I. Introduction
B engages an independent contractor, C. C negligently injures A. Can A sue B for the harm caused by the contractor (assuming that B is himself blameless)? When A has a contract with B, he will normally be able to recover (depending ultimately on the terms of the contract). But not in tort. Only if B's duty is (exceptionally) “non-delegable” must he answer for C's negligence (outside torts of strict liability, such as Rylands v Fletcher). This article explains the doctrinal cogency of that elementary distinction between contract and tort. It warns against drawing simple analogies between them (especially to justify liability in tort by considering B's liability had a hypothetical contract existed between A and B). This aspect of the recent decision in Woodland v Swimming Teachers Association is criticised accordingly.Footnote 1 Drawing analogies might appear to be a simple common-sense matter, and indeed the foundation of the common law technique. But it is in fact no value-neutral exercise, whether in private law or high constitutional matters.Footnote 2 Moreover, doctrinal reasoning can take us only so far. There are bigger questions lurking here. In the space of this article (with its primary focus on the doctrinal differences between contract and tort), we can only identify those bigger questions, and not provide final answers to them. The immanent controversy arises from the increasingly common use of independent contractors (“outsourcing”) in the modern economy. This social phenomenon raises questions about the traditional limitation of vicarious liability to the employment relationship. To date, there has been little appetite for questioning the axiom that there is no vicarious liability for independent contractors. It should now be openly debated. This article clears the ground for that consideration to proceed.
II. Woodland v Swimming Teachers Association
Miss Woodland was injured during a swimming lesson organised as part of the curriculum at her state primary school – allegedly due to negligent supervision by the lifeguard on duty at a pool belonging to a local authority (Basildon Council) other than the one responsible for the claimant's school (Essex County Council). Basildon had outsourced provision of lessons and lifeguard services to an independent contractor (Direct Swimming Services). Miss Woodland claimed against the lifeguard, the contractor, their common insurer (the first named defendant), and against both local authorities. On the bare facts, any claim against the authorities was destined to fail unless they owed the claimant a “non-delegable duty” rendering them liable for the contractor's negligence. Differing from the courts below, the Supreme Court identified such a “non-delegable duty” and declined to strike the claims out.
Lord Sumption identified the claim as one falling under a second general heading of “non-delegable duties” in English law (i.e. not the much-criticised category of “inherently hazardous operations”), namely where, pursuant to an “antecedent relationship” between the parties:
… the defendant is assuming a liability analogous to that assumed by a person who contracts to do work carefully. … The analogy with public services is often close, especially in the domain of hospital treatment in the National Health Service or education at a local education authority school, where only the absence of consideration distinguishes them from the private hospital or the fee-paying school performing the same functions under contract.Footnote 3
Lord Sumption further reasoned that, as fee-paying schools' responsibilities “are already non-delegable because they are contractual”, there was “in this particular context … no rational reason why the mere absence of consideration should lead to an entirely different result when comparable services are provided by a public authority”.Footnote 4 His Lordship similarly criticised “the technical distinctions that would otherwise arise between privately funded and NHS hospital treatment”.Footnote 5
Most would feel instinctive sympathy with an innocent child's severe injuries. That makes the result in Woodland hard to criticise. But the reasoning is not unproblematic. It is questionable whether the local authorities had really “voluntarily assumed responsibility” for the way that the contractors taught the claimant to swim, let alone for the contractors' solvency. Moreover, the advantageous position of claimants suing private schools and hospitals in contract does not of itself justify the extension of public service providers' liability in tort. People can always in principle bargain for greater rights (including protection against injury) through a contract. Potential contractual liability can hardly then be a guide for the limits of tort (it would essentially abolish any limits). The proper relationship between contract and tort is controversial, and historically fluid. Stated very crudely, the prevailing view today is that tort should set the baseline of safety that everyone is entitled to expect, irrespective of payment. People are free to use their wealth to purchase additional services (including higher standards of care) if they like. But, if consumers have to pay to get reasonable care – if payment is not merely for luxuries (“optional extras”) – we face the “uncomfortable” feeling that the tort baseline falls unacceptably short.Footnote 6 Criticism of the (over-)advantageous position of contracting parties in fact expresses dissatisfaction with the inadequacy of tort. Tort would then need to reassess its own contours of liability, without the argument (which always proves too much) that paying consumers might have more extensive rights of action under contract. Liability for breach of contact is usually strict – is that unfair on tort claimants who are usually required to prove fault?
III. Contract and Tort
There are many situations where liability is quite unproblematic in contract (e.g. for omissions, for pure economic loss) while controversial in tort. Many have argued for the expansion of tort liability in these areas, for various reasons. But few before Woodland passed from the trite observation that, had a contract existed between the parties, the defendant would have been liable to assert that therefore there must be liability in tort. Such reasoning seems dubious. Within the outer limits of public policy (e.g. illegality), there are few obligations that cannot be deliberately created by a suitably drafted contract. If tort liability always tracked the potential liabilities that parties could have created by contracting (although they actually did not contract), it would know virtually no bounds. This limitless expansion of tort would make much contracting redundant. Why contract for (and pay for) an obligation that the law of torts anyway imposes on the prospective promisor?Footnote 7
That last statement might be thought to prove too much. Is it not always the case that tort liability gives claimants “free” what they would otherwise had to have paid (contracted) for? Blanket disapproval of such “free-riding” leads directly back to the nineteenth-century world of very limited tort liability. Far from the post-Donoghue v Stevenson presupposition that we are all entitled to expect reasonable care from our neighbour, “in the period of classical contract law [c. 1770–1870], a right to due care was still largely seen as something for which [people] had to pay”Footnote 8:
In classical law it was clear that the promise principle was not merely an affirmative principle of liability, but also an exclusionary principle of no liability. In general, if you promised, you were liable, but if you did not promise, then conversely you were not liable …. Nor was this exclusionary function of promising purely the result of formalism or of limited vision. It reflected an ideological commitment to the respect for individual autonomy.Footnote 9
Winterbottom v Wright was not flawed by a logical fallacy that “escaped the perspicuity of judges like Abinger C.B.” only to be “brilliantly exposed” in Donogue v Stevenson.Footnote 10 That familiar fable (“what passes for legal reasoning in students' textbooks”) is “almost complete nonsense”; the court in Winterbottom relied on policy, not (fallacious) doctrinal “logic”.Footnote 11 Only the customer who paid for the goods should be entitled to sue the manufacturer in respect of defects, they reasoned. It looks one-sided today: what about the competing policy of consumer protection for injured bystanders? But Donoghue v Stevenson represents a policy choice – ultimately an “ideological commitment” – as much as the Court of Exchequer's in Winterbottom v Wright. The shift from contract to tort was “essentially designed to be redistributive”.Footnote 12
Atiyah hailed the “Fall of Freedom of Contract” in the mid-twentieth century (prematurely, as he came to admit). But tort liability has certainly expanded. The universal duty to exercise due care was couched in moral (indeed Biblical) terms by Lord Atkin in Donoghue v Stevenson. More prosaically, for Lord Reid “life would be impossible in modern conditions unless on the highway and in the market place we were entitled to rely on the other man behaving like a reasonable man”.Footnote 13 These are general duties arising between strangers, between everyone. Lawyers today take this for granted, yet the contrast with the “heyday of classical contract theory, when nearly all liabilities were thought to depend on some element of free choice, or consent”, is striking.Footnote 14
