Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-grxwn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-09T23:33:23.036Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bounded Ethicality and The Principle That “Ought” Implies “Can”

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 September 2015

Tae Wan Kim
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University
Rosemarie Monge
Affiliation:
University of St. Thomas
Alan Strudler
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract:

In this article we investigate a philosophical problem for normative business ethics theory suggested by a phenomenon that contemporary psychologists call “bounded ethicality,” which can be identified with the putative fact that well-intentioned people, constrained by psychological limitations, make ethical choices inconsistent with their own ethical beliefs and commitments. When one combines the idea that bounded ethicality is pervasive with the idea that a person morally ought to do something only if she can, it raises a doubt about the practical relevance of the moral principles that business ethics theory prescribes. We call this doubt the Radical Behavioral Challenge. It consists in the idea that people cannot generally conform to the normative ethical principles that business ethics theorists prescribe, and that these principles are therefore practically irrelevant. We answer the Radical Behavioral Challenge and explore normative implications of our answer.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Society for Business Ethics 2015 

INTRODUCTION

Recent social science research suggests that one’s capacity to act on her stated moral values is often significantly compromised by psychological limitations. Psychologists often refer to these limits as “bounded ethicality”—an umbrella term used to describe a diverse variety of psychological mechanisms that putatively lead people astray (Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011). Bounded ethicality, one might think, has a significant implication for moral decision-making, which we call the Radical Behavioral Challenge (RBC):

Bounded ethicality makes it psychologically impossible for people to make choices that reflect the moral principles they endorse and the moral principles articulated in normative business ethical theory, creating a gap between what normative theory prescribes and what people can in fact do.Footnote 1

Although RBC has not been expressly endorsed by psychologists or others, some psychologists make claims that can only be understood in its terms. For example, Bazerman and Tenbrunsel (Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 137) assert that particular bounded ethicality phenomena make it “psychologically impossible” that auditors will satisfy the obligation to do an objective audit, an obligation that presumably normative ethical theory, as well as the professional codes that auditors embrace, assign to auditors. Psychologists thus suggest that bounded ethicality raises a fundamental doubt about the value of normative ethical theory for business.

In the remainder of this paper we proceed as follows. In Section 2, we further explain bounded ethicality and elaborate on RBC. We argue that the soundness of RBC depends on a traditional moral principle, “ought implies can (OIC),” which provides, roughly, that a person ought to do something only if she can. In Section 3, we observe that OIC is subject to different interpretations, not all of which are defensible. We argue that the most sensible version of OIC enables us to hold businesspersons under the authority of moral obligations, even when they are influenced by bounded ethicality; normative theorizing should continue to set high ethical standards. In Section 4, we review objections to our view. In Section 5, we discuss the implications of behavioral findings for normative ethics, as well as the implications of our argument for behavioral theorizing.

Normative and behavioral business ethics have co-existed for decades, often with a degree of tension (Donaldson Reference Donaldson1994; Robertson Reference Robertson1993; Treviño and Weaver Reference Treviño and Weaver1994; Weaver and Treviño Reference Weaver and Treviño1994; Werhane Reference Werhane1994). Given the recent prominence of research in behavioral ethics and, in particular, the findings surrounding bounded ethicality, it is more important than ever to understand the relation of the two approaches, and to examine how each can contribute to the other. The contribution of behavioral ethics can be recognized without detracting from the importance of normative ethics for pedagogy and practice, we will conclude.

2. Bounded Ethicality and the Radical Behavioral Challenge

2.1. Bounded Ethicality

The social science field of behavioral ethics aims to explain the behavior of people who face ethical decisions (Bazerman and Gino Reference Bazerman and Gino2012; Tenbrunsel and Smith–Crowe Reference Tenbrunsel and Smith‐Crowe2008; Treviño, Weaver, and Reynolds Reference Treviño, Weaver and Reynolds2006). Psychologists have confirmed the existence of many pernicious influences on ethical decision—often operating at an unconscious level. When these influences lead to unethical behavior that conflict with an actor’s moral beliefs and commitments, the phenomenon may be referred to as bounded ethicality (Bazerman Reference Bazerman2011; Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011; Chugh, Bazerman, and Banaji Reference Chugh, Bazerman, Banaji, Moore, Cain, Loewenstein and Bazerman2005; Tenbrunsel Reference Tenbrunsel, Moore, Cain, Loewenstein and Bazerman2005).Footnote 2

One example of bounded ethicality is “ordinary prejudice,” which reveals itself in implicit associations about gender, race, and other demographic groups (Bertrand, Chugh, and Mullainathan Reference Bertrand, Chugh and Mullainathan2005; Green et al. Reference Green, Carney, Pallin, Ngo, Raymond, Iezzoni and Banaji2007; Greenwald et al. Reference Greenwald, Poehlman, Uhlmann and Banaji2009; Rudman and Ashmore Reference Rudman and Ashmore2007). These associations can lead to unintentionally discriminatory results, such as discriminatory hiring practices (Bertrand, Chugh, and Mullainathan Reference Bertrand, Chugh and Mullainathan2005) and unwarranted discrepancies in the evaluation of the skills and competencies of workers (Bertrand and Mullainathan Reference Bertrand and Mullainathan2004; Reeves Reference Reeves2014), which mimic the results of deliberate discrimination. Other elements of bounded ethicality include “in-group favoritism,” “self-serving bias,” “illusion of control,” “(overly) discounting future consequences,” and “motivated blindness.”Footnote 3

The literature on bounded ethicality is vast. For simplicity, we focus on the stream within it that discusses a phenomenon particularly relevant for business, motivated blindness. This stream is exemplified in work by Moore, Tanlu, and Bazerman (Reference Moore, Tanlu and Bazerman2010). These authors conducted an experiment in which 100 participants were randomly assigned to one of four groups: buyer, seller, buyer’s auditor, or seller’s auditor. Using the same information, including information about how to estimate the worth of a firm, the auditors were asked to estimate a certain company’s value. The auditors were instructed, “Your goal is for this assessment to be as impartial as you can make it,” and were promised a monetary reward for the accuracy of their judgments. The results show that the auditors were aware that their roles had influenced their appraisals, but significantly underestimated this influence and were unable to correct for it. The same experiment was replicated with more than 100 full-time professional auditors from one of the Big Four accounting companies in the U.S. and found similar results. The experiments indicate that the mere role assignment influences auditors to be biased in the interests of their clients (Moore, Tanlu, and Bazerman Reference Moore, Tanlu and Bazerman2010).

The experiments above may be construed to practically imply that “audit failures are natural by-products of the auditor-client relationship” (Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 137). The experiments may also imply that “the current U.S. audit system makes it ‘psychologically impossible’ … for even the most honest auditors to make objective judgments” (Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 137; italics ours). Thus, “cases of audit failure are inevitable” (Bazerman, Morgan, and Loewenstein Reference Bazerman, Morgan and Loewenstein1997, 90).

2.2. The Radical Behavioral Challenge (RBC)

In this section, we review RBC, explaining how bounded ethicality—for instance, motivated blindness—arguably presents a challenge to normative business ethics. We begin with the following hypothetical, inspired by the experiments outlined above (Moore, Tanlu, and Bazerman Reference Moore, Tanlu and Bazerman2010):

Case 1: The Biased Auditors’ Defense

Suppose that you consider buying stock in a California-based smartphone company. You rely upon publicly certified auditors’ reports to determine your stock portfolio. However, you do not know that the auditors were unconsciously biased towards the client’s interests due to motivated blindness. The estimated valuation of the company as reported by the company’s auditors is about 26 percent higher than estimates by impartial experts. A national newspaper happens to discover that the audit is notably biased and discloses the fact to the public. The stock market immediately responds to the scandal and the value of the company’s stocks decreases dramatically. You argue that the auditors and the accounting firm committed a wrong by violating the auditors’ duty to be impartial, independent, and objective (Duska and Duska Reference Duska and Duska2003, chap. 5–6). A clever representative of the auditors, Trevor, denies the complaint, saying, “We did not do anything we should not have done.” Trevor explains that the auditors intended to be as independent and fair as possible and that no act can be wrong or duty-infringing if it is beyond their capacities to act in such a way. Trevor goes on to argue that it is the supervising partners of the accounting firm, the CEO of the client company, and the relevant policy makers who have the institutional resources to enable the auditors to counteract the influence of motivated blindness; therefore, only they wronged you.

