Ethics 2018;23(4):9891007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

172. Saigle, V, Dubljevic, V, Racine, E. The impact of a landmark neuroscience study on “free will”: A review of articles using Libet et al.’s methods. The American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 2018;9(1):2941.Google Scholar

173. See note 12, Dackis, O’Brien 2005.

174. See note 23, Racine et al. 2015.

175. See note 23, Racine et al. 2015.

176. See note 167, Szott 2015.

Figure 0

Box 1. Different concepts used to describe voluntariness in the context of addiction

Figure 1

Table 1. Tools used to measure constructs related to voluntariness