Far from the absence of contract excluding tort liability (through “respect for individual autonomy”), Markesinis argued (addressing unreformed privity of contract) that English law has “An expanding tort law – [as] the price of a rigid contract law”.Footnote 15 Atiyah also welcomed recourse to tort where the absence of contractual liability arises from “arbitrary and perhaps technical restrictions”.Footnote 16 The high water mark in pure economic loss liability came in 1982 with Junior Books v Veichi.Footnote 17 But, within a decade, the courts had accepted that recognising tort duties of care within large construction/engineering projects risked subverting the contractual structure.Footnote 18 Even Atiyah agreed that cases involving “a deliberate refusal to accept responsibility in contract” should be treated differently.Footnote 19 Subcontractors' and suppliers' roles are deliberately separated from main contractors'. “There simply is no point in this elaborate set of commercial arrangements if the various parties are all liable for negligence in tort anyhow.”Footnote 20 To avoid “free-riding”, tort “should not duplicate opportunities of protection of the plaintiff and deterrence of the defendant which were already available to the plaintiff but which the plaintiff failed to take”.Footnote 21 Atiyah nevertheless observed that to accept this critique of Junior Books one must “follow the ideology of the New Right” with its “great revival of belief in Freedom of Contract”.Footnote 22 Fleming, too, argued that denying actions to those deemed capable of protecting themselves through contract reflected “the primacy of private ordering, expressing the ideology of the free-marketers of the 80s”.Footnote 23 Such arguments receive corroboration from the opposition of Judge Richard Posner to economic loss liability in tort. Posner J. prefers to describe it as “commercial loss” to make the point that “tort law is a superfluous and inapt tool for resolving purely commercial disputes. We have a body of law designed for such disputes. It is called contract law”.Footnote 24
Thus, whether to impose tort liability in the absence of a contract is no dry, technical question. Even to (“merely”) fill “gaps” assumes what “full” protection requires. If the parties could have contracted for the obligation, does tort liability not (at best) give the claimant something for nothing or (at worst) upset the parties' intentional exclusion of liability inter se? Such reasoning has now been accepted in some pure economic loss cases.Footnote 25 It does assume the primacy of contractual arrangements, as Fleming and Atiyah point out.Footnote 26 Arguably, today's “intellectual climate”, like that of the early nineteenth century, subscribes to “Free choice in all things, rational planning, calculated risk assessment, and the severest limitation of the active role of state and judge”.Footnote 27 But, since Donoghue v Stevenson, a very different approach has been taken to physical injury claims. Here it remains the case, conversely, that “the law of tort is the general law, out of which the parties can, if they wish, contract”.Footnote 28
The primacy of contract in the public sphere today, following the “outsourcing” or “contracting-out” of service provision, occasioned the claimant's legal difficulties in Woodland. Before that great policy shift of the 1980s (which remains politically controversial),Footnote 29 the fateful swimming lesson would have taken place in a pool staffed by council-employed lifeguards for whose negligence the council would have been vicariously liable.Footnote 30 The Supreme Court used that historical point to support liability for contractors; outsourcing should not worsen the legal position of injured members of the public (compared to the era when services were provided directly by council employees).Footnote 31 This, too, of course, is an ideological position.Footnote 32 Previously, the House of Lords accepted that outsourced care-home provision by a private company meant that the Human Rights Act 1998 did not apply (whereas the Act would, uncontroversially, have applied to a council-operated home). Lord Neuberger noted that part of the rationale for outsourcing “may be to avoid some of the legal constraints and disadvantages which apply to local authorities but not to private operators”; it was not for the court to rule on the validity of that policy, “unattractive though it may be to some people”.Footnote 33 Such abstentionism is no doubt a policy choice also. But at least Lord Neuberger acknowledged the sensitive dilemma. In Woodland, the Supreme Court simply assumed that outsourcing should not worsen the claimant's position. That position is not indefensible, of course. It would be a stretch of the imagination to attribute to Parliament a positive intention of making injured public service users worse off by contracting-out. On the other hand, the economic structure of outsourcing, especially the insurance arrangements adopted, arguably do require authorities to be insulated from their contractors' negligence.Footnote 34 But these arguments were simply not considered by the Supreme Court.Footnote 35
Contrary to the Supreme Court's expansionary approach, it is widely accepted that, outside directly inflicted physical injury cases, certain obligations are owed only when paid for – that is, in contract but not in tort. Sometimes this is implicit, sometimes openly acknowledged,Footnote 36 and sometimes even the justification for the absence of liability in tort.
Emergency services generally owe no common law duty of care to reply to call-outs.Footnote 37 The absence of liability for omissions applies even when the police are made aware of credible threats of severe personal injury, but fail to act.Footnote 38 Yet nobody doubts that a contractual claim would lie in parallel circumstances. When a plutocrat employs a bodyguard, there can be no doubt that the guard's contractual duties include responding to credible threats of violence against his employer. Or the resident of an exclusive gated community would be able to sue the firm employed to provide security services for negligently failing to apprehend burglars in her property; a claim denied to οἱ πολλοί suing the police in tort.Footnote 39 It would be ridiculous to posit contractual immunity here for failing to provide the service paid for, purely because public authorities are not liable in tort to the public at large for similar failings.Footnote 40 Conversely, while the absence of emergency service liability has certainly been criticised,Footnote 41 the objection is not that those who pay for similar services privately would have an action in contract and that the public (suing in tort) should not be worse off. The police themselves might be employed to provide “special services” for payment,Footnote 42 and thus (presumably) owe more extensive duties in contract than to the public at large. Tort sets its baseline independently from potentially wider rights in contract (for which people can, if they will, pay).
Courts have regularly dismissed tort claims while expressly acknowledging that a similar claim in contract might have succeeded. An example is “loss of a chance”, which has not been permitted to form the basis of claim in negligence.Footnote 43 In one leading case, Lord Scott suggested that claimants relying instead on contracts of employment might have been able to recover such losses.Footnote 44 Assuming this suggestion well founded,Footnote 45 the different result would follow from another doctrinal axiom: that while damage is the gist of the action in negligence (and so its existence must be proved on the balance of probabilities), a breach of contract is actionable per se (and consequential loss is quantified on a “chance” basis). This explains other divergences, including that over “preventive damages”.Footnote 46
Not all judges have approved such differential outcomes. In Hotson, Donaldson M.R. advocated loss-of-chance claims in tort, observing that if they were denied, National Health Service patients would be worse off than private patients relying on contracts in otherwise “identical circumstances”. The Master of the Rolls was “quite unable to detect any rational basis for [such] a state of the law”.Footnote 47 But the House of Lords was, and has remained, unmoved. That paying patients can recover lost-chance damages has not entailed recognition of that head of loss in negligence.Footnote 48
McFarlane v Tayside Health Board settled the “wrongful birth” debate: the pursuers could not recover the cost of bringing up a child conceived after an allegedly negligent vasectomy. The McFarlanes' action, against an NHS authority, was necessarily delictual.Footnote 49 But it was accepted that the position of a private patient suing in contract could well be different. Lord Slynn of Hadley stated that “If a client wants to be able to recover such costs he or she must do so by an appropriate contract”.Footnote 50 This accepts (as it must) that people can, if they wish (and can find a willing doctor), bargain for protection against the costs of childcare should the operation fail – freedom of contract. But that can scarcely require the same rights of action in tort to those who have not contracted for it. On the contrary, as Lord Slynn implies, tort protects certain basic rights (especially personal rather than economic interests) that people can pay to enhance by contracting for higher protection, if they are able.