Did the biased auditors do anything wrong? We think so. They breached a duty of impartiality. How could Trevor suggest otherwise?

Underlying Trevor’s defense is the philosophical doctrine that “ought” implies “can,” which we state in its most generic form as follows:

OIC: A moral principle binds an agent only if she can act on it.

The auditors committed a wrong only if they had a duty of impartiality, but Trevor, relying on OIC, thinks that the duty cannot and hence does not apply to the auditors.

In coming to terms with OIC, one must recognize that it contains at least two treacherous concepts. First, it is very difficult to say what it means for a principle to bind an agent. Intuitively, by saying that a principle binds a person, we mean that it gives her a reason to act on it and that it gives others a reason to view her critically if she fails to act on it. While this intuitive parsing will have to suffice for purposes of this paper, we note that it appeals to the idea of giving a person a reason to act, which is itself challenging, but outside our scope. The second problematic concept contained in OIC is that which a person can do. As we will argue, different interpretations of “what a person can do” have very different normative implications, and it is therefore important to settle on a sensible interpretation. Still, the basic idea of OIC seems plausible: if a moral agent ought to perform some action then it must be possible for her to do so. If it is impossible, the agent is not obligated to perform the action.

OIC is broadly accepted in the fields of moral philosophy (Altham Reference Altham1988; Donagan Reference Donagan1979; D. Levy Reference Levy and Kolb2008; Stern Reference Stern2004) and normative business ethics (Brenkert Reference Brenkert1995; Goodpaster Reference Goodpaster, Brenkert and Beauchamp2010; Jones and Felps Reference Jones and Felps2013; Kim Reference Kim2014; Phillips Reference Phillips2010). The plausibility of OIC seems clear when we reflect on the harshness of rejecting the principle. Thus, imagine that there is a baby in dire straits on Mars. If you could leap to Mars, you could save the baby. But you cannot make that leap, nor get to Mars in any other way. So it makes no sense to say that you do something wrong by failing to save the baby; because you cannot save the baby, it is untrue that you ought to save the baby. No doubt there are less exotic cases in which it makes sense to say that because you cannot do something, it is untrue that you ought to do it. For example, if you are a quadriplegic and see a baby drowning on the far side of a river, you have no obligation to swim to save the baby. The function of OIC is to enable us to respond intelligently to such cases.

As we have suggested, OIC can be interpreted in various ways. The first interpretation we consider is also the simplest:

OIC 1: A moral principle binds an agent only if she has the occurrent ability to act on it.Footnote 4

A person has an occurrent ability to perform some action, as we shall understand it, if it is true that if she tries to do that action, she will, and nothing prevents her from trying to perform that action. OIC 1 thus identifies what a person can do in terms of contingent facts about that person—what, in fact, happens when she tries to do something. We recognize that both what counts as a person trying to do something and what counts as preventing a person from trying are difficult notions, but we must leave them unanalyzed here.

OIC 1 has many applications. One can use it, for instance, to criticize utilitarianism (Griffin Reference Griffin1992, Reference Griffin1996). By pointing out that we cannot “perform the large-scale calculations of what is best that [utilitarianism] require[s]” (Griffin Reference Griffin1992, 130), one can argue that we are not under an obligation to maximize utility. OIC 1 also has more fundamental implications for moral theorizing in general. For example, James Griffin (Reference Griffin1992, 131) argues as follows:

Moral norms must be tailored to fit the human moral torso. They are nothing but what such tailoring produces. There are no moral norms outside the boundary set by our capacities. Moral norms regulate human action; a norm that ignores the limited nature of human agents is not an “ideal” norm, but no norm at all.

Thus, relying on the OIC 1, Griffin (Reference Griffin1992, Reference Griffin1996) proposes that determinations of right, wrong, duty, and obligation must be in part determined by contingent facts about human abilities. Later we argue that OIC 1 misconstrues the relevance of such facts.

We maintain that a plausible reconstruction of Trevor’s arguments defending the auditors must rely on OIC 1’s distinctive appeal to contingent facts about human abilities. Consider:

The Argument of Radical Behavioral Challenge (RBC):

  • Premise 1) An agent ought morally to act on a principle only if she has the occurrent ability to act on it. (OIC 1.)

  • Premise 2) The auditors in Case 1 do not have the occurrent ability to act on a principle requiring objectivity. (Empirical claim stemming from phenomenon of motivated blindness.)

  • Conclusion) Therefore, it is not true that the auditors in Case 1 ought to act on a principle requiring objectivity. Further, by not acting objectively, these auditors did nothing wrong.

Although as we have presented the argument for RBC, it is about motivational blindness and auditor independence, we will soon argue that the argument can be generalized to cover other obligations affected by other putative sources of bounded ethicality. Indeed, we doubt that any moral principle espoused in commonsense morality or by normative ethics theorists would escape a version of RBC, if RBC were a cogent argument.

Is the argument for RBC cogent? Not if either of its premises is false. We will argue, against Premise 1, that there are clear cases in which an agent lacks an occurrent ability to do x but still can and must do it. Before beginning that discussion, it is worth getting clear about why it is worth having. Thus, as a preliminary matter, we will discuss the significance of RBC. It is tempting to dismiss RBC as a straw person, but we think that it can be a real threat to normative ethics. We want to show that the straw person concern is unfounded. As we see it, there are two versions of the straw person concern: First, that RBC does not pose a problem for any normative theory, research, or claim; second, that nobody really embraces RBC. We address each in turn.

i) Which normative claims are challenged by RBC?:

RBC challenges many normative arguments, including any argument that maintains that auditors generally have an obligation to be impartial, objective, and fair. For example, Ronald Duska and Brenda Duska (Reference Duska and Duska2003, 31, 85, 95, 125, 203) defend the Code of Conduct of the American Institute of CPAs (AICPA), which stipulates that all members ought to adhere to “The principle of objectivity,” which “imposes the obligation to be impartial, intellectually honest, and free of conflicts of interest” (AICPA 2014). John Boatright (Reference Boatright2007) also justifies accountants’ moral obligation to be even-handed, which he refers to as the “gatekeepers’ obligation.” We suspect that most, if not all, business ethics teachers would accept that auditors have such a duty. RBC is inconsistent with all such positions.

But the challenge posed by RBC transcends auditor independence. For example, RBC challenges arguments in favor of fair treatment of minorities and other disadvantaged populations. Thomas Donaldson (Reference Donaldson1989) defends a list of fundamental international rights, including non-discriminatory treatment. Implicit biases against certain disadvantaged groups and in-group favoritism may thwart organizational efforts at non-discrimination.Footnote 5 Hence, RBC poses a challenge to the advocacy of rights against nondiscriminatory treatment.

More generally, RBC challenges moral guidance with respect to the values of fairness and justice in business organizations. For instance, Jeffrey Harrison and Andrew Wicks (Reference Harrison and Wicks2013) defend organizational justice as one of the four main values that any adequate stakeholders approaches should embody. Robert Audi and Patrick Murphy (Reference Audi and Murphy2006) explain that one important dimension of business integrity is the virtue of fairness. In fact, we suspect that almost all business ethics theories, except for those grounded in moral egoism, would submit that organizations should espouse and enhance the value and rules of fairness (e.g., Bowie Reference Bowie1991, Bowie Reference Bowie1998; McCall Reference McCall2001, McCall Reference McCall2003; Radin and Werhane Reference Radin and Werhane2003). However, certain forms of bounded ethicality, such as the self-serving bias or over-claiming credit, may make it difficult to see how one or one’s organization is behaving unfairly towards internal or external stakeholders, and can therefore impede fairness and justice from being realized (Brewer Reference Brewer1979; Dasgupta Reference Dasgupta2004; Epley and Caruso Reference Epley and Caruso2004; Ross Reference Ross and Berkowitz1977).

ii) Who asserts RBC?:

The second form that the straw person objection takes is as follows: RBC poses no challenge because nobody endorses it; there is no point arguing against RBC because it expresses a position that nobody takes.

