Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T22:14:59.132Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

SEALING OF THE UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 July 2021

GRIGOR SARGSYAN
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS RUTGERS UNIVERSITYNEW BRUNSWICK, NJ, USAE-mail: gs481@math.rutgers.edu
NAM TRANG
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS UNIVERSITY OF NORTH TEXASDENTON, TX, USAE-mail: Nam.Trang@unt.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

A set of reals is universally Baire if all of its continuous preimages in topological spaces have the Baire property. ${\sf Sealing}$ is a type of generic absoluteness condition introduced by Woodin that asserts in strong terms that the theory of the universally Baire sets cannot be changed by set forcings. The ${\sf Largest\ Suslin\ Axiom}$ ( ${\sf LSA}$ ) is a determinacy axiom isolated by Woodin. It asserts that the largest Suslin cardinal is inaccessible for ordinal definable surjections. Let ${\sf LSA}$ - ${\sf over}$ - ${\sf uB}$ be the statement that in all (set) generic extensions there is a model of $\sf {LSA}$ whose Suslin, co-Suslin sets are the universally Baire sets. We outline the proof that over some mild large cardinal theory, $\sf {Sealing}$ is equiconsistent with $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ . In fact, we isolate an exact theory (in the hierarchy of strategy mice) that is equiconsistent with both (see Definition 3.1). As a consequence, we obtain that $\sf {Sealing}$ is weaker than the theory “ $\sf {ZFC}$ + there is a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals.” This significantly improves upon the earlier consistency proof of $\sf {Sealing}$ by Woodin. A variation of $\sf {Sealing}$ , called $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ , is also shown to be equiconsistent with $\sf {Sealing}$ over the same large cardinal theory. We also outline the proof that if V has a proper class of Woodin cardinals, a strong cardinal, and a generically universally Baire iteration strategy, then $\sf {Sealing}$ holds after collapsing the successor of the least strong cardinal to be countable. This result is complementary to the aforementioned equiconsistency result, where it is shown that $\sf {Sealing}$ holds in a generic extension of a certain minimal universe. This theorem is more general in that no minimal assumption is needed. A corollary of this is that $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ is not equivalent to $\sf {Sealing}$ .

Type
Articles
Copyright
© 2021, Association for Symbolic Logic

We identify elements of the Baire space $\omega ^{\omega }$ with reals. Throughout the paper, by a “set of reals A,” we mean $A\subseteq \omega ^{\omega }$ . Given a cardinal $\kappa $ , we say $T\subseteq \bigcup _{n<\omega } \omega ^n \times \kappa ^n$ is a tree on $\omega \times \kappa $ if T is closed under initial segments. Given a tree T on $\omega \times \kappa $ , we let $[T]$ be the set of its branches, i.e., $b\in [T]$ if $b\in \omega ^{\omega }\times \kappa ^{\omega }$ and letting $b=(b_0, b_1)$ , for each $n\in \omega $ , $(b_0\restriction n, b_1\restriction n)\in T$ . We then let $p[T]=\{ x\in \omega ^{\omega }: \exists f((x, f)\in [T])\}$ . A set of reals A is $\gamma$ -universally Baire if there are trees $T,U$ on $\omega \times \lambda $ for some $\lambda $ such that $A = p[T] = \mathbb {R}\backslash p[U]$ and whenever g is $< \gamma $ -generic (i.e., g is V-generic for some forcing $\mathbb {P}\in V$ such that $|\mathbb {P}|<\gamma $ ), in $V[g]$ , $p[T] = \mathbb {R}\backslash p[U]$ . We write $A^g$ for $p[T]^{V[g]}$ ; this is the canonical interpretation of A in $V[g]$ .Footnote 1 A is universally Baire if A is $\gamma $ -universally Baire for all $\gamma $ . Let $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ be the set of universally Baire sets. Given a generic g, we let $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g=(\Gamma ^{\infty })^{V[g]}$ and ${\mathbb {R}}_g={\mathbb {R}}^{V[g]}$ . The notion of universal Baireness was first isolated and studied in [Reference Feng, Magidor and Woodin1].Footnote 2 A proper class of Woodin cardinals is typically assumed when studying universally Baire sets as it ensures $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ behaves nicely, e.g., $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ is closed under real quantifiers, continuous substitutions, and any two sets in $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ are Wadge comparable under this assumption.

The discovery of forcing almost immediately initiated the study of removing independence phenomena from set theory. Large cardinals were used to establish a plethora of results that generalize Shoenfield’s Absoluteness Theorem to more complex formulas than $\Sigma ^1_2$ . $\sf {Sealing}$ is perhaps the strongest generalization of Shoenfield’s Absoluteness Theorem one could hope for.

Definition 0.1. Woodin

$\sf {Sealing}$ is the conjunction of the following statements.

  1. 1. For every set generic g, $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, \mathbb {R}_g)\vDash \sf {AD}^+$ and ${\wp }({\mathbb {R}}_g)\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g, \mathbb {R}_g)=\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ .

  2. 2. For every set generic g over V, and for every set generic h over $V[g]$ , there is an elementary embedding

    $$ \begin{align*} j: L(\Gamma^{\infty}_g, \mathbb{R}_g)\rightarrow L(\Gamma^{\infty}_{g*h}, \mathbb{R}_{g*h}), \end{align*} $$

such that for every $A\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ , $j(A)=A^{h}.$

Woodin showed that if A is a universally Baire set of reals and the universe has a proper class of Woodin cardinals then the theory of $L(A, {\mathbb {R}})$ cannot be changed by set forcings. He achieved this by showing that if there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals then for any universally Baire set A and any two successive set generic extensions $V[g]\subseteq V[h]$ , there is an elementary embedding $j:L(A_g, {\mathbb {R}}_g)\rightarrow L(A_h, {\mathbb {R}}_h)$ . Under the stated large cardinal assumption, all $\Sigma ^1_2$ sets of reals are universally Baire. In fact, the largest class of sets of reals for which a Shoenfield-type generic absoluteness can hold is the collection of the universally Baire sets in the sense that if sufficient generic absoluteness is true about a set of reals then that set is universally Baire. More precisely, suppose $\phi $ is a property of reals. Let $A_{\phi }$ be the set of reals defined by $\phi $ . If sufficiently many statements about $A_{\phi }$ are generically absolute then it is because $A_{\phi }$ is universally Baire (see [Reference Steel24, Lemma 4.1]). Thus, the next place to look for absoluteness is the set of all universally Baire sets.