It is hard to see how this could be otherwise. The law allows people wide freedom to contract for services, on whatever terms they choose, including the rights of action should things go wrong. Tort law would collapse if its internal structure were replaced by speculation about the liabilities that parties might have assumed by contract. For this reason, pace Lord Sumption, “the mere absence of consideration” does, quite properly, “lead to an entirely different result”.Footnote 51 It is true that this may also lead to indirect social discrimination.Footnote 52 Those employing private bodyguards, or paying for private education, are necessarily persons of means. Those reliant on equivalent public services (the police, state schooling) may not be wealthy. To the extent that such contracts confer broader rights of action, the rich will be better protected against negligent harm. But you get what you pay for. The objection (if this is unfair) is not that the private consumer is protected too well, but that tort protects the public service recipient inadequately.
The Supreme Court's express disapproval of distinctions (in the present context) between state and private schooling or healthcare has undeniable egalitarian appeal. Such sentiments may or may not show the judiciary in tune with general social attitudes – the position is by no means uncontroversial.Footnote 53 But egalitarianism can hardly efface all doctrinal differences between contract and tort. So long as tort provides a certain level of protection to everyone (irrespective of payment) according to its own established structure and doctrine, and so long as people are entitled to use their wealth to contract for higher levels of protection, such distinctions are unavoidable. Liability for the fault of an independent contractor is one well-settled distinction. It is not clear why courts should rush to blur it when, in other areas (like loss of a chance), recipients of public services have been left worse off than private clients suing in contract. If anything should be criticised, it is not the contract-tort distinction, but the absence of liability for independent contractors in tort per se.
IV. Duties to Ensure that Care is Taken (and the “Non-Delegable Duty”)
A contractual “duty of care” is usually interpreted as one to see that care is taken (by whoever actually provides the relevant service). In tort, by contrast, a duty of care is normally just that – a duty that the defendant herself take reasonable care. Exceptionally, however, a more stringent tortious duty is imposed, that the defendant ensure that care is taken (by whoever is actually carrying out the relevant activity). This is known, very misleadingly, as a “non-delegable duty”. No duty of care can be delegated, but its performance may well be (whether to employees, independent contractors, or otherwise). Sometimes the defendant would be negligent not to “delegate” an activity to a more suitable third party (for example where expertise is needed).Footnote 54 It would be absurd to create a doctrine to prevent such delegation. But the “non-delegable duty”, despite its name, does no such thing. Engagement of independent contractors (and “delegation” of the relevant activity to them) remains perfectly permissible; however, the defendant must exceptionally ensure that they take reasonable care (or rather, since it is impossible to ensure that contractors are never careless, he must answer for any harm negligently caused).
It would be better to avoid the misnomer altogether.Footnote 55 But the terminology is so well entrenched that it may be less confusing to continue calling “non-delegable duty” what is more accurately a duty to ensure that care is taken. The reformulation is not just playing with words. Taking the ordinary duty to be careful first, it is always permissible (and sometimes – as seen – even obligatory) to engage suitable persons to carry out an activity on one's behalf. The careful defendant must take reasonable steps to ensure that the persons engaged really are “suitable”, and may thereafter need to instruct, train, and supervise them, depending on the circumstances. But the most reputable, best instructed, and closely supervised worker or firm may still make mistakes. Yet it is quite possible that one who employs a negligent worker has not been negligent himself. When owing the standard duty of care, the defendant employer will not be liable in that case.
To that statement, two qualifications must be made: vicarious liability and the “non-delegable duty”. The former is so important, and normal, that the qualification virtually swallows the rule. A defendant is vicariously liable for torts committed by his employees within the course of their employment. There are thus three ways to get judgment against the employer when a master–servant relationship exists. First, one can show that the servant was a tortfeasor and the tort in the course of employment. Secondly, one can show “direct” negligence on the part of the employer, such as a failure to employ suitable staff or to train them properly. Or thirdly (exceptionally), one can show a “non-delegable duty”, namely to ensure that care was taken by the employee. As Weir comments, all these situations are “inevitably triangular” but the “routes round the triangle really must be kept separate”.Footnote 56 Most claimants will take the first route, vicarious liability, for obvious reasons: the claimant does not have to prove the employer's fault (i.e. “direct” negligence)Footnote 57 or the existence of an exceptional “non-delegable duty”. But sometimes the simpler vicarious liability route is barred to the claimant. A tort might occur outside the course of employment. While that doctrine has been considerably expanded,Footnote 58 cases will still arise where the servant-tortfeasor is on a “frolic of his own”.
The extension of the course of employment, and other expansionary currents within vicarious liability, will divert ever more claims along this route. The paucity of claims resorting to “direct” negligence explains counsel's remarkable “round assertion” in 1986 that “no health authority ever had been, or in principle ever could be, under any such direct liability”, with sufficient plausibility to raise doubts for Mustill L.J.Footnote 59 It is now clear that a health authority may indeed be directly liable for failing to provide adequate treatment.Footnote 60 Direct institutional duties of care are often pleaded in cases where vicarious liability seems dubious.Footnote 61 Its success naturally requires proof that the employer was at fault.Footnote 62
One case in which vicarious liability remains axiomatically unavailable, despite its recent expansion, is when the person employed to do the job was an independent contractor. To affix liability on the negligent contractor's employer (more accurately, the contractor's customer),Footnote 63 the claimant must show breach by the customer/employer of his own duty to the claimant. If that duty is the ordinary duty to be careful, the claim will fail unless the customer/employer was at fault in engaging the contractor.Footnote 64 Of course, many claims will founder on this requirement. Exceptionally, however, the claimant has a much more advantageous route to the customer/employer – the “non-delegable duty”. Because this is (recall) a duty to ensure that care is taken, the customer/employer is in breach of it (irrespective of fault on his part) whenever the contractor is negligent. It is a duty to ensure a certain result, not merely to take care: a form of strict liability. This constitutes the “non-delegable duty's” exceptional status: “… it departs from the basic principles of liability in negligence by substituting for the duty to take reasonable care a more stringent duty, a duty to ensure that reasonable care is taken.”Footnote 65
Given this strict liability for the fault of another, the “non-delegable duty” bears more than a passing resemblance to vicarious liability. It has accordingly been dismissed as a “logical fraud”Footnote 66 – nothing more than a sleight of hand to produce what is supposed to be impossible, namely vicarious liability for the torts of independent contractors. Now, from a strictly doctrinal point of view, this charge is baseless. It stands to reason that the “non-delegable duty” must operate differently from vicarious liability, or it could not be applicable to independent contractors (to be less mealy-mouthed, it could not outflank the prohibition on vicarious liability unless it were something other than vicarious liability). They are “two routes round the triangle” – in Baroness Hale's words, “conceptually quite different”.Footnote 67 The doctrinal apparatus certainly differs – the “course of employment” is not as such relevant in cases of independent contractors, although a not dissimilar exception for “casual or collateral negligence” has been recognised.Footnote 68 Yet “non-delegable duties” are pled by tort claimants precisely because, and only because, there is no vicarious liability for independent contractors and the defendant may not have been careless personally. Despite the conceptual differences, the outcome is usually identical to vicarious liability.