Our response to the second form of the straw person argument relies on an empirical claim. We have heard the claim confirmed in the hallways of different business schools, and we feel confident that much of this journal’s readership shares our experience. The claim is that many business school colleagues and students dismiss normative business ethics as “impractical.” Anyone who has taught business ethics has likely encountered business students or practitioners who argue for some unarticulated versions of RBC. To our knowledge, however, no scholars have explicitly proposed RBC. Nonetheless, the mere fact that no scholar has actually proposed the challenge does not mean that we do not have reason to evaluate it. What is important is whether or not the challenge can be plausibly proposed, and, if so, whether it is forceful enough to challenge existing perspectives. We have shown that it is.

Second, the two premises of RBC are latent in two bodies of existing literature: philosophical ethics and behavioral ethics. The first premise of RBC is the OIC 1, which various scholars (e.g., Griffin Reference Griffin1992, Reference Griffin1996; Vranas Reference Vranas2007) have supported. The second premise of RBC is bounded ethicality, which has been well documented. Although no one has explicitly asserted RBC, its conclusion is contained in the two premises. In this article, we simply draw upon two areas of scholarship that do not often speak directly to one other in order to articulate the argument of RBC.

3. Rejecting the Radical Behavioral Challenge

In this section, we aim to show that RBC derives its plausibility from flaws in OIC 1. Kant had OIC correct, and, once one appreciates Kant’s analysis, RBC loses its appeal, as does OIC 1. The insight in Kant’s argument, we believe, is that it shows that judgments about what a person can do are typically more than empirical reports about individual propensities and occurrent abilities. People have rational resources that OIC 1 does not reflect.

3.1. Kant’s Version of OIC

We accept Robert Stern’s (Reference Stern2004) analysis of Kant’s (Reference Kant, Guyer and Wood1999, Reference Kant and Gregor1996b, Reference Kant and Gregor1996a) original articulation of OIC. On this interpretation, Kant did not mean for “can” to be interpreted according to individual agents’ contingent abilities. Instead, Kant argued that moral requirements are determined by “what obligations can be shown to apply to rational agents capable of acting rightly; and then, once the moral law is fixed, [Kant] uses ‘ought implies can’ to determine what we are capable of qua human beings, in so far as we fall under this law” (Stern Reference Stern2004, 60). On this view, the very fact that the moral law binds us indicates that, as rational beings, we are capable of following it. In a manner of speaking, according to Kant, whether we “can” is determined by the fact that we “ought.” One might then interpret Kant’s version of OIC as follows:

OIC 2: A moral principle binds an agent only if a rational agent acting out of respect for the moral law could act on it.

Notice that OIC 2 cannot be used to underwrite RBC. Presumably, for example, cognitively perfect, superhuman, rational moral agents could act on a principle of auditor objectivity, even if we cognitively flawed humans cannot.

However, OIC 2 may also pose problems for the critic of RBC. If “ought” implies “can” provides merely that we humans ought to do something only if perfect creatures could do that thing, it does not limit our obligations to do objective audits. As stated, OIC 2 seems implausibly demanding. For instance, it could conceivably underwrite an obligation to defy gravity, or perform some other physically impossible feat. Recall the Martian we discussed earlier. While our Martian was visiting us on Earth, if she noticed that a baby was in dire straits on Mars, who could be saved only by immediately popped to Mars, our superhuman Martian could save the baby. We cannot. That fact about us seems to support the idea that we have no obligation to save the baby. Ruling out the Martian case is something that a credible OIC principle should do, but OIC 2 fails to do it. Of course, as written, OIC 2 states a necessary condition for a morally binding principle, not a sufficient condition, and so it does not declare that we humans have an obligation to jump to Mars. Still, as a necessary condition, it is not informative about us humans.

A principle of charity of interpretation requires that we attribute to Kant a version of OIC that shows greater deference to human limits. Humans are subject to the laws of nature, just as they are subject to the moral law. One cannot ask human beings to overturn laws of nature, particularly those that govern human action. We thus propose the following interpretation of Kant’s OIC:

OIC 3: A moral principle binds a human agent only if, were she a rational human agent acting out of respect for the moral law and acting consistently with the laws of nature, she could act on it.Footnote 6

As no rational human agent could save the Martian baby, OIC 3 correctly avoids saying that it would be wrong to not save the baby. OIC 3 is otherwise promising. It generally does not deny the wrongfulness of an action as easily as OIC 1 does. Suppose that an adult responsible for childcare intentionally becomes so drunk that he cannot care for his child, and that the child consequently suffers a terrible accident. Arguably the adult does nothing wrong on OIC 1, because he did not have the occurrent ability to act on a principle dictating that one takes good care of his children. But he does something wrong on OIC 3, because a rational agent could act on a principle requiring that one take reasonable care of one’s child. How, if at all, do these differences matter for case involving the influence of bounded ethicality?

4. Comparing Versions of OIC

In this section we will argue that OIC 3 better illuminates issues of bounded ethicality than does OIC 1. In applying any OIC principle, much turns on the interpretation of the word “can” and its cognates. Can auditors, for example, act without bias? The fact, as we have seen, is that most don’t, and from that fact one might infer that most can’t, that bounded ethicality limits what most auditors can do. But we think that inference would be rash. In the moral assessment of the actions and auditors and others affected by bounded ethicality, options may be expansive. For all relevant moral purposes, we should conclude that auditors can do objective audits.

In some of the most influential psychological studies of phenomena that might be identified as bounded ethicality, most but not all subjects act against their moral obligations. Thus in Asch’s (Reference Asch1956), Darley and Batson’s (Reference Darley and Batson1973), and Milgram’s (Reference Milgram1974) works, many subjects act wrongly, succumbing to influences representing bounded ethicality, but other subjects do not. This suggests that the impact of bounded ethicality is fixed not by the laws of human nature but by human choice. One of Asch’s (Reference Asch1956) experiments found that 25% of the subjects under group pressure to conform to wrongful expectations refused to conform. While this is not a majority, it demonstrates that 25% of subjects did not succumb to the psychological influence of conformity. Similarly, in Darley and Batson’s (Reference Darley and Batson1973) study, seminary students were observed walking past a victim who needed help while they were on their way to give a talk. One group was not prompted to hurry, the second was prompted to hurry only moderately, and the third was prompted to hurry quite a lot by being told they were running late. Of the subjects who were not in any hurry, 63% helped the victim. A lower proportion, 45%, of those subjects under moderate-hurry conditions helped the victim in need. Of those under the high-hurry conditions, 10% helped. Again, there are individuals who, even under stressful conditions, can stop and do what seems most commendable. Milgram’s (Reference Milgram1974) experiments also feature individuals who did not succumb to obedience to authority. If these cases confirm the phenomenon of bounded ethicality, demonstrating that psychological influences can cause people to act wrongly, they also demonstrate that people can find ways to avoid or limit the effects of these influences.