The existence of a proper class of Woodin cardinals does not imply $\sf {Sealing}$ . In fact, in the minimal mouse with a proper class of Woodin cardinals, clause (1) of $\sf {Sealing}$ fails. Woodin [Reference Neeman11] has shown that assuming there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and a supercompact cardinal, and letting $\delta $ be a supercompact cardinal, then in $V^{Coll(\omega ,V_{\delta +1})}$ , $\sf {Sealing}$ holds. Theorem 1.1 shows that $\sf {Sealing}$ ’s consistency strength is below that of the existence of a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals, i.e., within the short extender region. The proof of this fact is beyond the scope of this paper; roughly, it follows from recent unpublished work of the first author, which shows that excellent hybrid mice, defined in Definition 3.1, exist, assuming the existence of divergent models of $\sf {AD}^+$ ; and the latter is consistent relative to the existence of a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals.Footnote 3 Therefore, $\sf {Sealing}$ is not a strong consequence of supercompactness as suggested by Woodin’s theorem.

Recent works [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18, Reference Steel20] suggest that $\sf {Sealing}$ has significant impacts on various aspects of inner model theory and the inner model program. A more detailed discussion of these connections is given in [Reference Steel20].

To introduce $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ , we first need to introduce the $\sf {Largest\ Suslin} {\sf Axiom} \ (\sf {LSA})$ . A cardinal $\kappa $ is $\sf {OD}$ -inaccessible if for every $\alpha <\kappa $ there is no surjection $f: {\wp }(\alpha )\rightarrow \kappa $ that is definable from ordinal parameters. A set of reals $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}$ is $\kappa $ -Suslin if for some tree T on $\omega \times \kappa $ , $A=p[T]$ . A set A is Suslin if it is $\kappa $ -Suslin for some $\kappa $ ; A is co-Suslin if its complement $\mathbb {R}\backslash A$ is Suslin. A set A is Suslin, co-Suslin if both A and its complement are Suslin. A cardinal $\kappa $ is a Suslin cardinal if there is a set of reals A such that A is $\kappa $ -Suslin but A is not $\lambda $ -Suslin for any $\lambda <\kappa $ . Suslin cardinals play an important role in the study of models of determinacy (see for example, various articles from the Cabal Volumes: [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel4Reference Martin and Steel10]).

The $\sf {Largest\ Suslin\ Axiom}$ was introduced by Woodin in [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel2, Remark 9.28]. The terminology is due to the first author. Here is the definition.

Definition 0.2. The $\sf {Largest\ Suslin\ Axiom}$ , abbreviated as $\sf {LSA}$ , is the conjunction of the following statements $:$

  1. 1. $\sf {AD}^+$ .

  2. 2. There is a largest Suslin cardinal.

  3. 3. The largest Suslin cardinal is $\sf {OD}$ -inaccessible.

In the hierarchy of determinacy axioms, which one may appropriately call the $\sf {Solovay\ Hierarchy}$ ,Footnote 4 $\sf {LSA}$ is an anomaly as it belongs to the successor stage of the $\sf {Solovay\ Hierarchy}$ but does not conform to the general norms of the successor stages of the $\sf {Solovay\ Hierarchy}$ . $\sf {LSA}$ is a very strong determinacy axiom; for example, it implies there are models of “ $\sf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}} + \Theta $ is regular.” Prior to [Reference Steel21], $\sf {LSA}$ was not known to be consistent. In [Reference Steel21], the first author showed that it is consistent relative to a Woodin cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals. Nowadays, the axiom plays a key role in many aspects of inner model theory, and features prominently in Woodin’s $\sf {Ultimate\ L}$ framework (see [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel3, Definition 7.14] and Axiom I and Axiom II on page 97 of [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel3]Footnote 5 ).

Definition 0.3. Let $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ be the statement $:$ For all V-generic g, in $V[g]$ , there is $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}_g$ such that $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_g)\vDash \sf {LSA}$ and $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ is the Suslin, co-Suslin sets of $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ .

$\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ is isolated by the authors in [Reference Steel20] as part of the consistency calculations of $\sf {Sealing}$ . $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ plays a role in clarifying relationships between strong forcing axioms such as Martin’s Maximum ( $\sf {MM}$ ) and variations of Woodin’s $(*)$ -axiom. For example, Woodin has observed, after the second author’s talk on the topic of $\sf {Sealing}$ at the XVI International Workshop in Set Theory at CIRM, Luminy, that assuming there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals, then $\sf {MM + LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {UB}$ implies $(*)^{++}$ fails, where $(*)^{++}$ , which says that ${\wp }(\mathbb {R})$ belongs to a $\mathbb {P}_{\textrm {max}}$ -extension of a determinacy model containing all reals and ordinals, is a strengthening of $(*)$ , which says that ${\wp }(\omega _1)$ belongs to a $\mathbb {P}_{\textrm {max}}$ -extension of $L(\mathbb {R})$ , the minimal model of determinacy containing all reals and ordinals. This suggests that $\sf {MM}^{++}$ cannot imply $(*)^{++}$ , in contrast to a recent result of Aspero and Schindler that $\sf {MM}^{++}$ implies $(*)$ .

1 The consistency of $\sf {Sealing}$

The following is our main theorem. We say that $\phi $ and $\psi $ are equiconsistent over theory T if there is a model of $T\cup \{\phi \}$ if and only if there is a model of $T\cup \{\psi \}$ .

Theorem 1.1 [Reference Steel20]. $\sf {Sealing}$ and $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ are equiconsistent over “there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary.”

The following variation of $\sf {Sealing}$ , called $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ , is a stronger statement than the version isolated by Woodin [Reference Neeman11]. $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ turns out to be equiconsistent with $\sf {Sealing}$ and $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ over the base theory of Theorem 1.1.

Definition 1.2. $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ is the conjunction of $:$

  1. 1. For any set generic g, $L(\Gamma^\infty_g,\mathbb{R}_g)\hspace{-1pt} \vDash\hspace{-1pt} \sf {AD}^+$ , and $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g\hspace{-1pt} =\hspace{-1pt} {\wp }(\mathbb {R})\hspace{-1pt}\cap\hspace{-1pt} L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g)$ .

  2. 2. There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and for any set generic g, in $V[g]$ , suppose $\delta $ is Woodin, whenever G is $V[g]$ -generic for either the $\mathbb {P}_{<\delta }$ -stationary tower or the $\mathbb {Q}_{<\delta }$ -stationary tower at $\delta $ , then

    $$\begin{align*}j(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g) = \Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*G},\end{align*} $$
    where $j: V[g] \rightarrow M \subset V[g*G]$ is the generic elementary embedding given by G.

Woodin has observed that assuming a proper class of Woodin cardinals which are limits of strong cardinals, $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ implies $\sf {Sealing}$ . The converse is not known. However, we can show the following theorem.

Theorem 1.3 [Reference Steel20]. $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ and $\sf {Sealing}$ are equiconsistent over “there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary.”

Woodin, in [Reference Neeman11], shows $\sf {Sealing}$ and a weak form of $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ are consistent relative to the existence of a supercompact cardinal and a proper class of Woodin cardinals. As explained above, a corollary of the theorems above, and recent work in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang16, Reference Hugh Woodin26], is the following theorem, which significantly improves Woodin’s theorem. Throughout this paper, we let $\sf {WLW}$ denote the theory “ $\sf {ZFC}$ + there is a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals.”

Theorem 1.4. Con $(\sf {WLW})$ implies Con $(\sf {Sealing} + \sf {Tower \ Sealing})$ .

In fact, the proof Theorem 1.4 shows that in a generic extension of an excellent hybrid mouse (cf. Definition 3.1), both $\sf {Sealing}$ and $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ hold. As mentioned in the introduction, the consistency of the existence of an excellent hybrid mouse follows from Con $(\sf {WLW})$ .

2 Self-iterability and $\sf {Sealing}$

Next, we state another theorem about the consistency of $\sf {Sealing}$ that implies $\sf {Sealing}$ and $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ are not equivalent. The Unique Branch Hypothesis ( $\textsf {UBH}$ ) is the statement that every normal iteration tree ${\mathcal {T}}$ on V has at most one cofinal well-founded branch. The Generic Unique Branch Hypothesis ( $\sf {gUBH}$ ) says that $\sf {UBH}$ holds in all set generic extensions. The notions of a pre-iterable structure and a generically universally Baire (guB) strategy are discussed in detail in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18, Section 1].

Suppose P is a transitive model of set theory. We let ${\sf {ile}}(P)$ be the set of inaccessible-length extenders of P. More precisely $\sf {ile}(P)$ consists of extenders $E\in P$ such that $P\vDash ``lh(E)$ is inaccessible and $V_{lh(E)}=V_{lh(E)}^{Ult(V, E)}$ ,” where $lh(E)$ is the length of the extender E.

Definition 2.1. We say that self-iterability holds if the following holds in V.

  1. 1. $\sf {gUBH}$ .

  2. 2. ${\mathcal {V}}=(V, {\sf {ile}}(V))$ is a pre-iterable structure that has a guB-iteration strategy.

The notions in Definition 2.1 abstract some of the essential properties of universally Baire strategies of fine-structural extender models that we need for the proof of the following theorem.

Theorem 2.2 [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18]. Assume self-iterability holds, and suppose there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and a strong cardinal. Let $\kappa $ be the least strong cardinal of V and let $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , \kappa ^+)$ be V-generic. Then $V[g]\vDash \sf {Sealing}$ .

Remark 2.3.

  1. (i) Normal iteration trees on $\mathcal {V}$ are coarse and are plus-2 trees in the sense of [Reference Sargsyan12]. However, the hypothesis of Theorem 2.2 cannot be weakened to just $\sf {gUBH}$ for plus-2 iterations as this form of $\sf {UBH}$ holds in a minimal mouse with a strong cardinal, a class of Woodin cardinals and a stationary class of measurable cardinals,Footnote 6 but this theory is weaker than $\sf {Sealing}$ as shown by the proof of Theorem 1.1.

  2. (ii) We note that there is no anti-large cardinal assumption in Theorem 2.2. Contrast this with the situation in the previous section, where $\sf {Sealing}$ is shown to hold in a generic extension of a minimal universe of a certain theory $($ i.e., the universe of a minimal excellent hybrid mouse, see Definition 3.1 $)$ .

  3. (iii) The proof of Theorem 2.2 is accessible to those with general knowledge of iterations, iteration strategies, and Woodin”s extender algebra, all of which are topics that can be presented without any fine structure theory.