This explains the appeal of “non-delegable duties” to claimants. Increasingly, judges have candidly admitted that “non-delegable duties” are recognised precisely to fill some perceived gap in vicarious liability. One such gap was the doctrine of “common employment”: an exception to vicarious liability when one servant was injured by another of the same master.Footnote 69 Judicial attitudes towards workplace injuries claims had softened by the end of the nineteenth century, as shown by the narrowed defence of volenti non fit injuria.Footnote 70 Yet it was beyond the judges to remove the common employment defence.Footnote 71 Instead, a “non-delegable duty” was created by the House of Lords in Wilsons & Clyde Coal Co v English:Footnote 72 when one worker carelessly injured a fellow worker, the employer was put in breach of its own duty to ensure that care was taken (i.e. to provide a safe system of work). Yet, despite being the “leading example” of the “non-delegable duty” approach, “Lord Wright's approach [in Wilsons] is vulnerable to the criticism that he advances no reason or policy consideration for fixing the employer with the higher duty to see that care is taken instead of the duty that he himself take reasonable care”.Footnote 73 Courts now accept what was once seen as a dangerously realist answer: the policy in Wilsons was to fill the gap in vicarious liability created by common employment.Footnote 74
Similarly, in a period when there were real doubts over whether hospital surgeons could be classified as employees (given that close control was the traditional hallmark of “servant” status), Lord Greene M.R. and Denning L.J. suggested that hospitals owed a “non-delegable duty” to ensure that all staff, irrespective of employment status, took reasonable care.Footnote 75 As Baroness Hale stated in Woodland, this invocation of the “non-delegable duty”, too, was “to get round what was then perceived to be another problem with the law of vicarious liability”.Footnote 76 Her Ladyship approved the circumvention, suggesting it as a “ready answer” to another lacuna that she identified in the context of modern hospitals (and schools) – injuries caused by the carelessness of an agency nurse or supply teacher.Footnote 77
Such judicial frankness is both welcome and rare. But it does raise further questions. What are the criteria for recognising an exceptionally stringent tortious duty to ensure that care is taken, departing as it does from the basic obligation in negligence to take reasonable care? If the sole criterion is to plug gaps in vicarious liability, this simply begs the question. Stating that there is a “gap” to be filled assumes that vicarious liability is (in the relevant respect) too narrow, but that needs to be demonstrated. And, if vicarious liability is too narrow, it does little credit to leave that doctrine unreformed while producing a simulacrum of outcome via the “non-delegable duty”. Should vicarious liability be flawed it demands reform, not a conceptual tap-dance to avoid the issue. Beatson L.J. has recently observed that, although for critics of vicarious liability “the concept of a non-delegable duty may appear to be a more attractive, direct and principled solution”, in fact (in Paula Gilliker's words) resort to it “derives from frustration at the limits of vicarious liability rather than any considered conceptual development”.Footnote 78 His Lordship therefore proceeded to address the boundaries of vicarious liability, as raised by the case. Such direct engagement is most welcome. Other recent cases have extended vicarious liability from its paradigm of the master–servant relationship.Footnote 79 The extension has not yet reached contractors. If and when that nettle is grasped, what independent reason for the retention of “non-delegable duties” in tort could be cited?
The strong suspicion remains that tort law exceptionally imposes strict liability to ensure that care is taken to reach functionally identical results to vicarious liability in situations where that doctrine is held inapplicable – admittedly, by conceptually distinct means. But which route we take round the triangle has little importance beyond preserving the doctrinal decencies (or less charitably, allowing questions about vicarious liability to remain unasked). In contract law, there is little debate about which route to take. Liability for others' negligence poses no special difficulties when promisors are strictly liable for non-performance.
V. Contractual Liability for the Fault of Others
The characteristic strictness of liability for breach of contract is not always sufficiently appreciated.Footnote 80 Strikingly, even duties that appear at first sight to be duties “of care” are interpreted as duties to ensure that care is taken – a strict duty to achieve a particular result, not merely take reasonable steps to achieve it.
Just as “why” a promisor failed to perform is generally “immaterial”Footnote 81 so is the question of “who” was responsible for the failure. Lord Diplock explained in Photo Production v Securicor that promisors frequently, and often of necessity, engage others to perform what they have undertaken to do:
My Lords, it is characteristic of commercial contracts, nearly all of which today are entered into not by natural legal persons, but by fictitious ones, i.e. companies, that the parties promise to one another that some thing will be done; for instance, that property and possession of goods will be transferred, that goods will be carried by ship from one port to another, that a building will be constructed in accordance with agreed plans, that services of a particular kind will be provided. … Where what is promised will be done involves the doing of a physical act, performance of the promise necessitates procuring a natural person to do it; but the legal relationship between the promisor and the natural person by whom the act is done, whether it is that of master and servant, or principal and agent, or of parties to an independent subcontract, is generally irrelevant. If that person fails to do it in the manner in which the promisor has promised to procure it to be done, as, for instance, with reasonable skill and care, the promisor has failed to fulfil his own primary obligation.Footnote 82
Cockburn C.J. similarly noted that promisees are usually “indifferent … whether [performance] is done by the immediate party to the contract, or by someone on his behalf”.Footnote 83 The promisee expects a service of the stipulated quality to be provided – not that the promisor personally performs it to that quality, or indeed personally does anything at all.
Here is the answer to Weir's question: “Why do textbooks on Contract not have a chapter on vicarious liability?”Footnote 84 A company selling goods, CIF Rotterdam, is not promising that it will deliver them there itself, let alone that it will personally take reasonable care to do it. Nor does the buyer expect these things. The promise is construed in absolute terms: the seller will ensure that the goods are delivered on the specified date and, if they are not, he will in breach of his own contractual undertaking, irrespective of whether he could have done otherwise. Whether the default is attributable to the promisor personally (impossible when the promisor is not a natural person), or to his own employees, or to an independent contractor is immaterial. Strict liability makes such questions of fault (and, a fortiori, whose fault) irrelevant.
Although not quite so obviously, contractual duties that appear to be framed in less-than-absolute terms are equally stringent. A duty to supply goods of satisfactory quality is not a duty to supply perfect goods guaranteed against any risk of failure. The duty in a charter party to supply a seaworthy ship does not require an unsinkable vessel. Nevertheless, there is an absolute duty to achieve the relevant (qualified) standard: it is no defence for a seller to prove that he took all possible care to deliver satisfactory goods (if those delivered did not, in fact, reach that standard), or for the ship-owner to plead that he did everything possible to make the ship seaworthy (if, in fact, it was not).
Crucially for present purposes, even contractual duties to render services of a good, professional standard are construed as a duty to ensure that care is taken.Footnote 85 For example, in construction contracts, the builder's usual obligation is to build in a “workmanlike manner”.Footnote 86 But this imports a guarantee that the work is done in a “workmanlike” way, whoever actually carries it out. Builders commonly engage various subcontractors (in addition to their own workforce); even the largest firms contract out specialist tasks like installing lifts. Should any of the subcontractors (or their sub-subcontractors, etc.) fail to do the work in a “workmanlike manner”, the main building contractor will be put in breach of its own duty to see that the project is satisfactorily carried out and completed.Footnote 87 It is immaterial that a reputable subcontractor had been selected, instructed, and monitored. A duty to guarantee that care is taken by whoever does the work, although exceptional in tort, is a standard feature of construction contracts.