Even Bazerman and Tenbrunsel (2011, chap. 8) acknowledge it is possible to help individuals correct their behaviors in the face of bounded ethicality. One suggested technique for countering the effects of bounded ethicality is the engagement of “pre-commitment devices,” through which individuals are encouraged to publicly share their intended ethical choices with impartial third-parties, as this helps to escalate their commitment and increases the likelihood that they will behave as they hope (see Brockner and Rubin Reference Brockner and Rubin1985 for reviews). Another suggestion is to learn to “recognize the signs that you are in a cognitive minefield, slow down, and ask for reinforcement from System 2 thinking,” which involves reflection and careful analysis, as opposed to relying on one’s intuitive System 1 thought processes (Kahneman Reference Kahneman2011, 417). To be fair, Kahneman believes this is more difficult than it sounds. To help the process along, Bazerman and Tenbrunsel suggest “focusing on the abstract principles that guide decisions” and “thinking about the values and principles that you believe should guide the decision” to help engage one’s System 2 processes (Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 157). Tools to do so include imagining what you would like said in your eulogy or thinking about whether you would feel comfortable sharing your decision with your mother (Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 156–157). While we should not exaggerate the extent to which these tactics help decision-makers do the right thing, the fact that the tactics often help individuals avoid the impact of bounded ethicality is evidence that bounded ethicality has limited impact on auditor decision-making and is not, as Bazerman and Tenbrunsel (Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 137) say, “inevitable." Further, if bounded ethicality is not inevitable, then it is not a law of nature.

One might object that we rely on a simplistic notion of how laws of nature affect human action. These laws can be probabilistic and not deterministic. If the laws are merely probabilistic, then they do not dictate that each auditor acts in a biased way, but rather that it is probable that for any particular auditor, she acts in a biased way, or that a particular proportion of auditors do so. So, the objection concludes, we should not be surprised when some people show themselves not to be victims of bounded ethicality; some people are victims, others are not, and victims cannot do objective audits. If one engages in a biased action as an expression of either a probabilistic law or a deterministic law, the normative significance is the same, one might argue: the action occurs as the result of a law of nature outside one’s control, and one cannot sensibly be expected to act on a principle requiring one to do otherwise, that is, one cannot be required to break the laws of nature in order act in an unbiased manner. And so, one might think, to the extent that psychological findings of bounded ethicality express even probabilistic laws of nature, they show that most cannot adhere to principles proscribing bias. That fact, combined with OIC 1, one might conclude, shows that these auditors do no wrong by issuing biased reports. In response to this objection, we maintain that it makes no difference whether psychological laws undergirding bounded ethicality and bias are probabilistic or deterministic; the same choices are available no matter what the structure of the law. In saying this, we invoke Bazerman, Tenbrunsel, and others who do research on bounded ethicality while advising people how to avoid its pitfalls. Bounded ethicality may indeed be a pernicious influence, but there is no reason to think that it is an influence that competent people can’t handle. Hence, bounded ethicality presents no reason in support for RBC.

When Bazerman and Tenbrunsel talk about interacting with people who have problematic biases, the approach they advocate demonstrates the superiority of OIC 3 to OIC 1. Recall that OIC 3 instructs us to assess what a person can do in terms of what a rational agent can do, while OIC 1 instead has us look at a person’s contingent propensities. Bazerman and Tenbrunsel approach people with biases as agents with the rational resources to improve their behavior, not as a set of propensities constrained to repeat behavior. Bazerman and Tenbrunsel’s practice is hopeful about human rational possibilities, and thus makes best sense on OIC 3, not OIC 1.

A proponent of RBC might say that we do not take bounded ethicality seriously enough, that we do not appreciate how it can make some moral choices in fact impossible; she might thus claim that OIC 3 is unrealistic. To answer this concern, we introduce a case in which bounded ethicality may seem more powerful than in the auditor case, a case in which we stipulate that the decision-maker simply cannot, in one important sense of that term, avoid biased judgment. Reflection on this case shows, we believe, that OIC 1, not OIC 3, is unrealistic:

Case 2: The Loan Officer

You head an Asian-American household living in a rental. To achieve your dream to be a homeowner, you apply for a home mortgage. Your loan officer was raised to dislike persons of East Asian origin and has long cultivated her racism by reading racist tracts and immersing herself in a racist subculture. Through her upbringing and actions, she has been rendered incapable of making decisions in racially impartial ways. There is no remedy available to the racist loan officer in the moment that she must decide on your application. She denies the loan, despite the fact that she has approved loans to similarly qualified Caucasian loan applicants. Therefore, you believe that she has unfairly discriminated against you, acting wrongly. The officer claims that she is incapable of applying the loan criteria in a race-neutral way; she says that it is untrue that she ought not to discriminate unfairly against Asians.

Let us suppose, for the sake of argument, that it makes sense to say that this loan officer was psychologically incapable of applying loan criteria in a race-neutral way. She disapproved the loan, thereby committing a paradigmatically wrongful, racist act. One might think that this particular act is not entirely the officer’s fault, because she was raised as a racist since childhood. Even so, we maintain, it makes sense to say to her, “You ought not to reject that loan application for racist reasons.”

Proponents of the OIC 1, such as Vranas (Reference Vranas2007), might deny that it makes sense to tell the loan officer that she should not reject the loan application for racist reasons, arguing that because the loan officer was incapable of acting on non-racist reasons, it makes no sense to complain when she acts on racist reasons. Still, Vranas might say that there exists a way to account for our judgment about what is appropriate to say to the racist. For instance, proponents might argue that we should not infer from the statements, “You ought not to be racist,” or “You ought to be race-neutral in applying the loan criteria,” an actual ascription of an obligation or duty to the racist. Instead, we ought to interpret these statements as merely pointing out what would be “fitting or good” in these circumstances (Vranas Reference Vranas2007, 179). In other words, this kind of “ought” statement is not really evaluative or prescriptive, but merely idealized or aspirational, and, as such, does not imply “can” (Altham Reference Altham1988, 281–282; Haines Reference Haines1972, 263). We disagree.

The proponents’ interpretation is not plausible in addressing the appropriateness of the demand, “You ought to be race-neutral in applying the criteria.” Assuming that this demand is appropriate given the moral facts at hand, it is odd to interpret the “ought” statements as merely issuing an aspirational statement about what would have been “fitting or good.” It makes much more sense to interpret the statements at face value, i.e., as a moral demand that the loan officer be impartial now. Thus, given our practices, it makes sense to reject OIC 1, and thereby to reject RBC.

In contrast to the OIC 1, OIC 3 does not necessitate a scramble to find the hidden meanings in appropriate-sounding “ought” statements. For the OIC 3, the proper point of reference for “can” is duties or obligations ascribed to a rational agent capable of acting rightly and operating under the laws of nature. Because denying a loan based on race is inconsistent with the moral value or rules of fairness, rational agents capable of acting rightly are under the obligation not to be racist; loan officers are obligated to decide loans in a race-neutral manner. OIC 3 confirms this obligation.

An implication of embracing the OIC 1 is that we lower moral standards for those confronting bounded ethicality and other social or psychological influences that act as impediments to doing the right thing. While it is important for normative theorizing and pedagogy to recognize those impediments, these impediments should not function as a justification for not doing the right thing. Conceding RBC and allowing bounded ethicality to partially determine moral standards of right and wrong would lead to a corruption of those standards, rendering them false and overly lax. It would also open the door to a subjectivism of morals, which makes it plausible for the racist loan officer and the auditors to reply, “Well, impartiality may be right for you, but it is not right for me.” These complaints about OIC 1, Vranas’ interpretation of OIC, show that it is normatively undesirable, resulting in an unattractive lowering of moral standards. He might respond that even if his position points to undesirable facts about humans, it does not follow that his position is false. To show that the position is false, we must show some flaw in OIC 1. The Loan Officer Case simplifies the task of finding a flaw, because it stipulates that the loan officer occurrently cannot act in an unbiased way.

It makes sense to criticize the loan officer’s action as wrong, we think, because a person’s failures of rationality do not limit his obligations. We will show this for the case of culpable drunkenness, and suggest a generalization to bounded ethicality. Bounded ethicality affects decision-making in morally different ways, and it is worth sorting through some of the varieties.