Recall from [Reference Hugh Woodin26] the statement of Hod Pair Capturing $(\sf {HPC})$ : For any Suslin, co-Suslin set $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}$ , there is a least-branch (lbr) hod pair $({\mathcal {P} },\Sigma )$ such that A is definable from parameters over $(HC,\in , \Sigma )$ . No Long Extender $(\sf {NLE})$ is the statement: there is no countable, $\omega _1+1$ -iterable pure extender premouse M such that there is a long extender on the M-sequence. The notion of least-branch hod mice (lbr hod mice) is defined precisely in [Reference Hugh Woodin26, Section 5].

Definition 2.4. $\sf {gHPC}$ is the statement $:$ suppose $V[g]$ is a set generic extension of V, suppose in $V[g]$ , $M = L(\Gamma ,\mathbb {R})$ is a model of $\sf {AD}^+$ , then $M\vDash \sf {HPC}$ .

Theorem 2.5 [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18]. Suppose self-iterability holds and there is a proper class of inaccessible cardinals which are limit of Woodin cardinals. Suppose $\sf {gHPC}$ and $\sf {NLE}$ hold. Then $V\vDash \sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ fails.

Remark 2.6.

  1. (i) The proof of this theorem is given in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18, Section 7]. One shows that letting $\lambda $ be an inaccessible cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega ,<\lambda )$ be V-generic, then in $V[g]$ , there cannot be a set $A\subset \mathbb {R}$ such that $L(A,\mathbb {R})\vDash \sf {LSA}$ and $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ is the Suslin–co-Suslin sets of $L(A,\mathbb {R})$ .

  2. (ii) The hypotheses of Theorem 2.5 hold in the universe of lbr hod mice that have a proper class of inaccessible cardinals which are limit of Woodin cardinals $($ cf. [Reference Steel23, Theorem 3.3] and [Reference Hugh Woodin26] $)$ . So such hod mice satisfy “ $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ fails.”

Remark 2.6, Theorem 2.5, and the fact that self-iterability and $\sf {gHPC}$ hold in any generic extension of an lbr hod mouse with a proper class of Woodin cardinals give us the following.

Corollary 2.7 [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18]. Let V be the universe of an lbr hod mouse with a proper class of inaccessible cardinals which are limit of Woodin cardinals and a strong cardinal. Let $\kappa $ be the least strong cardinal of V and $g\subseteq Coll(\omega ,\kappa ^+)$ be V-generic. Then $V[g] \vDash “\sf {Sealing}$ holds and $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ fails.”

Corollary 2.7 is surprising and unexpected in light of the above results. For example, generic absoluteness for $L({\mathbb {R}})$ , namely, for all successive generics g and h, there is an elementary embedding $j:L({\mathbb {R}}_g)\rightarrow L({\mathbb {R}}_{g*h})$ , is equivalent to the existence and the universal Baireness of the next canonical set beyond $L({\mathbb {R}})$ , namely ${\mathbb {R}}^{\#}$ .Footnote 7 While one cannot hope that $\sf {Sealing}$ would imply both the existence and the universal Baireness of the next canonical set of reals beyond $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ ,Footnote 8 one could still hope that the cause of $\sf {Sealing}$ is the existence of some nice set of reals just like the cause of the generic absoluteness of $L({\mathbb {R}})$ is the universal Baireness of ${\mathbb {R}}^{\#}$ .Footnote 9 Because the next nice set beyond $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ cannot be universally Baire, the best we can hope for is that the next set beyond $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ creates an $\sf {LSA}$ model over $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ . In fact, this discussion was the original motivation for isolating $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {UB}$ . Contrary to our expectations, what causes $\sf {Sealing}$ to hold may not be coded into a set of reals as demonstrated by Corollary 2.7.

3 Outline of proofs

We first give a brief outline of the proofs of Theorems 1.1 and 1.3. The crucial notion involved in these proofs is that of an excellent hybrid premouse, which is a kind of short-tree strategy hybrid premice, where the short-tree strategy is that of an lsa hod premouse. The notions of lsa hod premice and their short-tree strategies are crucial for the analysis of models of $\sf {LSA}$ and are treated in detail in [Reference Steel21]. Roughly an lsa hod premouse ${\mathcal {P} }$ is a hod premouse with the largest Woodin cardinal $\delta ^{\mathcal {P} }$ , ${\mathcal {P} } = ({\mathcal {P} }|\delta ^{\mathcal {P} })^{\sharp }$ , and letting $\kappa $ be the least $<\delta ^{\mathcal {P} }$ -strong cardinal in ${\mathcal {P} }$ , then $\kappa $ is a limit of Woodin cardinals. If $\Sigma $ is an iteration strategy of ${\mathcal {P} }$ , then the short part $\Sigma ^{sh}$ of $\Sigma $ is the part of $\Sigma $ that acts on short trees according to $\Sigma $ , so $\Sigma ^{sh}({\mathcal {T}})$ is defined and is $\Sigma ({\mathcal {T}})$ if and only if ${\mathcal {T}}$ is short.Footnote 10 We say that $({\mathcal {P} },\Lambda )$ is a short-tree strategy (sts) hod pair if ${\mathcal {P} }$ is an lsa hod premouse and $\Lambda $ is a short-tree strategy of ${\mathcal {P} }$ . If ${\mathcal { Q}}$ is a $\Lambda $ -premouse above ${\mathcal {P} }$ , then we say that ${\mathcal { Q}}$ is an sts premouse based on ${\mathcal {P} }$ .Footnote 11

Suppose $({\mathcal {P} }, \Lambda )$ is an sts hod pair, where $\Lambda $ has hull condensation and strong branch condensation (see [Reference Steel21] for a detailed discussion of these notions). $\Lambda $ has branch condensation for pullbacks if whenever $\pi :{\mathcal { Q}}\rightarrow {\mathcal {P} }$ is elementary, the $\pi $ -pullback of $\Lambda $ has branch condensation. For a more detailed discussion of these topics, see [Reference Sargsyan15, Reference Steel20, Reference Steel21].

We say that $[\nu , \delta ]$ is a window if there are no Woodin cardinals in the interval $(\nu , \delta )$ . Given a window w, we let $\nu ^w$ and $\delta ^w$ be such that $w=[\nu ^w, \delta ^w]$ . We say that window w is above $\kappa $ if $\nu ^w\geq \kappa $ . Suppose $\kappa $ is a cardinal. We say window-based self-iterability $(\sf {WBSI})$ holds at $\kappa $ if for any window w that is above $\kappa $ and for any successor cardinal $\eta \in (\nu ^w, \delta ^w)$ , setting $Q= H_{\eta ^+}$ , Q has an $Ord$ -iteration strategy $\Sigma $ which acts on iterations that only use extenders with critical points $>\nu ^w$ .

Definition 3.1. Suppose ${\mathcal {P} }$ is hybrid premouse. We say that ${\mathcal {P} }$ is excellent if

  1. 1. ${\mathcal {P} }\vDash T_0$ , where $T_0$ says “ $\sf {ZFC}$ + There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals + the class of measurable cardinals is stationary + no measurable cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals carries a normal ultrafilter concentrating on the set of measurable cardinals.”

  2. 2. There is a Woodin cardinal $\delta $ of ${\mathcal {P} }$ such that ${\mathcal {P} }\vDash ``{\mathcal {P} }_0=_{\textit{def}}({\mathcal {P} }|\delta )^{{\#}}$ is a hod premouse of lsa type,” ${\mathcal {P} }$ is an sts premouse based on ${\mathcal {P} }_0$ and ${\mathcal {P} }\vDash ``S^{\mathcal {P} }$ , which is a short tree strategy for ${\mathcal {P} }_0$ , has hull condensation, strong branch condensation, and branch condensation for pull-backs.”

  3. 3. Given any $\tau <\delta ^{{\mathcal {P} }_0}$ such that $({\mathcal {P} }_0|\tau )^{{\#}}$ is of lsa type, there is ${\mathcal {M}}\lhd {\mathcal {P} }$ such that $\tau $ is a cut point of ${\mathcal {M}}$ and ${\mathcal {M}}\vDash ``\tau $ is not a Woodin cardinal.”

  4. 4. Letting $\delta $ be as above, ${\mathcal {P} }\vDash ``\sf {WBSI}$ holds at $\delta $ .”

If ${\mathcal {P} }$ is excellent then we let $\delta ^{\mathcal {P} }$ be the $\delta $ of clause 2 above and ${\mathcal {P} }_0=(({\mathcal {P} }|\delta ^{\mathcal {P} })^{\#})^{\mathcal {P} }$ .Footnote 12

For one direction of Theorems 1.1 and 1.3, assume the existence of an excellent hybrid premouse ${\mathcal {P} }$ . Let $\delta = \delta ^{\mathcal {P} }$ , $\kappa $ be the least $<\delta $ -strong cardinal in ${\mathcal {P} }_0$ , and $g\subset Coll(\omega ,\delta )$ be ${\mathcal {P} }$ -generic. Then one can show in ${\mathcal {P} }[g]$ , $\sf {Sealing}$ , $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ , and $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ hold. We give a sketch of $\sf {Sealing}$ holds; the reader can consult [Reference Steel20, Section 3] for a detailed proof. Let $\Lambda $ be the short-tree strategy of ${\mathcal {P} }_0$ coded by $S^{\mathcal {P} }$ . The smallness assumptions in clause (1) of Definition 3.1 amongst other things imply that all local non-Woodin cardinals of a hod premouse (or hybrid premouse) are witnessed by ${\mathcal { Q}}$ -structures which are initial segments of ${\mathcal {P} }$ and are tame. Clause (3) prevents us from constructing a “smaller” excellent hybrid premouse by performing certain fully backgrounded sts constructions over $({\mathcal {P} }_0|\tau )^{\sharp }$ inside ${\mathcal {P} }$ . Clauses (2) and (4) (combined with clause (1)) allow us to extend $\Lambda $ and the window-based strategy for ${\mathcal {P} }|\eta $ , where $\eta \in [\nu ^w, \delta ^w]$ and $[\nu ^w, \delta ^w]$ is a window above $\delta $ , to any set generic extension over ${\mathcal {P} }$ (cf. [Reference Steel20, Section 2]. Let h be a generic filter over ${\mathcal {P} }[g]$ and $\Lambda ^h$ be the interpretation of $\Lambda $ in ${\mathcal {P} }[g*h]$ . We then can “capture” $\Gamma ^{\infty }_{g*h}$ in the following sense: letting $\Delta ^h$ be the collection of $A\subseteq \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P} }[g*h]}$ in ${\mathcal {P} }[g*h]$ such that for some countable ${\mathcal {T}}$ according to $\Lambda ^h$ such that the iteration embedding restricted to ${\mathcal {P} }_0^b = ({\mathcal {P} }_0|(\kappa ^+)^{{\mathcal {P} }})$ exists, then

(1) $$ \begin{align} \Delta^h = \Gamma^{\infty}_{g*h}. \end{align} $$

[Reference Steel20, Lemma 3.3] shows that $L(\Delta ^h, \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P} }[g*h]})$ can be realized as the derived model of an iterate of ${\mathcal {P} }_0$ . The proof of [Reference Steel20, Lemma 3.3] and various lemmas in [Reference Steel20, Section 2] uses substantially the fact that window-based iterability in ${\mathcal {P} }$ and its generic extensions implies various backgrounded constructions in ${\mathcal {P} }$ and in its generic extensions converge. Equation (1) then implies clause (1) of $\sf {Sealing}$ . A standard argument (cf. [Reference Steel20, Lemma 3.4]) shows that for any generic filter k over ${\mathcal {P} }[g*h]$ , there is an elementary embedding $j: L(\Delta ^h, \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P} }[g*h]})\rightarrow L(\Delta ^{h*k}, \mathbb {R}^{{\mathcal {P} }[g*h*k]})$ such that for any $A\in \Delta ^h$ , $j(A) = A^{k}$ . This implies clause (2) of $\sf {Sealing}$ .

The proof of Theorem 2.2’s main idea is similar to the sketch above. The self-iterability hypothesis of the theorem for the most part allows us to simulate the proof sketched above. We can find a transitive model R Footnote 13 with sufficient iterability such that $H_{\kappa ^+}\subset R$ and there is an iterate S of R such that for some $\lambda $ , a limit of Woodin cardinals of S, for some S-generic $g\subseteq Coll(\omega , <\lambda )$ , letting $\mathbb {R}^*_g = \bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda } \mathbb {R}^{S[g \cap Coll(\omega , \alpha )]}$ , and $Hom^*_g$ be the collection of sets $A\in S(\mathbb {R}^*_g)\cap {\wp }(\mathbb {R})$ such that for some $\alpha <\lambda $ , there is a pair $(T, U)\in S[g\cap Coll(\omega , \alpha )]$ such that $S[g\cap Coll(\omega , \alpha )]\vDash ``(T, U)$ are $<\lambda $ -absolutely complementing trees” and $p[T]^{V({\mathbb {R}}^*)}=A$ , then we have the following:

  • $\mathbb {R}^*_g = \mathbb {R}^V$ .

  • $Hom^*_g = \Gamma ^{\infty }$ .

The fact that $\kappa $ is strong is used substantially in the proof of $Hom^*_g = \Gamma ^{\infty }$ above. $\sf {Sealing}$ holds in $V^{Coll(\omega ,\kappa ^+)}$ then follows by a standard argument. See [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18].

Now we sketch the proof of the other direction of Theorems 1.1 and 1.3. In particular, assuming $\sf {Sealing}$ (or $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ , or $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ ) and the large cardinal base theory of the theorems, we want to show that excellent hybrid premice exist. The proof of this occupies Sections 4–10 of [Reference Steel20] and involves many details and ideas. Many of these ideas, especially the notion of condensing sets and various hybrid (sts) backgrounded constructions, feature prominently in the HOD analysis of models of $\sf {LSA}$ as well as the core model induction proof that $\sf {LSA}$ is consistent relative to $\sf {PFA}$ (cf. [Reference Steel21]). The main thing we need to prove is: assuming no excellent hybrid premice exist, then certain hybrid (sts) fully backgrounded constructions converge (see [Reference Steel20, Sections 8–10]) to a model ${\mathcal {P} }$ , which turns out to be an excellent hybrid premouse. There are many consequences that we need from the hypothesis to guarantee the convergence of such constructions, but one main set of consequences is described in [Reference Steel20, Section 5]: there is a stationary class S of measurable cardinals $\mu $ which is a limit of Woodin cardinals, there is a $\nu < \textrm {min}(S)$ , and there are sequences $(Y_{\mu }: \mu \in S)$ , $(A_{\mu }: \mu \in S)$ such that the following hold for $\mu \in S$ :

  1. (i) letting $h\subset Coll(\omega , <\mu )$ be V-generic, then $Hom^*_h = \Gamma ^{\infty }_h$ ,

  2. (ii) $A_{\mu }\in Y_{\mu }$ and $A_{\mu }$ codes $H_{\mu }$ , and the hod limit of $L(Hom^*_h, \mathbb {R}^*_h)$ ,Footnote 14

  3. (iii) whenever $Y_{\mu } \subseteq X\prec H_{\mu ^+}$ and X has size $<\mu $ , is closed under $\nu $ -sequences, X captures Lp $^{cuB,\Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })$ in the sense that letting $\pi _X: M_X\rightarrow X$ be the uncollapse map, then $\pi _X^{-1}(Lp^{cuB,\Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })) = Lp^{cuB,\Lambda }(\pi _X^{-1}(A_{\mu }))$ , where $\Lambda $ is the $\pi _X$ -pullback strategy of $\Psi _{\mu }$ .Footnote 15

$\sf {Sealing}$ (or $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ , or $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}$ ) and the fact that $\mu $ is measurable can be used to show

$$ \begin{align*} \text{cof}(o(Lp^{cuB,\Psi_{\mu}}(A_{\mu}))) < \mu. \end{align*} $$

The significance of $\nu $ is that it is an ordinal that bounds cof $(o(Lp^{cuB,\Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })))$ for all $\mu \in S$ and $\nu $ is obtained from the usual Fodor’s argument applied to the (class) function $\mu \mapsto \textrm {cof}(o(Lp^{cuB,\Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })))$ ; this in turn allows us to “capture” $Lp^{cuB,\Psi _{\mu }}(A_{\mu })$ by a club of X as described in (iii) above. The reader can consult [Reference Steel20] for details on how these facts are put together into a proof of convergence of various hybrid fully backgrounded constructions.

4 Variations of $\sf {Sealing}$ and open problems

The rather mild assumption used in Theorems 1.1 and 1.3 that the class of measurable cardinals is stationary is probably not needed. As mentioned above, it is mainly used in [Reference Steel20, Section 5] to show that a certain (definable) regressive class function is constant on a stationary class of measurable cardinals. The existence of the ordinal $\nu $ above follows from this. We suspect that refinements of our techniques will eliminate this assumption. We conjecture the following.

Conjecture 4.1. The following theories are equiconsistent.

  1. 1. ${\sf {Sealing}}\ + $ “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.”

  2. 2. $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}\ + $ “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.”

  3. 3. ${\sf {Tower \ Sealing}}\ + $ “There is a proper class of Woodin cardinals.”

As discussed in [Reference Steel20], the core model induction becomes very difficult past $\sf {Sealing}$ . A good test problem for practitioners of the core model induction is the following problem.

Problem 4.2. Prove that Con $(\sf {PFA})$ implies Con $(\sf {WLW})$ .

We know from the results above that $\sf {WLW}$ is stronger than $\sf {Sealing}$ and is roughly the strongest natural theory at the limit of traditional methods for proving iterability. We believe it is plausible to develop core model induction methods for obtaining canonical models of $\sf {WLW}$ from just $\sf {PFA}$ .Footnote 16 The paper [Reference Sargsyan and Trang19] is the first step towards this goal; in the paper, we have constructed from $\sf {PFA}$ hod mice that are stronger than $\mathcal {P}$ in Definition 3.1.

The following are variations of the theories discussed above.

Definition 4.3. $\sf {Sealing}^+$ is the conjunction of $:$

  1. 1. For every set generic g over V, in $V[g]$ , ${\wp }(\mathbb {R}_g)\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g) = \Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ and $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g) \vDash ``{\sf {AD}_{\mathbb {R}}} + \Theta $ is regular.”

  2. 2. For every set generic g over V, and for every set generic h over $V[g]$ , in $V[g][h]$ , there is an elementary embedding

    $$ \begin{align*} j: L(\Gamma^{\infty}_g, \mathbb{R}_g)\rightarrow L(\Gamma^{\infty}_{g*h}, \mathbb{R}_{g*h}), \end{align*} $$
    such that for every $A\in \Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ , $j(A)=A^{h}.$

$\sf {Sealing^-}$ is the statement $:$ “For every set generic g over V, in $V[g]$ , $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g = {\wp }(\mathbb {R})\cap L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g)$ and there is no $\omega _1$ sequence of distinct reals in $L(\Gamma ^{\infty }_g,\mathbb {R}_g)$ .”

$\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}^-$ is the statement $:$ “For every set generic g over V, in $V[g]$ , there is $A\subseteq {\mathbb {R}}_g$ such that $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_g)\vDash \sf {LSA}$ and $\Gamma ^{\infty }_g$ is contained in $L(A, {\mathbb {R}}_g)$ .”

The proofs of Theorems 1.1 and 1.3 show the following. Let $T=``$ there exists a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary.” Then the following theories are equiconsistent:

  1. 1. $\sf {Sealing}+T$ .

  2. 2. $\sf {Sealing}^++T$ .

  3. 3. $\sf {Sealing}^- + T$ .

  4. 4. $\sf {Tower \ Sealing} + T$ .

  5. 5. $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}+T$ .

  6. 6. $\sf {LSA}$ - $\sf {over}$ - $\sf {uB}^-+T$ .

The following conjecture, if true, would be an ultimate analog of the main result of [Reference Steel22], which shows, assuming a proper class of measurable cardinals, the statement “ $\sf {AD}$ holds in $L(\mathbb {R})^{V^{\mathbb {P}}}$ for every poset $\mathbb {P}$ ” is equivalent to “for every poset $\mathbb {P}$ , $L(\mathbb {R})^{V^{\mathbb {P}}}\vDash $ there is no uncountable sequence of distinct reals.”

Conjecture 4.4. Suppose there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals and the class of measurable cardinals is stationary. Then the following are equivalent.

  1. 1. $\sf {Sealing}$ .

  2. 2. $\sf {Sealing}^+$ .

  3. 3. $\sf {Sealing}^{-}$ .

  4. 4. $\sf {Tower \ Sealing}$ .

We end this paper by the following question. In every known model of ${\sf {MM}} + $ there is a proper class of Woodin cardinals, $(*)^{++}$ fails.

Question 4.5.

  1. 1. Is $\sf {MM} + \sf {LSA}$ -over-UB consistent?

  2. 2. Is ${\sf {MM}} + (*)^{++}$ consistent?

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank the NSF for its generous support. The first author is supported by NSF Career Award DMS-1352034. The second author is supported by NSF Grants DMS-1565808 and DMS-1849295, and NSF Career Grant DMS-1945592. They would also like to thank the referee for a careful read of a previous version of the paper and for offering several helpful suggestions that improve the exposition.

Footnotes

1 One can show $A^g$ does not depend on the choice of $T,U$ .

2 One can find a proof that the two definitions of universal Baireness that we mention in this paper are equivalent.

3 Another outline of the proof that $\sf {Sealing}$ is consistent relative to the existence of a Woodin cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals is as follows. The existence of an lbr hod premouse ${\mathcal {P} }$ as in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang17, Theorem 1.2] follows from the existence of a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals by [Reference Sargsyan and Trang17, Step 4]. Then letting $\lambda _0$ be as in [Reference Sargsyan and Trang17, Theorem 1.2], ${\mathcal {P} }|\lambda _0$ satisfies the hypothesis of [Reference Sargsyan and Trang18, Theorem 0.4], which is Theorem 2.2 stated in this paper.

4 Solovay defined what is now called the $\sf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ (see [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel2, Definition 9.23]). It is a continuous sequence of ordinals with the largest element $\Theta $ , where $\Theta $ is the least ordinal that is not a surjective image of the reals. One then obtains a hierarchy of axioms by requiring that the $\sf {Solovay\ Sequence}$ has complex patterns. $\sf {LSA}$ is an axiom in this hierarchy. The reader may consult [Reference Sargsyan14] or [Reference Kechris, Löwe and Steel2, Remark 9.28].

5 The requirement in these axioms that there is a strong cardinal which is a limit of Woodin cardinals is only possible if $L(A, {\mathbb {R}})\vDash \sf {LSA}$ .

6 This fact is due to Steel (see [Reference Steel23, Theorem 3.3]).

7 This fact is due to Steel and Woodin. For example, see genericity iterations in [Reference Hugh Woodin25].

8 As all universally Baire sets are already in $\Gamma ^{\infty }$ .

9 Or rather the universal Baireness of the $\omega _1$ -iteration strategy of ${\mathcal {M}}_{\omega }^{\#}$ .

10 One can let $\Sigma ^{sh}({\mathcal {T}})$ be undefined or be equal to ${\mathcal {M}}({\mathcal {T}})^{\sharp }$ as in [Reference Steel21]. One major technical challenge of analyzing the HOD of the minimal model of $\sf {LSA}$ is to define short tree strategies without having the full strategies available and indexing short trees in lsa hod mice. See [Reference Steel21] for more details.

11 Again, the reader can consult [Reference Steel21] for details on how to index short trees and the ${\mathcal { Q}}$ -structure authentication procedure in ${\mathcal { Q}}$ . This is one major technical advance that [Reference Steel21] contributes to the study of hod mice.

12 We allow for the possibility that an excellent hybrid premouse is a proper class.

13 R can be taken to be the transitive collapse of a sufficiently elementary substructure of $V_{\xi }$ , for some large, regular cardinal $\xi $ .

14 The hod limit does not depend on the choice of generics.

15 Here $\Psi _{\mu }$ is the strategy of $\mathcal {H}_{\mu }$ , the canonical one-cardinal extension of the hod limit of $L(Hom^*_h, \mathbb {R}^*_h)$ , and the stack Lp $^{cuB,\Psi }$ is defined in [Reference Steel20, Section 4].

16 The second author observes (cf. [Reference Sargsyan and Trang19]) that assuming $\sf {PFA}$ and there is a Woodin cardinal, then there is a canonical model of $\sf {WLW}$ . The proof is not via core model induction methods, but just an observation that the fully backgrounded construction as done in [Reference Sargsyan13] reaches a model of $\sf {WLW}$ . The Woodin cardinal assumption is important here. The argument would not work if one assumes just $\sf {PFA}$ and/or a large cardinal milder than a Woodin cardinal, e.g., a measurable cardinal or a strong cardinal.

References

Feng, Q., Magidor, M., and Woodin, H., Universally Baire sets of reals , Set Theory of the Continuum (Berkeley, CA, 1989) (H. Judah, W. Just, and H. Woodin, editors), Mathematical Sciences Research Institute Publications, vol. 26, Springer, New York, 1992, pp. 203242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Löwe, B., and Steel, J. R. (eds.), Games, Scales, and Suslin Cardinals: The Cabal Seminar, vol. I , Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 31, Association for Symbolic Logic and Cambridge University Press, Chicago and Cambridge, 2008.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Löwe, B., and Steel, J. R. (eds.), Wadge Degrees and Projective Ordinals. The Cabal Seminar, vol. II , Lecture Notes in Logic, 37, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2012.Google Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Löwe, B., and Steel, J. R. (eds.), Ordinal Definability and Recursion Theory: The Cabal Seminar, vol. III , Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 43, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2016. Including reprinted papers from the Caltech-UCLA Cabal seminars held in Los Angeles, CA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Martin, D. A., and Moschovakis, Y. N. (eds.), Cabal Seminar 77–79 , Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 839, Springer, Berlin, 1981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Martin, D. A., and Moschovakis, Y. N. (eds.), Cabal Seminar 79–81 , Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1019, Springer, Berlin, 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S., Martin, D. A., and Steel, J. R. (eds.), Cabal Seminar 81–85 , Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1333, Springer, Berlin, 1988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kechris, A. S. and Moschovakis, Y. N. (eds.), Cabal Seminar 76–77 , Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 689, Springer, Berlin, 1978.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larson, P. B., The Stationary Tower , University Lecture Series, vol. 32, American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2004. Notes on a course by W. Hugh Woodin.Google Scholar
Martin, D. A. and Steel, J. R., Iteration trees . Journal of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 7 (1994), no. 1, pp. 173.Google Scholar
Neeman, I., Inner models in the region of a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 116 (2002), nos. 1–3, pp. 67155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sargsyan, G., Descriptive inner model theory, this Journal, vol. 19 (2013), no. 1, pp. 1–55.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G., Hod Mice and the Mouse Set Conjecture , Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 236(1111), American Mathematical Society, Providence, 2015.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G., Generic generators, to appear.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G., Announcement of recent results in descriptive inner model theory. Available at http://www.grigorsargis.net.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., Sealing from iterability, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , 2019, to appear. Available at math.unt.edu/~ntrang.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., A core model induction past the Largest Suslin Axiom, in preparation.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., The exact consistency strength of generic absoluteness for universally Baire sets, in preparation.Google Scholar
Sargsyan, G. and Trang, N., The largest Suslin axiom, submitted. Available at math.rutgers.edu/~gs481/lsa.pdf.Google Scholar
Steel, J. R., Core models with more Woodin cardinals , The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 67 (2002), no. 3, pp. 11971226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., Local  ${\mathrm{K}}^{\mathrm{c}}$  constructions , The Journal of Symbolic Logic , vol. 72 (2007), no. 3, pp. 721737.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., The derived model theorem , Logic Colloquium 2006 (S. B. Cooper, H. Geuvers, A. Pillay, and J. Vänäänen, editors), Lecture Notes in Logic, vol. 32, Association of Symbolic Logic, Chicago, 2009, pp. 280327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., An outline of inner model theory , Handbook of Set Theory (M. Forman and A. Kanamori, editors), Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 15951684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, J. R., Normalizing iteration trees and comparing iteration strategies. Available at math.berkeley.edu/~steel/papers/Publications.html.Google Scholar
Hugh Woodin, W., The Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, and the Nonstationary Ideal , revised ed., De Gruyter Series in Logic and Its Applications, vol. 1, Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin, 2010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hugh Woodin, W., In search of ultimate-L: The 19 th Midrasha mathematicae lectures, this Journal, vol. 23 (2017), no. 1, pp. 1–109.Google Scholar