Generations of common lawyers have reasoned that, when someone pays for goods of a particular quality, or for a service of a certain standard, an absolute obligation presumptively arises to provide it – not merely an obligation to make reasonable efforts to provide it. The customer is purchasing the stipulated goods or services, and it is a matter of complete indifference to him how the provider chooses to render them. (For the reasons given by Lord Diplock, it is (to put it no higher) readily foreseeable that the provider will rely on various employees, agents, and contractors to do so.) Strict duties therefore meet commercial expectations.
Strong evidence for that assertion is the widespread acceptance of the common law position in industry-adopted standards (which could, of course, replace the default strict liability with fault-based standards if these were commercially preferable).Footnote 88 For example, major construction projects are frequently governed by Joint Contracts Tribunal (JCT) standard forms, drawn up by representatives of all the industry's interest groups. The JCT forms make no attempt to displace the builder's strict duty to ensure that the project is completed in a “workmanlike manner” by a personal obligation to take reasonable care that could be discharged by employing competent subcontractors. Understandably so. Such a limited duty would be much less valuable to the employer. He would pay much less for it, if he would accept it at all – which he probably would not.
Chains of contracts in the building industry (from employer, to main contractor, to subcontractor, etc.) remain governed by privity of contract. Even since the common law doctrine was relaxed by statute, nearly all JCT forms have been careful to exclude the possible operation of the Contracts (Rights of Third Parties) Act 1999. Each party answers in law only to his immediate employer and not to other parties farther up the chain (even though they too will foreseeably suffer loss from his shoddy work). Such an arrangement assumes and necessitates the strict liability discussed above. Imagine that a subcontractor, C, does unsatisfactory work despite being carefully engaged and supervised by the main contractor, B. Given privity of contract, the building owner (i.e. B's employer, A) will not be able to sue C in contract for the substandard work – and, after a brief period of confusion, this remains the position in tort also.Footnote 89 Were (blameless) B not liable to A for C's substandard work either, then A would have no remedy against anyone – a commercial absurdity. (Hence, no doubt, why leading works on construction law do not expressly discuss B's contractual liability in this common situation: it truly goes without saying.) But the result is not felt unduly harsh on B, who can pass liability on to the “ultimate culprit” using the “well known chain of third party procedures”.Footnote 90
This approach is not of course limited to building contracts. A rare case in which the principles were openly considered is Wan v Kwan Kin Travel Services.Footnote 91 The plaintiff was drowned owing to the negligence of a transportation company in China during a holiday booked with the first defendant, a Hong Kong-based travel agent. The issue was whether the travel agent “undertook no more than that [to] arrange for services to be provided by others” or undertook to provide those services itself. The distinction appears slender. However, in the first case, the duty can be discharged by showing that reasonable care and skill were taken in selecting those other persons, whereas, in the second case:
The fact that the supplier of services may under the contract arrange for some or all of them to be performed by others does not absolve the supplier from his contractual obligation. He may be liable if the service is performed without the exercise of due care and skill on the part of the subcontractor … . The obligation undertaken is thus, if the person undertaking to supply the services performs them himself, that he will do so with reasonable skill and care, and that if, where the contract permits him to do so, he arranges for others to supply the services, that they will be supplied with reasonable skill and care.Footnote 92
The Privy Council held that the travel agent through its contract “undertook to provide and not merely to arrange all the services” and was therefore liable for the negligence of its Chinese subcontractor. Their Lordships disagreed with the Hong Kong Court of Appeal's view that it was “an intolerable burden … to be held liable for the negligence of a transport operator in another country”.Footnote 93 Lord Slynn observed that the travel agent could protect itself by bargaining for contractual protection from those who were to perform the services (the “chain of contracts” reasoning described above) or by including a suitable exemption clause in contracts with its customers.Footnote 94
To sum up, it is standard practice to construe contractual duties “of care” as an obligation to ensure that care is taken when the relevant service is rendered. (Of course, when the obligation is personal to the promisee – such as a celebrated singer engaged to sing at a concert – it amounts to a personal duty of care, but such situations are uncommon in commercial law for the reasons given by Lord Diplock.Footnote 95) The Supreme Court in Woodland was therefore right to assume that a client suing a private school or hospital in contract would succeed where harm was caused by a negligent contractor (e.g. agency nurse or supply teacher).Footnote 96 There is strong reason to believe that the strictness of this approach meets commercial expectations. Moreover, strict liability for subcontractors accords with the default strictness of liability across the law of contract. There is no need to talk about a special category of “non-delegable duty” (nor indeed, as Weir observes, “vicarious liability”) in a general system of strict liability. The promisor is put in breach of his own (absolute) duty to render the promised services by the actual performer's failure. Contractual obligation is concerned with what has to be done – how it is done (and by whom it is done) is usually immaterial.
It might be thought immoral to hold people liable for failing to achieve that which they could not reasonably do – such as ensuring that a remote independent company take care of your customers, in Wan. Moral concerns have apparently encouraged retention of a fault standard in German contract law.Footnote 97 If so, the common law is amoral with insouciance. A contractual promise is treated as a guarantee of performance or, at least, its monetary equivalent. The doctrine of frustration is accordingly narrow. The fact that it is impossible to deliver goods for reasons entirely beyond the seller's control does not excuse him.Footnote 98 No more does the impossibility of control by the travel agent in Wan. Contract lawyers devote very little attention to the questions of fault “with which tort lawyers are so familiar”.Footnote 99 The two systems have entirely different assumptions about moral responsibility and fault.
VI. “Voluntary Assumption of Responsibility” in Tort
The previous section shows that duties to ensure that care is taken are standard in the law of contract, consistently with strict contractual liability and satisfying commercial expectations. By contrast, fault plays a dominant role in tort. Even fully accepting that significant pockets of strict liability remain and “the common law's approach to fault is explicably more diverse than is sometimes realised”,Footnote 100 fault is frequently necessary. By definition, liability in the tort of negligence requires it. One can lament the “one-size-fits-all approach to fault”Footnote 101 and decry negligence's “staggering march”,Footnote 102 but a fortiori “non-delegable duty of care” remains a contradiction in terms. It is not a duty to be careful at all, but one to ensure a particular result (i.e. that the activity in question is carefully carried out). If tort liability generally requires fault, then a good reason is needed to depart from that standard by imposing a strict duty to ensure that care is taken.
Even Robert Stevens, who identifies the “swollen ‘tort’ of negligence” (rather than the “non-delegable duty”) as “the cuckoo in the nest” of tort law,Footnote 103 accepts that strict liability's limits necessitate limits on “non-delegable duties”. It has been impossible to identify a general principle of strict liability for dangerous things since Read v J Lyons & Co.Footnote 104 It accordingly became anomalous to preserve “non-delegable duties” for so-called ultra-hazardous activities.Footnote 105 Stevens admits the inconsistency: “It seems insupportable that a [careful] defendant will be held liable for the extra-hazardous activity of an independent contractor, when it would not be so liable if it carefully carried out the same activity itself.”Footnote 106 But does this reasoning not apply to any area in which liability is usually based on fault (which is much of the law of torts)? Stevens rightly draws attention to strict liability under various statutes.Footnote 107 But these are no more than further isolated instances of the “exceptional and heterogeneous” situations in which “a person may be liable although his own organisation has operated flawlessly”.Footnote 108 Parliament might theoretically lay down general strict liabilities (e.g. for hazardous activities). But in this area, as so often, the legislature has seemed “afraid to rise to the dignity of a general proposition”.Footnote 109 The extant strict(er) statutory duties are piecemeal. No general strict duty (even less “non-delegable duty”) can be synthesised from them. By contrast with the position in contract law, there is no general principle of strict liability, nor therefore strict liability for independent contractors, in tort.