If, in fact, the loan officer in our scenario cannot make an unbiased decision, it is her fault that she cannot, as she has chosen to cultivate her biases. OIC 1 measures a person’s obligation purely in terms of her occurrent abilities, but that is implausible when it is her fault that her present abilities are defective. When it is one’s fault that one cannot avoid doing a wrong, one’s action may nonetheless be wrong and even blameworthy. Consider wrong acts committed while drunk. When a drunk driver recklessly injures a pedestrian, his action is nonetheless wrong; he may even be regarded as blameworthy for that action, as long as he voluntarily became drunk. His drunkenness has no bearing on what ultimately he should have done: drive cautiously, not recklessly, even though he could not have driven cautiously in the occurrent sense of “can” from OIC 1. It follows from reflection on the culpable drunkenness case, we think, that the sense of “can” in OIC 3 is what matters for morally right action, not the sense of “can” in OIC 1. In Case 2, the loan officer voluntarily put herself into a position in which her bias would lead her to do wrong. She is responsible for her bias and the wrong acts that issue from it, just as the culpable drunk is responsible for what he does while drunk. Our loan officer scenario is not unrealistic. A person who rises to the position of a loan officer has had many years to try to neutralize her bias. If she does not, she is complicit in that bias. Both the culpable drunkenness case and the self-cultivated bias case are interesting because they show that sometimes the fact that a person cannot occurrently engage in an action does not exclude her from an obligation to engage in that action. In both these cases, the fact that a person cannot occurrently fulfill her obligation is in part her fault, but we do not think that this fact is an essential feature of cases in which occurrent disabilities do not limit moral obligation.

Suppose, for the sake of argument, that the loan officer is somehow not complicit in her bias, and that she simply cannot, as a matter of her occurrent abilities, bring herself to make an unbiased decision on the East Asian’s application. She can still act rightly even if she cannot reach an unbiased verdict on the loan applications. For example, she can recuse herself, refusing to make a decision on the application, turning the application over to a better-equipped colleague. If the loan officer nonetheless makes a biased decision on the application, we can then reasonably complain that she made the morally wrong choice on the application, because she had another option available to her, turning the choice over to someone else. The highest moral standards properly apply to the loan officer. The best explanation why she should recuse herself is that it would be wrong for her to reach a biased verdict on the loan application.Footnote 7 A proponent of OIC 1 will, of course, respond that it makes no sense to say that the loan officer ought to act fairly because she (occurrently) can’t. But, as we have already seen in the drunk driver case, sometimes it makes sense to say that a person ought to do something even if he occurrently can’t. Culpable drunkenness constitutes one context in which an occurrent ability to do something (drive carefully) turns out to be no prerequisite for an obligation to do that thing (drive carefully), but it is only one example of a morally flawed exercise of rationality not limiting obligations. There are others. Indeed, even if one is nonculpably intoxicated because, for example, someone secretly put drugs in one’s soft drink, one must nevertheless drive carefully, not recklessly. A compromised state of mind, if relevant, may give one an excuse for doing something wrong, but does not make one’s action any less wrong. Just as we are all morally obligated not to drive recklessly in ways affected by intoxication, no matter what our occurrent abilities, we are also required not to act in ways affected by personal prejudices and other moral failures of rationality. The right action for the loan officer is to issue a fair verdict, no matter what her occurrent abilities. Doing so is what a rational person concerned about conforming to the moral law would do. Thus, OIC 3 captures the correct sense of “ought implies can,” OIC 1 does not, and RBC is defeated.

5. Objections

In this section, we respond to objections that might be raised against our arguments.

5.1. Objection 1: Case 2 and the Role of “Can”

One might doubt that Case 2 functions as a strong argument against RBC. Case 2 recommends that the loan officer take action against her bias. But if she can do this, then it would seem that she can be impartial after all. A case in which a person can simply avoid the biases of bounded ethicality is irrelevant to RBC, the objection might conclude.

In response, we would point out we stipulate that in Case 2 it is psychologically impossible for the auditor to avoid bias; her occurrent psychological state stands in the way of an impartial judgment. But while we hold that she cannot avoid bias, we maintain that as a practical matter she can avoid acting on her bias. It is important to see that her action is wrong so that it is clear that she should not do it. OIC 1 does not allow one to declare her action to be wrong. And that is sufficient reason to reject OIC 1 in favor of OIC 3.

5.2. Objection 2: Blame, Liability, and Punishment

One might invoke the following reductio as a way in order to reject OIC 3:

  • Premise 1) OIC 3.

  • Premise 2) OIC 3 justifies blaming, holding liable, or punishing someone for something that she cannot occurently do.

  • Premise 3) Blaming, holding liable, or punishing someone for something she cannot occurently do is unfair.

  • Conclusion) Therefore, OIC 3 should be rejected.

This argument is mistaken because Premise (2) is false. Our argument concerns act evaluation (e.g., Tony has an ex ante duty not to perform a particular act; or a particular act is impermissible). Act evaluation is conceptually distinct from agency evaluation (e.g., Tony is not culpable, blameworthy, or liable for performing a particular act) (Arpaly and Schroeder Reference Arpaly and Schroeder2014; Bennett Reference Bennett1995).Footnote 8 Consider, for instance, cases of criminal law where the punishment, which can be understood as a public expression of blameworthiness (Feinberg Reference Feinberg1965), is partly determined by mens rea of criminals and relevant situational factors. It is noteworthy, however, that the processes for attributing blame, liability, or punishment to agency does not affect the wrongness or the impermissibility of the criminal act itself. Whether someone intentionally hurts a child or does so through negligence or even unintentionally, the act of child abuse per se is wrong and impermissible, regardless of the mental states or any capabilities of the agent. The agent in both cases has an equally stringent duty not to abuse children.

Likewise, regardless of whether, for example, the biased auditors’ agencies are blameworthy/culpable/liable for the financial damage involved in Case 1, one can, as a separate matter, argue that they have an independent duty to be impartial. Even if they did something they should not have done, it is a different matter to define how blameworthy they are. Hence, the fact that OIC 3 implies that the auditors have a duty of fairness does not necessarily entail anything about agency evaluation, blame, punishment, or liability. Thus, Premise 2) must be rejected, which responds to the objection at hand.Footnote 9

6. Conclusion

We have presented an argument to defend normative business ethics against the Radical Behavioral Challenge (RBC). If we are correct about the status of RBC, normative ethics can continue to ascribe obligations and to generate “ought” statements that bind even those moral agents susceptible to the influence of bounded ethicality. That is, the obligations of moral actors remain the same regardless of their knowledge of bounded ethicality or their ability to effectively combat it. Naturally, the knowledge that bounded ethicality exists may generate new obligations for moral actors—the obligation, for example, to undertake effective means to combat the relevant social and psychological influences of bounded ethicality. It is a significant contribution of behavioral business ethics that it helps us to think about the necessity of recognizing these new obligations.

Interestingly, RBC challenges even behavioral business ethicists’ criticism about the insufficiency of normative business ethics for ethics education. Behavioral business ethicists’ pedagogical challenge to normative ethics is that theories of normative business ethics are irrelevant for ethics education because they cannot help individuals to make the right decision or act rightly (Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, chap. 2). To overcome psychological impediments, behavioral ethicists suggest that the auditors, for instance, look to the findings of behavioral ethics. Note that this remedy assumes that the right thing to do is not to be biased in favor of their clients. In other words, behavioral ethicists, just like their normative counterparts, would assert a normative claim that the auditors ought not to be biased toward the clients. This clearly normative claim, which many behavioral business ethicists believe to be true, enables behavioral business ethicists to criticize normative business ethics arguments and pedagogy. If RBC is true, however, then the normative claim that the auditors ought not to be biased is untenable, and, accordingly, behavioral ethicists’ pedagogical criticisms of normative ethics are likewise untenable. Thus, in defending the usefulness of normative business ethics against RBC, we have bolstered the practical and pedagogical relevance of behavioral ethics, too.

What contribution can behavioral ethics make to normative business ethics?Footnote 10 Normative business ethics’ primary role is to study what values organizations should espouse, assess what obligations or duties to ascribe to individuals within those organizations, and determine which policies and regulations are appropriate for governing businesses and markets in a just society. As we mentioned, this requires normative business ethics theory to develop frameworks to understand organizational and individual obligations for handling problems of bounded ethicality. In addition, because normative ethics also concerns itself with evaluating whether agents are blameworthy or deserving of punishment, it is possible that bounded ethicality may affect such agential evaluations. Whether bounded ethicality can affect blameworthiness and how it might mitigate blame deserve serious investigation and present an area for fruitful future research (Holroyd Reference Holroyd2015; N. Levy Reference Levy2014; Machery Reference Machery2010; Saul Reference Saul, Jenkins and Hutchison2013).