It follows that there can be no general parallel between the undoubted contractual liability for an independent contractor's default and liability in tort. However, in Woodland, Lord Sumption's analogy was drawn not in the archetypical tort situation between complete strangers, but given a pre-existing relationship between the parties. Moreover, his Lordship considered cases where the defendant “assumes responsibility” to the claimant for the carefulness of his contractors. The analogy between contract and tort here seems strong.Footnote 110 Commentators have argued persuasively that “assumption of responsibility” is the central principled determinant of the “non-delegable duty”.Footnote 111 The Supreme Court has now endorsed this explanation. It seems reassuring to have a unified theory in place of the ad hoc precedents that so “perplexed” Glanville Williams and had become little clearer half a century later.Footnote 112 But, on closer examination, the explanation is much less convincing. Usually, liability has not been “assumed”, but imposed by the courts. In its original nursery of pure economic loss, that criticism has been widely accepted, so the elevation of “assumption of responsibility” into the touchstone for “non-delegable duties” is puzzling. For, if liability depends more on judicial imposition than party intention, the analysis is simply pushed back one stage: when should such duties be imposed? Bluntly, “assumption of responsibility” provides no test at all, and no answers – it simply poses the same questions in a disguised form.
“Assumption of responsibility” has enjoyed mercurial favour from those set on extending tort liability in a contractual direction. Admittedly, when taken at face value, its central case presents a seductive argument for liability. If a defendant expressly guarantees the carefulness of his contractors (or expressly undertakes to use reasonable care to protect the claimant's financial or other interests), there is a case for holding the defendant liable for not doing so even in the absence of payment (i.e. of contract).Footnote 113 If the defendant's undertaking truly gives rise to a “relationship equivalent to contract” (without actually constituting one),Footnote 114 that seems a good reason to allow recovery in negligence for kinds of loss, or in kinds of situations, that contract recognises (but tort normally does not).Footnote 115 Such an undertaking may generate a positive duty to improve the claimant's position (whereas ordinarily “pure omissions” do not lead to liability in tort). An express undertaking to prevent self-harm generated an extraordinary duty of care of this kind in Calvert v William Hill.Footnote 116 As Stevens says, where a duty is voluntarily assumed, “the law is, inevitably, less concerned with preserving [the defendant's] interest in liberty of action”.Footnote 117 Such an assumption may override other rules that would ordinarily preclude liability, including the policy of protecting public authorities from claims that might engender a “defensive” approach.Footnote 118
The great difficulty is how rarely the persuasive central case arises in practice.Footnote 119 Not surprisingly, for how many people would willingly and expressly undertake wider legal liabilities without payment for doing so, or without compulsion?Footnote 120 The conjecture is born out by the case law on pure economic loss. In very few cases involving liability for “assuming responsibility” did the defendant expressly undertake a legally enforceable obligation (one sounding in liability in the event of careless performance). In the cognate area of promissory estoppel, some exhibit a sceptical attitude to such “undertakings” – Longmore L.J. has demanded clear evidence of an alleged promise to forgo rights without any obvious reciprocal benefit.Footnote 121
By contrast, in cases where “assumption of responsibility” has been invoked to hold defendants liable for (e.g.) pure economic loss in tort, judges have seemed enthusiastic to saddle defendants with exceptional tort liability when they could have – but did not – contractually promise to protect the relevant interests.Footnote 122 Increasingly, it has been accepted that “notional” or “objective” “assumption of responsibility” reflects judicial imposition rather than the intentions of the actual defendant,Footnote 123 in which case it depends on questions of “fairness and policy” and is not “a simple question of fact”.Footnote 124 Thus “assumption of responsibility” usually operates as a mere cipher. It is expressive of the conclusion reached, not an independent reason for it.
Lord Sumption referred in passing to “assumption of responsibility's” usual relevance as a “tool” for controlling economic loss liability.Footnote 125 But no mention was made of the many difficulties with it, and criticisms of it, in that context. This is unfortunate. Even one of the theory's prominent supporters, John Murphy, accepts that the language is “apt to mislead … insofar as it suggests an element of voluntariness on the part of the defendant which is clearly absent in most non-delegable duty cases … The truth is that ‘assumed responsibilities' in non-delegable duty cases are more commonly imputed by the courts than voluntarily undertaken by defendants”.Footnote 126
The oxymoronic enterprise of “calling an imposition an assumption” has been heavily criticised elsewhere.Footnote 127 The real question is when such liability should be imposed. Search for a fictitious promise to undertake additional liability is very unlikely to provide the answer.
The landmark decisions expanding hospitals' direct liability over the last century generally identified relevant “undertakings” by the hospital. But no promissory conduct or statements by doctors or hospital managers have been identified. In Hillyer v St Bartholomew's Hospital (1909), “The only duty undertaken by the defendants is to use due care and skill in selecting their medical staff”.Footnote 128 Disapproving this in Gold v Essex County Council, Lord Greene M.R. considered the obligations assumed by the hospital (whether contractual or otherwise).Footnote 129 In Cassidy v Ministry of Health, Denning L.J. founded his decision (a cornerstone of hospitals' “non-delegable duty”) on the “acceptance” of a patient for treatment. By accepting him, the hospital had undertaken to use reasonable care and skill.Footnote 130 It is now well established that such acceptance generates a positive duty to treat (so that hospitals do not benefit from the “omissions principle”).Footnote 131 Why this does not apply to (other) emergency services when they answer a 999 call is not wholly clear.Footnote 132
But whether an NHS hospital could lawfully refuse to treat a patient is doubtful – in which case the voluntariness of their acceptance seems fictitious.Footnote 133 Perhaps health authorities choose to open a hospital in a particular place, and individual doctors choose to practise medicine (or work at a given hospital or in a certain medical field). By this time, however, the notion of “voluntary assumption” has become greatly attenuated, compatibly with Atiyah's very wide, and weak, version. Having considered implied terms in contracts of sale, Atiyah argued that the (clearly tortious) obligations on drivers were no less “voluntary”. A driver “is voluntarily on the road, voluntarily driving his car, and may be said to submit himself to the requirements of the law with as much or as little truth as the seller of goods”.Footnote 134 Few would attempt to base road users' obligations to take care on assumption of responsibility. Such duties are acknowledged to be imposed by law. That is equally true of medical negligence.
Its expansion over the century since Hillyer's case has nothing to do with hospital authorities' moves to assume more extensive legally enforceable duties. Rather, as one of the leading Canadian cases recognises, the tortious “relationship between hospitals and the public in contemporary society” has altered to reflect “profound changes in social structures and public attitudes relating to medical services and the concomitant changes in the function of hospitals in providing them”.Footnote 135 Kirby P. advocated the expansion of “non-delegable duties” to accommodate “the intensely technological nature of modern hospitals” – especially the use of “visiting experts” (who are not hospital employees) to operate equipment.Footnote 136 The emphasis throughout has been on adapting liability to meet public expectations. It has surely been imposed by law, not voluntarily assumed by hospitals.
Woodland is another dubious example of “voluntarily assumed” responsibility.Footnote 137 Previously, in Customs v Barclays Bank, a claim failed because the defendant bank's compulsion (by court order) to freeze its customer's account was inimical to the argument that it had voluntarily assumed responsibility to the claimant beneficiary of the freezing order (i.e. its customer's creditor).Footnote 138 That a public authority was under a statutory duty to perform a task has been seen as precluding a “voluntary assumption of responsibility” for its performance.Footnote 139 Essex County Council was under similar legal compulsion. The statutory National Curriculum for England requires that “All schools must provide swimming instruction either in Key Stage 1 or Key Stage 2”. State schools like Whitmore Junior School therefore have no choice but to provide swimming lessons. This aspect of Woodland fits uneasily with the whole notion of a “voluntary” assumption of responsibility. Essex runs schools because it has a public duty to do so; it had no choice whether to school Miss Woodland and no choice under the National Curriculum whether to teach her to swim. (Equally, Basildon Council had no choice but to consider private operators for its leisure services; local authorities can operate facilities themselves only if this represents “best value”.Footnote 140)
Tomlinson L.J. feared that recognising liability in Woodland might “chill” schools against providing wider educational experiences – since they have no control over outside premises and staff but would be accountable for their negligence.Footnote 141 Lord Sumption stated that schools need not answer for “those to whom no control over the child has been delegated, such as bus drivers or the theatres, zoos or museums to which children may be taken by school staff in school hours”.Footnote 142 This might help assuage concerns that potential legal liability deters the provision of adventurous youth activities.Footnote 143 But we may safely predict that Lord Sumption's obiter comments will be tested in future litigation.Footnote 144 Ironically, there would be a much stronger argument that a school had voluntarily assumed responsibility for pupils' safety on a theatre visit (where Lord Sumption was at pains to rule out liability) which was organised on the school's initiative rather than obligatory under the National Curriculum. It is a relief that swimming lessons (at least) cannot be withdrawn because of schools' fears about liability after Woodland. But the statutory duty precluding that undesirable outcome makes “voluntary assumption of responsibility” untenable.
It may be socially desirable to hold state schools strictly liable for the negligence of anybody carrying out educational functions on their behalf. But inventing “assumptions of responsibility”, or drawing parallels with contract that are unsustainable for fault-based tort liability, are not convincing ways to justify it.
VII. Tort and the Baseline of Safety: Vicarious Liability for Independent Contractors?
Tort law is not a fault-based monoculture (albeit fault is generally seen as a good prima facie reason for liability). There are islands of strict liability (albeit seen as exceptional and requiring justification). Indeed, the continent of negligence harbours within it a vast empire of strict liability for the torts of others (vicarious liability). The true justification for vicarious liability is perennially controversial. But its practical importance cannot be in doubt. While tort remains theoretically based on individual responsibility, in practice a large proportion of tort liability is imposed on organisations (business corporations, public authorities) answering impersonally for their employees' torts. Despite its blatant inconsistency with notions of personal responsibility, vicarious liability attracts surprisingly few critics. Its “social convenience and rough justice” evidently exerts a wide appeal,Footnote 145 in part because vicarious liability mostly avoids holding organisations “personally” liable for their “own” torts. Although such direct liability might sound desirable in principle, it would necessitate rules to attribute the acts of natural persons to corporate abstractions, to decide whether an organisation was at fault “itself”. Of course, such theories are not beyond the wit of man, but historically they have been obscured by “anthropomorphic inquir[es]” and their “metaphysical shadows”,Footnote 146 and even the modern “contextual” approach is scarcely free of difficulty.Footnote 147 Vicarious liability performs an attribution function in a broad and simple way.Footnote 148 The employer answers for all torts committed by employees in the course of employment. The possibility of direct liability of the organisation “itself” remains but, as noted above, the very width of vicarious liability (the other route round the triangle) precludes that inquiry in most cases.
Business organisation today has placed this model under pressure. Vicarious liability is said, axiomatically, to apply to employees (only) and not to independent contractors. Once, such situations were less common and those that arose threatened to expand strict liability for individuals (the householder-client of a negligent plumber, etc.).Footnote 149 But, when businesses frequently do, and public authorities typically must, outsource their operations to independent contractors, a troubling gap opens up. The Supreme Court in Woodland evidently thought it unacceptable that authorities would escape liability after outsourcing services to negligent contractors (absenting negligence in the outsourcing process). It has been suggested above that equal unease would arise irrespective of parallel contractual liability (no similar services provided for payment); the contract issue is ultimately a red herring. It is time to face openly whether vicarious liability, which has recently experienced more than one “William Ellis moment” by expanding beyond strict employer–employee relationships,Footnote 150 could also extend to independent contractors.
Woodland, of course, provides the seed from which the revolution might grow. We have argued above that much of the Supreme Court's reasoning simply cannot be accepted. The analogy with contract is unconvincing and ultimately irrelevant: “voluntary assumption of responsibility” a transparent fiction. Yet the presence of unconvincing arguments does not necessarily mean the decision is wrong. As a matter of precedent, it is here to stay, in any event. How broad are the implications? Woodland could inaugurate a specific rule of vicarious liability for contractors for the benefit of vulnerable groups (school pupils, hospital patients, etc.). Protecting such persons has an especially appealing resonance as a general matter,Footnote 151 and patients' “special need of care” was cited by Mason J. as a reason for imposing exceptional “non-delegable duties” in his influential judgment in Kondis v State Transport Authority.Footnote 152 Potentially though, this is a far-reaching basis for a supposedly exceptional rule. Is not every stranger (i.e. everyone who lacks “alternative means of protection”)Footnote 153 vulnerable to the financial consequences of a negligent contractor's impecuniosity?Footnote 154 Even confining “vulnerability” to physical risks, this justifies the much-derided category of “ultra-hazardous activities” as readily as special weakness of claimants.Footnote 155 For, as Murphy says, vulnerability “comprises no more than the inverse of abnormal risk”.Footnote 156 Also, as discussed, Lord Sumption sought to preclude future extensions of liability to extramural activities beyond the direct physical control of school authorities.Footnote 157 Yet there is no serious suggestion that schoolchildren become any less vulnerable in such situations – indeed, with much “adventure activity”, the opposite must be true.
Another possibility, canvassed already,Footnote 158 is that Woodland is better seen as a special principle applicable to public authorities: these should not be able to contract out of the liabilities they would previously have borne (qua master of servant-tortfeasors) by outsourcing the provision of public services. This might seem politically appealing to some. But there is no apparent basis for such a “preservation of liability” in the legislation enabling (and requiring) outsourcing of service provision, nor (it seems) in general principles of administrative law.Footnote 159 Such arguments have not found judicial favour in the past, such as in A v MoD, which raised the very question whether the Ministry's (alleged) non-delegable duty to patients could be sloughed off by its outsourcing medical care to other providers, instead of running its own military hospitals (it could).Footnote 160 Similarly, Wright J. found nothing in the relevant legislation to displace the ordinary rule precluding liability for the torts of an independent contractor, when the Secretary of State had delegated functions to a privately run immigration detention centre.Footnote 161
In any event, outsourcing is hardly a phenomenon confined to public services. It originated in the private sector and was imported to the public realm in the hope of improving efficiency. The “problem” of an organisation's outsourcing functions to independent companies instead of providing them in-house is just as likely to confront accident victims in the private context. Again, therefore, the general question of vicarious liability for contractors is raised.
Space precludes an answer here. But the costs and benefits can be sketched. At a very simple level, victims would benefit from having a second, potentially solvent target (the client of the contractor-tortfeasor), whereas those clients would, obviously, lose out. But it is not simply a transfer between the groups (a zero-sum game). There is reason to think that extending vicarious liability to contractors would result in the widespread inefficiency of double insurance (two parties insuring against the same risk – a cost which benefits only the insurance industry). At present, one benefit of outsourcing a function is precisely that the risk of liability (for injuries created by the activity) is outsourced too. As Merkin and Steele report, it is normal for outsourcing contracts to oblige the contractor to carry public liability insurance against such risks – a clear recognition that the risk has been transferred.Footnote 162 Of course, the “outsourcer” does not need to insure against those same liabilities (given the classical common law rule). Should Woodland herald a general collapse of that rule however, it is plain that “outsourcers” would need to insure against those risks too – hence the inefficiency.Footnote 163 (In passing, we can note that the same “double insurance” cost is not imposed in practice by (ordinary) vicarious liability for employees: simply, the employee is typically not insured, and does not need to be insured, because actions for damages against employees personally (rather than the vicariously liable employer) are extremely rare – and those that are brought have been controversial enough to lead to calls for legislative reversal,Footnote 164 or spurred judges to extreme doctrinal innovation to protect the employee.Footnote 165 In short, the position (de facto if not de jure)Footnote 166 is that vicarious liability excludes the personal liability of employees.Footnote 167 But nobody suggests that contractors should not remain liable in a Woodland situation – hence the double insurance problem.)
It might seem Scrooge personified to suggest that Miss Woodland's damages claim against the authorities should have been struck out – even pointing out that her rights of action against the lifeguard, the lifeguard's employer (the contractor), and their common insurer remained unimpaired. But tort lawyers must beware another unsavoury literary archetype.Footnote 168 Lady Bountiful is typically thought patronising but, when the riches bestowed belong not to the judges but the litigating parties, they commit the further sin of deriving pleasure “from the consciousness of spending others' money better than they would themselves”.Footnote 169 At the very least, any reform in the law must consider who pays the price. Generalising vicarious liability for contractors would of course impose costs on their clients (“employers”) but also, less obviously, on society as a whole through the waste of double insurance. Given the prevalence of outsourcing, this would not only act as a drag on private enterprise, but also increase the price of delivering public services (in crude terms, more of the finite revenue from taxation will be spent on insurance premiums,Footnote 170 and so less on teachers, as a result of Woodland).
VIII. Conclusion
It may be helpful to summarise the argument:
(1) The law can, and does, recognise duties to ensure that care is taken by whoever is carrying on a particular activity (as opposed to a personal duty to take care oneself). As a duty to ensure a certain outcome, this is a (specific) form of strict liability.
(2) Such duties are normal in contract. This reflects the general expectation that even promises to provide a measured service (e.g. “good and workmanlike” carpentry) guarantee that services of that quality will be provided. Promisors do not usually undertake to provide the service themselves: it is widely appreciated in many (if not most) contracts that they cannot. A fortiori they do not merely promise to take care personally to provide services of the stipulated standard (e.g. by carefully selecting those who are actually to do the work). A promisee is usually indifferent about who performs; what matters is what is performed (i.e. services of the stipulated standard). These points are rarely explicitly discussed, but are widely assumed for the allocation of liability in multi-party arrangements. The presumption fits the near-absolute liability for breach across the law of contract.
(3) Duties to ensure that care is taken have exceptionally been recognised in tort under the misleading label “non-delegable duty” (which should ideally be discarded). But such duties are as anomalous within fault-grounded liability such as negligence as they are redundant in torts of strict liability.Footnote 171 Even accepting that negligence is not the only tort and that strict liability retains a sporadically important role,Footnote 172 a convincing reason is necessary to justify a strict duty to ensure that care is taken when, ordinarily, a defendant would not be liable in the absence of fault. Delegating performance to an apparently competent, carefully selected contractor ordinarily discharges a duty of care by performing it.
(4) It has been proposed that a voluntary assumption of responsibility (i.e. to ensure that care is taken) justifies such a duty. The theory has received wide support and attractively identifies a species of tort liability analogous to contract. However, if taken seriously, “assumption of responsibility” would justify liability in very few situations (i.e. only when, without payment, a defendant willingly assumed such a strict, legally enforceable obligation). In practice, the concept has been discredited by frequent invocation in cases where there was neither express nor implied assumptionFootnote 173 and/or nothing voluntary about it (including Woodland).
(5) The Supreme Court in Woodland strove to avoid leaving a state school pupil, suing in tort, in a worse position when injured by an independent contractor than a private school pupil would be, suing in contract. But such distinctions are inevitable. Contract and tort doctrines differ fundamentally (e.g. on accrual of the cause of action), leading to different outcomes (e.g. on “preventive” and “loss-of-chance” damages). The subject matter of this article is another prominent example. Even more obviously (indeed tautologously), promisees will be in a better position when they negotiate and pay for a higher degree of protection through their contracts. Fine distinctions arise when identical services are provided both gratuitously (e.g. by public authorities) and for reward (under contract). Drawing such distinctions may seem invidious but, from a purely doctrinal perspective, that is not a satisfactory reason for ignoring them.
(6) In sum, it has been shown why duties to ensure care is taken fit easily into contract but only with great difficulty into tort; that the different approaches derive from fundamental features of contractual and tortious liability, especially the role of fault (and not merely “technical differences”);Footnote 174 that the distinction cannot be ignored solely because it produces different (less generous) outcomes in tort cases compared with factually similar contract claims; that “assumption of responsibility” holds out some promise for principled bridging of the divide, but it has been more often abused than convincingly applied.
As the work of Atiyah and others has demonstrated, the position of the contract–tort borderline changes over time and stirs deep economic and political controversies. While coherence with the overall doctrinal structure of contract and tort is (it has been argued here) important, it cannot ultimately determine the economic/political questions that lie beneath the surface. The most influential contemporary counterblast to the expansion of tort has little traction upon the instant question. Giving commercial parties for free (i.e. through tort) obligations that they could have paid for by contracting has been heavily (and rightly) criticised.Footnote 175 But the corollary is that absence of contract should not exclude tort liability when the claimant was “vulnerable” (i.e. not well placed to protect herself through a contract).Footnote 176 If the contractual analogy in Woodland is in the end misleading, the absence of a contract still does not preclude wider liability in tort outside the commercial sphere.
Woodland, if correctly decided, should therefore be seen as establishing a level of protection that everyone is entitled to expect, irrespective of paymentFootnote 177 –namely that organisations should be vicariously liable for the negligence of their contractors. This is the logical outcome of “contract envy” of the superior protection of injured private pupils or patients. The intuitive discontent, properly understood, relates to tort's inadequacy in an absolute sense, not just in comparison with potential rights under contracts. (Such a comparison proves too much, since contracting consumers might always be better protected, yet courts have frequently affirmed limits on tort liability notwithstanding contract beneficiaries' greater rights.) Absenting a true voluntary assumption of responsibility, tort liability is imposed by law. Whether we discuss duties to ensure care is taken, “non-delegable duties”, or vicarious liability (for contractors) ultimately matters little. But the third option would avoid the anomalies of the former, discussed above. It would focus attention on what seems to be the real question latent in this area: should organisations now answer for their contractors as well as their employees, when outsourcing is becoming ubiquitous? Considering the justifications for vicarious liability, and for traditionally limiting it to employees, will be necessary to answer this question. By contrast, the absolute liability of a promisor when a service fails to meet the contractually defined standard provides little illumination for a law of torts which retains fault as its basic standard of personal responsibility.