Finally, we ask, does behavioral business ethics have anything to learn from normative ethics? The normative findings that we have revealed in this article have significant implications about behavioral theorizing. If the philosophical argument that we have defended in this article is correct, then we have good reason to maintain higher moral standards, even though each and every businessperson may not always be able to perform these duties or obligations. If an important goal of behavioral business ethics is to help businesspersons to perform these duties, they have two primary options. One option is to lower standards with the assistance of the OIC 1, which is a possibility we have rejected. The second and more promising option is to emphasize the existence of those who have cultivated or possess the ability to live bold, unbounded ethicality, that is, those who do not succumb to the influence of pessimistic, bounded ethicality. This suggests that it is worth paying closer attention to these individuals capable of breaking through the influence of bounded ethicality. We want to recall that Asch’s (Reference Asch1956) memorable study was titled “Studies of Independence and Conformity: I. A Minority of One Against A Unanimous Majority” (italics ours), and that 25% of the experiment participants were capable of independence in the face of pressures to conform. In this line of reasoning, we suggest that behavioral ethics scholars have good reason to study not only the bounded ethicality of the 75%, but to expend equal time and resources studying the unbounded ethicality of the 25%.

Acknowledgements

An earlier version of this article was presented at the Society for Business Ethics Annual Meeting in Philadelphia. We are indebted to Ken Goodpaster, Nien-hê Hsieh, Jessica Kennedy, Daryl Koehn, and Diana Robertson for their feedback. Several anonymous reviewers, along with BEQ editor Denis Arnold, provided excellent guidance. Thanks to all for comments and advice, including those who think that we are absolutely wrong.

Footnotes

1. Joshua Margolis has written about the gap between what normative theory prescribes and what people can actually do, calling it the “responsibility gap” (Margolis 2009). However, while Margolis calls upon normative business ethicists to be mindful of this gap, his statements do not necessarily imply an endorsement of the Radical Behavioral Challenge.

2. In other sources, bounded ethicality is defined somewhat differently. For instance, the video and associated teaching materials on the University of Texas at Austin’s Ethics Unwrapped website simply refer to bounded ethicality as the notion that situational influences can overcome dispositional ones, even overriding individuals’ own ethical preferences (Prentice Reference Prentice2014). However, other sources, including those cited above, are more specific in defining bounded ethicality as an umbrella term designating influences that prompt us to undertake unethical actions that go against our stated or conscious ethical beliefs without our awareness. We abide by the latter definition in this article.

3. In-group favoritism has to do with the fact that we are more likely to do favors for those who are similar to ourselves, e.g., in terms of race, nationality, religion, gender (Brewer Reference Brewer1979; Dasgupta Reference Dasgupta2004 for a literature review). The effects of in-group favoritism can be found in business settings, such as mortgage lending, or non-business settings, such as doing favors for one’s relatives and friends with respect to the distribution of scarce resources. As with implicit biases, the effects of in-group favoritism can also mimic those of intentional discrimination (Bazerman and Tenbrunsel Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 38–39). The self-serving bias refers to our tendency to process and evaluate information in ways that are self-serving. It is evidenced in a variety of ways (Epley and Caruso Reference Epley and Caruso2004). For instance, we tend to over claim credit due to us for positive outcomes (Ross Reference Ross and Berkowitz1977) and overestimate the extent to which others will respond the same way we do to similar situations (Ross, Greene, and House Reference Ross, Greene and House1977). The illusion of control refers to the fact that we tend to overestimate our control over outcomes, thereby underestimating the role of luck or chance (Feather and Simon Reference Feather and Simon1971). Overly discounting the future leads to the application of unreasonably high discount rates to the future, giving undue preference to short term considerations over long term ones (Loewenstein and Thaler Reference Loewenstein and Thaler1989). This can lead to suboptimal and unethical decision-making. Bazerman and Tenbrunsel (Reference Bazerman and Tenbrunsel2011, 48–49) review a number of problems that stem from overly discounting the future, such as environmental destruction, climate change, and the explosion of the national debt of the United States. Lastly, motivated blindness refers to the fact that we discount or ignore information that it is in our interest not to notice (Gino, Moore, and Bazerman Reference Gino, Moore and Bazerman2008).

4. In Robert Stern’s (Reference Stern2004) article, what we call OIC 1 is referred to as strong OIC, and OIC 2 is referred to as weak OIC. In Stern’s article, the qualifiers “weak” and “strong” refer to the role the capabilities of an individual actor (i.e., their “can”) play in defining standards of right and wrong. Seen this way, OIC 1 (strong OIC) refers to the version in which the capacities of individual agents are decisive for the standards of right and wrong for them, and OIC 2 (weak OIC) refers to the version in which those capacities are not at all relevant, such that the capacities play a weak (or nonexistent) role.

5. For instance, male and female academics voting whether or not to hire a job candidate were more likely to vote to hire the male candidate versus the female candidate with the same CV (Steinpreis, Anders, and Ritzke Reference Steinpreis, Anders and Ritzke1999). Likewise, resumes with names commonly associated with Caucasians received 50% more interview offers than resumes with names commonly associated with African-Americans (Bertrand and Mullainathan Reference Bertrand and Mullainathan2004). If RBC were a cogent argument, one would not be able to say that those in charge of hiring in these contexts are committing a wrong.

6. For simplicity we limit OIC 3 to human agents. A fuller version of the principle would apply to all rational agents.

7. As an anonymous reviewer points out, one might object to Case 2 along the following lines. If, as we stipulate, the loan officer could avoid acting on her bias by recusing herself, then she should have been aware of her bias. Otherwise, she would not be able to recuse herself, because she would not see a reason to avoid acting on her bias. Then, one might doubt that Case 2 is relevant to Case 1. The auditors in Case 1 were not aware of the bias—a common feature of bounded ethicality—, so they could not see a reason to take preventive measures to counteract their bias.

However, Case 2 does not function as a parallel argument. It functions as reductio ad absurdum against OIC 1 alone, showing that OIC 1 would force an inability to assign the racist loan officer an obligation to be impartial in applying loan criteria—an absurdity. We choose the racist loan officer who could avoid acting on her bias and recuse herself, because her case is offensive enough to clearly show the absurdity of OIC 1. As we have discussed, if OIC 1 is defeated, then RBC is defeated, regardless of the parallel between Cases 1 and 2.

8. Perhaps another way to characterize our distinction can be gleaned from the literature on legal excuses and justifications. In the legal literature, an agent who offers an excuse admits wrongdoing, but denies that she ought to be blamed. This is in contrast with a justification, which is offered when an agent wants to argue that what she did was not wrong given the circumstances, even if the act in question is commonly thought to be wrong. For further reading, see Austin (Reference Austin1956), Baron (Reference Baron2005), Berman (Reference Berman2003), Dressler (Reference Dressler1987), and Robinson (Reference Robinson2009).

9. One might ask: Doesn’t bounded ethicality challenge the agential aspect of normative business ethics? Specifically, critics might argue that typical theories of normative business ethics, developed with the presumption that individuals can do what is ethically required, would not hesitate to claim that the biased auditors in Case 1 are fully blameworthy or liable as agents unrestrained by bounded ethicality. As explained, this is a tangential issue to our topic in this paper, but let us briefly explain why this criticism is not challenge to normative business ethics. For the sake of argument, suppose that the biased auditors in Case 1 were not blameworthy at all. This would not be a challenge to normative ethics. It would be a challenge only to those who believed that the empirical findings about limited human capacities are irrelevant to agent evaluation. Careful normative ethicists, when evaluating agency, pay attention to mental states and all other relevant situational factors (e.g., Goodpaster Reference Goodpaster, Brenkert and Beauchamp2010; Reference Goodpaster2011; Schreck, van Aaken, and Donaldson Reference Schreck, van Aaken and Donaldson2013). If the auditors’ biased valuations are unintentionally biased, then their culpability, i.e., the degree of blameworthiness, must be adjusted accordingly, a moral fact that few normative business ethicists would contest. This adjustment would be no surprise to normative ethicists, given the rich discussions about culpability and blameworthiness in normative ethics, such as those found in philosophical discussions regarding the function of excuses and justifications in criminal law (e.g., Austin Reference Austin1956; Baron Reference Baron2005; Berman Reference Berman2003; Dressler Reference Dressler1987; Robinson Reference Robinson2009). Therefore, if certain ethicists do not consider mental states or other relevant factors in determining culpability, they would be the origin of the problem, not normative theory itself. Still, perhaps, all of us, including the general public, were a little bit naïve before learning the findings on bounded ethicality. We believe that there is good reason for all business ethics instructors and theorists to pay more attention to these findings.

10. For example, work by Christopher Bryan, Gabrielle Adams, and Benoît Monin (Reference Bryan, Adams and Monin2013) suggests that one can reduce unethical behavior by giving instructions framed in terms of character and identity (e.g., “Please don’t be a cheater”), as opposed to framing them in terms of the act (e.g., “Please don’t cheat”). Additionally, it has been shown that encouraging a belief in determinism increases cheating (Vohs and Schooler Reference Vohs and Schooler2008). As an anonymous reviewer points out, one might argue that these kinds of findings have implications for normative theory, if one of its roles is to influence people to behave ethically.

References

REFERENCES

Altham, J. E. J. 1988. “Understanding the Logic of Obligation.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 62: 271–83.Google Scholar
American Institute of Certified Public Accountants (AICPA). 2014. “AICPA Code of Professional Conduct.” Code of Conduct. American Institute of Certified Public Accountants, Inc.http://www.aicpa.org/Research/Standards/CodeofConduct/DownloadableDocuments/2014December15ContentAsof2014Sept24CodeofConduct.pdf.Google Scholar
Arpaly, Nomy, and Schroeder, Timothy. 2014. In Praise of Desire. OUP USA Oxford Moral Theory.Google Scholar
Asch, Solomon E. 1956. “Studies of Independence and Conformity: I. A Minority of One against a Unanimous Majority.” Psychological Monographs: General and Applied 70(9): 170. doi:10.1037/h0093718.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Audi, Robert, and Murphy, Patrick E. 2006. “The Many Faces of Integrity.” Business Ethics Quarterly 16(1): 321. doi:10.5840/beq20061615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Austin, J. L. 1956. “A Plea for Excuses: The Presidential Address.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57: 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baron, Marcia. 2005. “Justifications and Excuses.” Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 2: 387.Google Scholar
Bazerman, Max H. 2011. “Bounded Ethicality in Negotiations.” Negotiation and Conflict Management Research 4(1): 811. doi:10.1111/j.1750-4716.2010.00069.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bazerman, Max H., and Gino, Francesca. 2012. “Behavioral Ethics: Toward a Deeper Understanding of Moral Judgment and Dishonesty.” Annual Review of Law and Social Science 8: 85104. doi:10.1146/annurev-lawsocsci-102811-173815.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bazerman, Max H., Morgan, Kimberly P., and Loewenstein, George F. 1997. “The Impossibility of Auditor Independence.” MIT Sloan Management Review 38(4): 8994.Google Scholar
Bazerman, Max H., and Tenbrunsel, Ann E. 2011. Blind Spots: Why We Fail to Do What’s Right and What to Do about It. New Haven: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, Jonathan. 1995. The Act Itself. 1st edition. Oxford : New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Berman, Mitchell N. 2003. “Justification and Excuse, Law and Morality.” Duke Law Journal 53(1): 177.Google Scholar
Bertrand, Marianne, Chugh, Dolly, and Mullainathan, Sendhil. 2005. “Implicit Discrimination.” The American Economic Review 95(2): 9498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bertrand, Marianne, and Mullainathan, Sendhil. 2004. “Are Emily and Greg More Employable than Lakisha and Jamal? A Field Experiment on Labor Market Discrimination.” The American Economic Review 94(4): 9911013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boatright, John R. 2007. “Reluctant Guardians: The Moral Responsibility of Gatekeepers.” Business Ethics Quarterly 17(4): 613–32. doi:10.5840/beq20071742.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bowie, Norman E. 1991. “Challenging the Egoistic Paradigm.” Business Ethics Quarterly 1(1): 121. doi:10.2307/3857590.Google Scholar
Bowie, Norman E. 1998. “A Kantian Theory of Capitalism.” Business Ethics Quarterly, New Approaches to Business Ethics, Special Issue: 3760.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brenkert, George G. 1995. “‘The Environment, The Moralist, The Corporation and Its Culture.’” Business Ethics Quarterly 5(4): 675–97. doi:10.2307/3857409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, Marilynn B. 1979. “In-Group Bias in the Minimal Intergroup Situation: A Cognitive-Motivational Analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 86(2): 307–24. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.86.2.307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brockner, Joel, and Rubin, Jeffrey Z. 1985. Entrapment in Escalating Conflicts. New York: Springer-Verlag. http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-1-4612-5072-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bryan, Christopher J., Adams, Gabrielle S., and Monin, Benoît. 2013. “When Cheating Would Make You a Cheater: Implicating the Self Prevents Unethical Behavior.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 142(4): 1001–5. doi:10.1037/a0030655.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chugh, Dolly, Bazerman, Max H., and Banaji, Mahzarin R. 2005. “Bounded Ethicality as a Psychological Barrier to Recognizing Conflicts of Interest.” In Conflicts of Interest: Challenges and Solutions in Business, Law, Medicine, and Public Policy, edited by Moore, Don A., Cain, Daylian M., Loewenstein, George, and Bazerman, Max H., 7495. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darley, John M., and Batson, C. Daniel. 1973. “‘From Jerusalem to Jericho’: A Study of Situational and Dispositional Variables in Helping Behavior.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 27(1): 100108. doi:10.1037/h0034449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dasgupta, Nilanjana. 2004. “Implicit Ingroup Favoritism, Outgroup Favoritism, and Their Behavioral Manifestations.” Social Justice Research 17(2): 143–69. doi:10.1023/B: SORE.0000027407.70241.15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donagan, Alan. 1979. The Theory of Morality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Donaldson, Thomas. 1989. The Ethics of International Business. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Donaldson, Thomas. 1994. “When Integration Fails: The Logic of Prescription and Description in Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 157–69. doi:10.2307/3857487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dressler, Joshua. 1987. “Reflections on Excusing Wrongdoers: Moral Theory, New Excuses and the Model Penal Code.” Rutgers Law Journal 19: 671.Google Scholar
Duska, Ronald F., and Duska, Brenda Shay. 2003. Accounting Ethics. Foundations of Business Ethics 2. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Epley, Nicholas, and Caruso, Eugene M. 2004. “Egocentric Ethics.” Social Justice Research 17(2): 171–87. doi:10.1023/B:SORE.0000027408.72713.45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feather, N. T., and Simon, J. G. 1971. “Causal Attributions for Success and Failure in Relation to Expectations of Success Based upon Selective or Manipulative Control.” Journal of Personality 39(4): 527–41. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6494.1971.tb00060.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feinberg, Joel. 1965. “The Expressive Function of Punishment.” The Monist 49(3): 397423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gino, Francesca, Moore, Don A., and Bazerman, Max H. 2008. “See No Evil: When We Overlook Other People’s Unethical Behavior.” SSRN Scholarly Paper ID 1079969. Rochester, NY: Social Science Research Network. http://papers.ssrn.com/abstract=1079969.Google Scholar
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. 2010. “Corporate Responsibility and Its Constituents.” In The Oxford Handbook of Business Ethics, edited by Brenkert, George G. and Beauchamp, Tom L., 126–57. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. 2011. “Goods That Are Truly Good and Services That Truly Serve: Reflections on ‘Caritas in Veritate.’” Journal of Business Ethics 100 (S1): 916.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Green, Alexander R., Carney, Dana R., Pallin, Daniel J., Ngo, Long H., Raymond, Kristal L., Iezzoni, Lisa I., and Banaji, Mahzarin R. 2007. “Implicit Bias among Physicians and Its Prediction of Thrombolysis Decisions for Black and White Patients.” Journal of General Internal Medicine 22(9): 1231–38. doi:10.1007/s11606-007-0258-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenwald, Anthony G., Poehlman, T. Andrew, Uhlmann, Eric Luis, and Banaji, Mahzarin R. 2009. “Understanding and Using the Implicit Association Test: III. Meta-Analysis of Predictive Validity.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 97(1): 1741. doi:10.1037/a0015575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, James. 1992. “The Human Good and the Ambitions of Consequentialism.” Social Philosophy and Policy 9(02): 118–32. doi:10.1017/S0265052500001436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Griffin, James. 1996. Value Judgement: Improving Our Ethical Beliefs. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Haines, Nicolas. 1972. “Ought and Can.” Philosophy 47(181): 263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, Jeffrey S., and Wicks, Andrew C. 2013. “Stakeholder Theory, Value, and Firm Performance.” Business Ethics Quarterly 23(1): 97124. doi:10.5840/beq20132314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holroyd, Jules. 2015. “Implicit Bias, Awareness and Imperfect Cognitions.” Consciousness and Cognition 33 (May): 511–23. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2014.08.024.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jones, Thomas M., and Felps, Will. 2013. “Shareholder Wealth Maximization and Social Welfare: A Utilitarian Critique.” Business Ethics Quarterly 23(2): 207–38. doi:10.5840/beq201323215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1996a. The Metaphysics of Morals. Edited by Gregor, Mary J.. 2nd edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1996b. Practical Philosophy. Edited by Gregor, Mary J. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel. 1999. Critique of Pure Reason. Edited and translated by Guyer, Paul and Wood, Allen W. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kim, Tae Wan. 2014. “Decent Termination: A Moral Case for Severance Pay.” Business Ethics Quarterly 24(2): 203–27. doi:10.5840/beq20145278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levy, David. 2008. “Ought Implies Can.” Edited by Kolb, Robert W. Encyclopedia of Business Ethics and Society. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
Levy, Neil. 2014. “Consciousness, Implicit Attitudes and Moral Responsibility.” Noûs 48(1): 2140. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0068.2011.00853.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewenstein, George, and Thaler, Richard H. 1989. “Anomalies: Intertemporal Choice.” The Journal of Economic Perspectives 3(4): 181–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, Edouard. 2010. “The Bleak Implications of Moral Psychology.” Neuroethics 3(3): 223–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, John J. 2001. “Employee Voice in Corporate Governance: A Defense of Strong Participation Rights.” Business Ethics Quarterly 11(1): 195213. doi:10.2307/3857877.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCall, John J. 2003. “A Defense of Just Cause Dismissal Rules.” Business Ethics Quarterly 13(2): 151–75. doi:10.5840/beq200313211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milgram, Stanley. 1974. Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
Moore, Don A., Tanlu, Lloyd, and Bazerman, Max H. 2010. “Conflict of Interest and the Intrusion of Bias.” Judgment and Decision Making 5(1): 3753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Phillips, Robert A. 2010. “Ethics and Network Organizations.” Business Ethics Quarterly 20(3): 533–43. doi:10.5840/beq201020333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prentice, Robert. 2014. “Bounded Ethicality.” Ethics Unwrapped. http://ethicsunwrapped.utexas.edu/video/bounded-ethicality.Google Scholar
Radin, Tara J., and Werhane, Patricia H. 2003. “Employment-at-Will, Employee Rights, and Future Directions for Employment.” Business Ethics Quarterly 13(2): 113–30. doi:10.5840/beq200313212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeves, Arin N. 2014. “Written in Black & White: Exploring Confirmation Bias in Racialized Perceptions of Writing Skills.” Yellow Paper Series. Chicago, IL: Nextions LLC. http://www.nextions.com/wp-content/files_mf/13972237592014040114WritteninBlackandWhiteYPS.pdf.Google Scholar
Robertson, Diana C. 1993. “Empiricism in Business Ethics: Suggested Research Directions.” Journal of Business Ethics 12(8): 585–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Paul H. 2009. “A System of Excuses: How Criminal Law’s Excuse Defenses Do, and Don’t, Work Together to Exculpate Blameless (and Only Blameless) Offenders.” Texas Tech Law Review 42: 259.Google Scholar
Ross, Lee. 1977. “The Intuitive Psychologist and His Shortcomings: Distortions in the Attribution Process.” In Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, edited by Berkowitz, Leonard, 10:174221. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Ross, Lee, Greene, David, and House, Pamela. 1977. “The ‘false Consensus Effect’: An Egocentric Bias in Social Perception and Attribution Processes.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13(3): 279301. doi:10.1016/0022-1031(77)90049-X.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rudman, Laurie A., and Ashmore, Richard D. 2007. “Discrimination and the Implicit Association Test.” Group Processes & Intergroup Relations 10(3): 359–72. doi:10.1177/1368430207078696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saul, Jennifer. 2013. “Implicit Bias, Stereotype Threat, and Women in Philosophy.” In Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change?, edited by Jenkins, Fiona and Hutchison, Katrina, 3960. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schreck, Philipp, van Aaken, Dominik, and Donaldson, Thomas. 2013.“Positive Economics and the Normativistic Fallacy: Bridging the Two Sides of CSR.” Business Ethics Quarterly 23(2): 297329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steinpreis, Rhea E., Anders, Katie A., and Ritzke, Dawn. 1999. “The Impact of Gender on the Reveiw of the Curricula Vitae of Job Applicants and Tenure Candidates: A National Empirical Study.” Sex Roles 41 (7/8): 509–428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stern, Robert. 2004. “Does ‘Ought’ Imply ‘Can’? And Did Kant Think It Does?” Utilitas 16(01): 4261. doi:10.1017/S0953820803001055.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenbrunsel, Ann E. 2005. “Commentary: Bounded Ethicality and Conflicts of Interest.” In Conflicts of Interest: Challenges and Solutions in Business, Law, Medicine, and Public Policy, edited by Moore, Don A., Cain, Daylian M., Loewenstein, George, and Bazerman, Max H., 96103. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenbrunsel, Ann E., and Smith‐Crowe, Kristin. 2008. “Ethical Decision Making: Where We’ve Been and Where We’re Going.” The Academy of Management Annals 2(1): 545607. doi:10.1080/19416520802211677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Treviño, Linda K., and Weaver, Gary R. 1994. “Business ETHICS/BUSINESS Ethics: One Field or Two?” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 113–28. doi:10.2307/3857484.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Treviño, Linda K., Weaver, Gary R., and Reynolds, Scott J. 2006. “Behavioral Ethics in Organizations: A Review.” Journal of Management 32(6): 951–90. doi:10.1177/0149206306294258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vohs, Kathleen D., and Schooler, Jonathan W. 2008. “The Value of Believing in Free Will: Encouraging a Belief in Determinism Increases Cheating.” Psychological Science 19(1): 4954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vranas, Peter B. M. 2007. “I Ought, Therefore I Can.” Philosophical Studies 136(2): 167216. doi:10.1007/s11098-007-9071-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weaver, Gary R., and Treviño, Linda K. 1994. “Normative And Empirical Business Ethics: Separation, Marriage Of Convenience, Or Marriage Of Necessity?” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 129–43. doi:10.2307/3857485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Werhane, Patricia H. 1994. “The Normative/Descriptive Distinction in Methodologies of Business Ethics.” Business Ethics Quarterly 4(2): 175–80. doi:10.2307/3857489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar