Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T07:38:29.290Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Premise Disputes and Political Ideology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 November 2020

David C. Barker*
Affiliation:
Department of Government, American University, Washington, DC, USA
Morgan Marietta
Affiliation:
Department of Political Science, University of Massachusetts, Lowell, MA, USA
*
*Corresponding author. E-mail: dbarker@american.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

A substantial body of scholarship highlights the role of core values as elements of liberalism–conservatism. However, researchers have yet to fully appreciate the contribution of premises, or abstract descriptive beliefs. This disjuncture has occurred despite the fact that for centuries, philosophers have used premises about human nature and society to ground their religious, political and economic theories. In the observational and experimental studies described in this article, the authors examine the extent to which such premise disputes stand independently from value conflicts as ideological ingredients. The findings suggest that premises are distinct and meaningful elements of political cognition, analogous in importance to several well-worn values.

Type
Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

The ‘nature of belief systems in mass publics’ has captivated (and confounded) political scientists for decades (for example, Abramowitz and Saunders Reference Abramowitz and Saunders1998, Ansolabehere, Rodden and Snyder Reference Ansolabehere, Jonathan and Snyder2008; Bobbio Reference Bobbio1997; Conover and Feldman Reference Conover and Feldman1981; Converse Reference Converse and Apter D1964; Ellis and Stimson Reference Ellis and Stimson2012; Lane Reference Lane1962; Levendusky Reference Levendusky2009). Within this research tradition, several studies have emphasized the centrality of abstract normative priorities (variously referred to as ‘core values’, ‘moral foundations’ or ‘principles’) to liberalism–conservatism (for example, Feldman Reference Feldman1988; Goren, Federico and Kittilson 2009; Graham, Haidt and Nosek Reference Graham, Haidt and Nosek2009; Jacoby Reference Jacoby2006; Peffley and Hurwitz Reference Peffley and Hurwitz1985; Rokeach Reference Rokeach1973; Schwartz Reference Schwartz1992; Tetlock Reference Tetlock1986; Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990). However, political scientists have yet to comparably appreciate the distinct role of premises, or abstract descriptive beliefs, as ideological ingredients – despite the fact that for centuries, philosophers have used premises regarding human nature and society to ground their religious, political and economic visions (for example, Augustine ~400; Burke Reference Burke1790; Hobbes Reference Hobbes1651; Jefferson Reference Jefferson1776; Locke 1689; Madison Reference Madison1787; Marx and Engels Reference Marx and Engels1848; Rousseau Reference Rousseau1762; Smith Reference Smith1776).

In this article, we address this gap in scholarship. Drawing insights from Polarity Theory (Tomkins Reference Tomkins and White1964), Cultural Theory (for example, Thompson, Ellis, and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990), Dual-Process Cognitive Motivational Theory, and Reality Theory (Kruglanski Reference Kruglanski1999), and building upon our own theoretical perspective (Marietta Reference Marietta2011), we examine the extent to which three core premise disputes about human nature and society (human benevolence–selfishness, progress idealism–skepticism, social stability–fragility) may account for the variance in liberalism–conservatism – independently from five essential value conflicts that are known to underlie such ideological differences (collectivism–individualism, humanism–theism, sexual progressivism–traditionalism, pacifism–militarism and nurturance–punitiveness). Studies 1 and 2 use nationally representative data to assess these relationships (with respect to both ideological identification and issue-based liberalism–conservatism), and Study 3 uses a randomized controlled experiment to compare how subjects respond to ‘evidence’ regarding human nature which complements their ideological perspective relative to that which contradicts it. In all three studies the data are consistent with our hypotheses, suggesting that premises are distinct and important elements of political ideology.

Ideology, Values and Premises

One useful definition of political ideology is ‘a fairly coherent and comprehensive set of ideas that explains and evaluates social conditions, helps people understand their place in society, and provides a program for social and political action’ (Ball, Dagger and O'Neill Reference Ball, Dagger and O'Neill2016, 5; see Jost, Federico and Napier Reference Jost, Federico and Napier2009 for a review of definitions). The dominant ideological cleavage in the United States pits liberalism against conservatism (for example, Abramowitz and Saunders Reference Abramowitz and Saunders1998; Ellis and Stimson Reference Ellis and Stimson2012; Jacoby Reference Jacoby1991; Knight Reference Knight1985).

Though ‘liberal’ or ‘conservative’ identifications do not usually constrain the majority of Americans’ issue attitudes across policy dimensions (for example, Converse Reference Converse and Apter D1964; Kinder and Kalmoe Reference Kinder and Kalmoe2017), the labels do correspond to a trove of important psychological traits, motives, needs and cognitive styles (for example, Jost Reference Jost2006; Jost et al. Reference Jost2003). Fittingly, then, for well over 50 years, political psychologists have been trying to understand the structure and substance of liberalism–conservatism. Within that line of inquiry, a dense literature highlights the importance of core values as ideological determinants.

Values

For our purposes, values can be defined simply as abstract normative priorities.Footnote 1 The earliest considerations of core values as they relate to politics tended to treat them as broadly accessible alternatives to ideology (for example, Feldman Reference Feldman1988; Feldman and Steenbergen Reference Feldman and Steenbergen2001; Rokeach Reference Rokeach1973). However, over the past 20 years, the conventional wisdom has come to view values – and value conflicts, in particular – as important elements of ideology, especially as they relate to its three basic dimensions: economic, cultural and security/foreign policy (for example Graham, Haidt, and Nosek Reference Graham, Haidt and Nosek2009; Jacoby Reference Jacoby2006; Jost, Federico, and Napier Reference Jost, Federico and Napier2009; McAdams et al. Reference McAdams2008; Pjurko, Shalom and Davidov Reference Pjurko, Shalom and Davidov2011; Tetlock Reference Tetlock1986).Footnote 2

Specific Value-Ideology Linkages

When it comes to the economic dimension of ideology, the intersecting values of liberalism include egalitarianism (Feldman Reference Feldman1988; Jacoby Reference Jacoby2006; Jost et al. Reference Jost2003; McCloskey and Zaller Reference McCloskey and Zaller1984; Swedlow and Wyckoff Reference Swedlow and Wyckoff2009; Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990), humanitarianism Footnote 3 (for example, Feldman and Steenbergen Reference Feldman and Steenbergen2001), nurturance (for example, Barker and Tinnick Reference Barker and Tinnick2006; Lakoff Reference Lakoff1996; McAdams et al. Reference McAdams2008), collectivism (Hofstede Reference Hofstede2001) and universalism (for example, Schwartz Reference Schwartz1992), whereas the values of economic conservatism include individualism (for example, Feldman Reference Feldman1988; Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990; Yoon Reference Yoon2014), limited government (for example, Goren Reference Goren2012), support for free enterprise (for example, Feldman Reference Feldman1988; McCloskey and Zaller Reference McCloskey and Zaller1984; Schwartz, Caprera and Vecchione Reference Schwartz, Caprera and Vecchione2010), proportionality or punitive ‘fairness’ (for example, Haidt Reference Haidt2012) and hierarchism (for example, Schwartz, Caprera and Vecchione Reference Schwartz, Caprera and Vecchione2010; Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990).Footnote 4

As for cultural ideology, intersecting liberal values include civil libertarianism/tolerance (for example, Jacoby Reference Jacoby2006; McCloskey and Zaller Reference McCloskey and Zaller1984; Sullivan, Piereson and Marcus Reference Sullivan, Piereson and Marcus1981; Swedlow and Wyckoff Reference Swedlow and Wyckoff2009), sexual progressivism (for example, Layman and Green Reference Layman and Green2006) and multiculturalism (for example, Schwartz, Caprera and Vecchione Reference Schwartz, Caprera and Vecchione2010), and conservative values include sexual traditionalism (for example, Hunter Reference Hunter1992; Layman Reference Layman2001; Layman and Green Reference Layman and Green2006), moral traditionalism (for example, Goren Reference Goren2012), sanctity (for example, Haidt Reference Haidt2012), in-group loyalty (for example, Haidt Reference Haidt2012) and order (for example, Swedlow and Wycoff Reference Swedlow and Wyckoff2009).

Finally, with respect to security/foreign policy ideology, the values of liberalism include pacifism (for example, Hurwitz and Peffley Reference Hurwitz and Peffley1987), multiculturalism (again) and humanitarianism (again); the values of conservatism include militarism (Hurwitz and Peffley Reference Hurwitz and Peffley1987; Wittkopf Reference Wittkopf1990), strength (Braithwaite Reference Braithwaite1997; Goren Reference Goren2012), nationalism (Hurwitz and Peffley Reference Hurwitz and Peffley1987), punitiveness (for example, McCleary and Williams Reference McCleary and Williams2009), ethnocentrism (Hurwitz and Peffley Reference Hurwitz and Peffley1987) and tough mindedness.

Linking the three dimensions of liberalism–conservatism together, liberalism is associated with an understanding of morality that emphasizes moral compassion, whereas conservatism emphasizes moral discipline (Barker and Tinnick Reference Barker and Tinnick2006).Footnote 5 These competing understandings of morality correspond to conflicting interpretations of the proper role of authority/government: liberals tend to view government's role as that of a helpful Sherpa, whereas conservatives tend to envision a strict schoolmaster (for example, Barker and Tinnick Reference Barker and Tinnick2006; Lakoff Reference Lakoff1996; McAdams et al. Reference McAdams2008).

Other Psychological Constructs of Liberalism–Conservatism

Importantly, though, the psychology of political ideology is about more than what can be objectively dubbed ‘values’. Indeed, some of the normative orientations we have listed above (for example, hierarchism, traditionalism, punitiveness, in-group loyalty, order, tough-mindedness, ethnocentrism) overlap with broader dispositions toward authoritarianism and/or social dominance, each of which undergirds political conservatism – though in somewhat different ways, with authoritarianism being more predictive of cultural conservatism and social dominance orientation being more predictive of economic conservatism (for example, Duckitt Reference Duckitt2001; Feldman and Stenner Reference Feldman and Stenner1997; Haidt Reference Haidt2012; Hetherington and Weiler Reference Hetherington and Weiler2009; Jost et al. Reference Jost2003; Pratto et al. Reference Pratto1994; Sidanius and Pratto Reference Sidanius and Pratto1999; Stenner 3005).

Likewise, some of the value conflicts we have described are also consistent with Cultural Theory's (CT) ‘group’ and ‘grid’ dimensions of social relations (for example, Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990). The group dimension refers to the extent to which an individual is incorporated into bounded social units. The more one is incorporated in this way, the more likely one is to possess progressive economic values (egalitarianism, humanitarianism, nurturance, etc.). The grid dimension refers to the extent to which an individual's life is circumscribed by externally imposed prescriptions. The more it is, the more likely one is to possess conservative cultural and security values (moral and sexual traditionalism, punitiveness, etc.).

In summary, the correspondence between value priorities and liberalism–conservatism is intuitive, compelling and well established, but it is also incomplete. Liberalism–conservatism also reflects deeper psychological dispositions relating to order, change, certainty, simplicity, cognitive closure, anxiety, threat sensitivity and negativity bias, among other things (for example, Hibbing, Smith and Alford Reference Hibbing, Smith and Alford2014; Jost et al. Reference Jost2003; Jost et al. Reference Jost2007; Pedersen, Muftuler and Larson Reference Pedersen, Muftuler and Larson2017; for good overviews, see Jost Reference Jost2006; Jost, Federico and Napier Reference Jost, Federico and Napier2009; Jost et al. Reference Jost2003). We believe these psychological dispositions are likely related to various abstract beliefs about human nature and society – a.k.a. ‘premises’ – which inform part of what we mean when we describe someone as ‘liberal’ or ‘conservative’. In the remainder of this article, we explore the potential relationships between premise beliefs and liberalism–conservatism more fully than has been attempted to date.

Premises

To reiterate, premises are not about how people believe things should be, but rather how people believe things are.Footnote 6 Theoretically speaking, it stands to Aristotelian reason that one pathway through which humans form specific attitudes is by extrapolating them from a set of abstract premises to which they subscribe (for example, Kruglanski Reference Kruglanski1999). And indeed, since more or less the beginning of recorded time, premises about human nature have been a common preoccupation of political, religious and economic philosophers (for example, Augustine ~400; Hobbes Reference Hobbes1651; Jefferson Reference Jefferson1776; Locke 1689; Madison Reference Madison1787; Plato 375 BCE; Rousseau Reference Rousseau1762; Smith Reference Smith1776; Thucydides 404 BCE).

Yet in their empirical accounts of political attitudes and ideology, political scientists typically ignore premise disputes or conflate them with value conflicts (for example, Converse Reference Converse and Apter D1964; Feldman Reference Feldman1988; Sears, Huddy and Schaffer Reference Sears, Huddy and Schaffer1986). This standard practice is certainly understandable; it is difficult in practice to delineate where premises stop and values begin, and the causal relationship between them is certainly not clear.Footnote 7 Nevertheless, conceptually and theoretically speaking, it is important to distinguish premise disputes from value conflicts, and to give the former greater empirical attention.

A few lines of extant research do point to premises as important undercurrents of liberalism–conservatism. For example, Tomkins (Reference Tomkins and White1964) argues that conservatives are more likely than liberals to presume that people are essentially bad and that the world is a dangerous place – premises that are consistent with (or perhaps emerge from) heightened psychological needs for security, order and so on (see Jost et al. Reference Jost2003 for an excellent overview of the way psychological needs inform liberalism–conservatism). In the foreign policy realm, Brewer and Steenbergen show that support for isolationist or co-operative policies is connected to views of human nature (Reference Brewer and Steenbergen2002).

Moreover, the CT scholars to which we referred earlier distinguish between ‘crowning postures’ that are descriptive and those that are prescriptive (though they use different terms than most other political psychologists have). They posit that different ‘myths’ about human and physical nature (what we would call premises) combine with values and ‘grid’ versus ‘group’ social relations to produce four different cultures (hierarchism, egalitarianism, individualism and fatalism; for example, Coughlin and Lockhart Reference Coughlin and Lockhart1998; Douglas Reference Douglas1982; Ellis Reference Ellis1993; Grendstad and Selle Reference Grendstad and Selle2000; Swedlow Reference Swedlow2011; Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990; Wildavsky and Dake Reference Wildavsky and Dake1990; see Swedlow et al. Reference Swedlow2016 for a for an overview of this literature and the measurement scales that CT scholars have used).Footnote 8

Finally, John Duckitt and his colleagues make some empirical progress, using what we would term premise beliefs (they call them ‘worldviews’) to predict authoritarianism and social dominance orientation – which they in turn use to predict political liberalism–conservatism (for example, Duckitt Reference Duckitt2001; Sibley, Wilson and Duckitt Reference Sibley, Wilson and Duckitt2007, also see Altemeyer Reference Altemeyer1988; Altemeyer Reference Altemeyer1998; Federico, Hunt and Ergun Reference Federico, Hunt and Ergun2009).

However, scholars have yet to systematically examine the independent role of specific premise disputes as ideological ingredients, which differentiates them empirically from value conflicts in models of liberalism–conservatism. We make such an effort here. In the next sub-section, we provide the theoretical scaffolding needed to ground our hypotheses with respect to three specific premise disputes about human nature and society.

Specific Premise Disputes and Liberalism–Conservatism

In examining premises and liberalism–conservatism, there are any number of specific premises on which we might have focused. We focus on three foundational premise disputes that have grounded philosophical arguments for centuries: Are humans intrinsically benevolent or selfish? Is significant social progress attainable without God's fingerprints? Is society intrinsically stable or fragile? These questions, though distinct, are interrelated in that they each contrast a sanguine impression of human nature and society with a cynical one.

Intrinsic Human Benevolence–Selfishness

Premise disputes regarding human benevolence–selfishness undergird the predominant schools of religious, economic and political philosophy in the United States. With regard to religious philosophy, many Christian traditions (especially evangelical and fundamentalist ones) begin from the Calvinistic premise that humans are fundamentally depraved, while others (most mainline Protestant and Catholic traditions) view human nature as being more complicated (for example, Williams Reference Williams2008). When it comes to economic philosophy (which has been central to leftright orientations for as long as that distinction has had meaning), laissez-faire capitalism assumes that the inherent selfishness of humankind must be channeled (for example, Mandeville Reference Mandeville1732; Smith Reference Smith1776), whereas socialists and welfare state advocates place much greater faith in the co-operative instincts of humans (for example, Marx and Engels Reference Marx and Engels1848; Rawls Reference Rawls1971). Finally, as for patently political philosophy, classical proponents of popular democracy assumed that human nature is broadly altruistic and co-operative (for example, Jefferson Reference Jefferson1776; Rousseau Reference Rousseau1762), whereas those who favored a republic (or stronger forms of government) assumed that human nature is either selfish or that it varies greatly across individuals (for example, Hobbes Reference Hobbes1651; Madison Reference Madison1787; also see Golding Reference Golding1954).

Grounding their arguments to some degree in those classical philosophies, CT researchers (for example, Grendstad and Selle Reference Grendstad and Selle2000; Swedlow Reference Swedlow2011; Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990) posit that (1) egalitarianism (which corresponds to liberalism, both economically and socially) naturally follows from the premise that human beings are intrinsically well intentioned, whereas (2) individualism (which corresponds to economic but not social policy conservatism) grows out of the presumption that humans are immutably selfish and (3) hierarchism (which corresponds to cultural but not economic policy conservatism), stems from the premise that human character is naturally depraved but can (and indeed must) be redeemed by the right institutions.Footnote 9

Additionally, Silvan Tomkins’ (Reference Tomkins and White1964) polarity theory posits that left-wing ideologies presume that people are basically good and that the purpose of society is to facilitate human growth, whereas right-wing ideologies presume people are essentially bad and that the function of society is to set limits to prevent irresponsible behavior (also see de St. Aubin Reference de St. Aubin1996; Stone and Schaffner Reference Stone and Schaffner1988).

Moreover, John Duckitt and his colleagues (for example, Duckitt Reference Duckitt2001; Sibley, Wilson and Duckitt Reference Sibley, Wilson and Duckitt2007) have observed that those who believe the world is a competitive jungle (and by inference that people are intrinsically competitive rather than co-operative) tend to be oriented toward social dominance, which is itself associated with economic conservatism (for example, Pratto et al. Reference Pratto1994; Sidanius and Pratto Reference Sidanius and Pratto1999).

Consistent with these perspectives, we posit that conservatism grows (in part) out of the conviction that human character is inclined toward self-interest, aggression and sloth, which is why conservatives perceive the need for institutions such as the market, the church and the family to counter such natural tendencies, and why they view the proper role of authority as disciplinary, albeit limited (for example, Will Reference Will2019). By contrast, we posit that liberalism stems in part from the belief that human character is either intrinsically well intentioned or a blank slate, meaning that neither a highly competitive economic system nor a strongly punitive justice system is necessary to encourage people to act benevolently and responsibly, and that the proper role of government is therefore to provide nurturance (for more theoretical elaboration (but no empirical tests), see Marietta Reference Marietta2011). In sum:

Hypothesis 1: Belief in the premise that human character is inherently and immutably benevolent (selfish) is associated with ideological liberalism (conservatism).

Progress Idealism–Skepticism

Premise disputes regarding human nature are not only about inherent human decency; they also relate to inherent human capacity – including the capacity for improvement. Even if humanity's goals are magnanimous, how capable are humans of achieving them? Again, many Christian traditions offer a skeptical response, unless God (or the agents of God) step(s) in. Indeed, the classical Lutheran and Calvinistic presumptions of human depravity were about weakness as well as wickedness. This cultural premise was paramount across Protestant Europe in the 1600s–1700s until philosophers like Rousseau challenged it, promoting a humanistic vision of relentless human progress instead (see Pinker Reference Pinker2018 for a recent overview). A backlash followed, with British conservative intellectual forbear Edmund Burke (Reference Burke1790) reasserting a classic questioning of secular human capacity as justification for his skepticism toward popular democracy and broader Utopian ambitions.Footnote 10

Here, like before, CT has something to contribute. According to the CT typology, egalitarians believe that human beings have great capacity for change (and thus to achieve progress) as long as heavy-handed institutions do not hold them back (Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky Reference Thompson, Ellis and Wildavsky1990). This understanding is consistent with a liberal vision of humankind that is progressing steadily toward a free, equal and prosperous Utopia. By contrast, per CT, individualists (who, again, are economically conservative) presume that human selfishness is immutable, and that progress is therefore possible if and only if social/economic structures encourage and harness that selfishness into competition (that is, as long as they do not get in the way). Sharing individualists’ pessimism regarding human nature but not its capacity for change, CT's hierarchists (who may lean left economically because of their high ‘group’ orientation but are culturally conservative because of their high ‘grid’ orientation) presume the opposite – that human weakness can be fortified but only by coercive institutions, such as the church or a legal/governmental framework that is designed to impose discipline. If the heirarchists are right, then perhaps some definitions of ‘progress’ might be achievable, but secular Utopian visions (in which communities are both co-operative and free from coercion) would appear laughably naïve.Footnote 11

Moreover, Jost et al. (Reference Jost2003) review several studies that treat liberalism as an ideology that welcomes change, which is consistent with an idealistic view of the potential for social progress through human efforts, and conservatism as an ideology that resists change, which suggests a cynical view of the potential for social progress through human efforts.

By making the proposed relationship between progress idealism–skepticism and ideology explicit, we argue that regardless of one's presumptions about inherent human decency, if one thinks that government-sponsored attempts to engender progress will inevitably lead to ruin instead – because ordinary people are bound to muck things up – then one is not going to support such efforts, preferring instead to trust ‘the invisible hand’ to maintain equilibrium. This is the essence of free market conservatism (also see Will Reference Will2019). Economic liberals believe the public, via the government, can (and must) try to make things better through direct market interventions. If liberals were to share conservatives’ faith that such efforts are all futile anyway, even they would presumably put their energies elsewhere (again, see Marietta Reference Marietta2011 for more theoretical elaboration). In sum:

Hypothesis 2: Idealism (skepticism) with respect to the notion that human efforts can produce social progress is associated with ideological liberalism (conservatism) – especially economic liberalism (conservatism).

Social Stability–Fragility

Finally, we suggest that premise disputes regarding society's inherent social stability–fragility are also an important ideological determinant. Specifically, we expect that those who perceive the nation's defense, economy or culture to be necessarily precarious are more likely to also see threats looming around every corner – a tendency that often corresponds to authoritarianism and political conservatism more broadly (for example, Feldman and Stenner Reference Feldman and Stenner1997; Hibbing, Smith and Alford Reference Hibbing, Smith and Alford2014; Jost et al. Reference Jost2003; Jost et al. Reference Jost2007).Footnote 12 That is, differences in assumptions regarding the degree to which the world is dangerous – and thus that civilized society is inherently precarious – may prompt greater security concerns and suspicion of outsiders, thereby priming socio-cultural conservatism (for example, Duckitt and Fisher Reference Duckitt and Fisher2003; Federico, Hunt and Ergun Reference Federico, Hunt and Ergun2009).Footnote 13 As with the previous two hypotheses, see Marietta (Reference Marietta2011) for a more detailed theoretical argument.

It is worth considering, though, whether this premise dispute regarding social stability–fragility might itself be partially derivative of the views about human nature that we have already discussed. If an individual believes humankind is inherently malevolent – whether redeemable or not – then he or she is more likely to view the world as a dangerous place filled with bad people (reflected in other nations, other cultures and so on) who pose a threat to American culture and society. In other words, to worry that one's own nation or culture is precarious, one has to presume that foreign nations and cultures will inflict harm if given the opportunity. And to presume that, one has to also believe that basic human nature is wicked or at least highly selfish and competitive. However, if human beings were – on the whole and in roughly equal proportion to one another – decent and well intentioned, then there would be no reason to distrust their motives, and there would therefore be less reason to feel threatened by changes to the culture, economy or world.Footnote 14

Despite such theoretical overlap, for now we treat the social stability–fragility premise dispute as distinct from the premise disputes that pertain directly to human nature. Stated formally:

Hypothesis 3: Belief in the premise that the nation and culture are stable (fragile) is associated with ideological liberalism (conservatism) – especially cultural and security liberalism (conservatism).

We conducted three studies to test our hypotheses. Studies 1 and 2 use observational data from 2013 and 2014 to examine the degree to which the three premise disputes described above predict ideological identification and issue-based political ideology, while also accounting for prominent value conflicts and other confounds. Study 3 uses a priming experiment to observe the extent to which (a) liberals respond favorably to ‘evidence’ that paints a sanguine portrait of human nature and society while rejecting information to the contrary (Hypothesis 4a) and (b) conservatives react precisely the opposite way (Hypothesis 4b).

Studies 1 and 2: Observational Evidence

In these studies, we estimated a series of generalized ordered-logit and ordinary least squares regression models predicting liberalism–conservatism with three premise disputes (human benevolence–selfishness, progress idealism–skepticism and societal stability–fragility), five value conflicts (collectivism–individualism, humanism–theism, sexual progressivism–traditionalism, pacifism–militarism and nurturance–punitiveness) as well as other potential confounds.

Data and Measurement

We collected nationally representative survey responses as part of the 2013 and 2014 Cooperative Congressional Election Studies (CCES).Footnote 15 For efficiency's sake, we focus our discussion on the 2014 data and results; we present the 2013 results – which are highly similar to those we discuss below – in Appendix Section III, 10–14.

Measuring liberalism–conservatism

To assess the empirical robustness of our findings, and in recognition of the fact that liberalism–conservatism resonates in American politics both as an identity and as a constellation of policy preferences, we measure it using five distinct dependent variables: (a) a single survey item of self-identified liberalism–conservatism (three-point scale, converted to 0–1; ‘conservative’= 1), (b) a policy preference factor score index (maximum-likelihood extraction) on the following issues: poverty, education, health care, minimum wage, the environment, racial inequality, undocumented immigration, gun control, abortion, gay marriage, defense, terrorism, affirmative action and the Iraq War (Cronbach's α = 0.86; Eigenvalue = 5.11); (c) an economic policy preference factor score index (poverty, the minimum wage, education, health care, minimum wage and the environment; Cronbach's α = 0.82; Eigenvalue = 2.77); (d) a ‘culture war’ policy preference index (abortion, gay marriage, immigration, affirmative action and gun control; Cronbach's α = 0.63; single factor extracted; Eigenvalue = 1.51) and (e) a security policy preference factor score index (defense, terrorism and the Iraq War; Cronbach's α = 0.66; Eigenvalue = 1.38).Footnote 16 The specific question wording, factor loadings and communalities for each indicator appear in the Appendix. We deleted missing observations using the listwise procedure (in alternative specifications we imputed missing observations in the issue-based liberalism–conservatism measure, which improves the statistical significance of some relationships. See Appendix Section I, Table A5, 6).

Measuring premise disputes

We again used factor analysis (maximum-likelihood extraction) to measure the three premise disputes we discussed earlier in order to generate multi-item indices of each premise dispute and to attenuate random error. First, we presented respondents with a series of paired statements. For each paired comparison, we asked them to indicate, on a four-point scale, which statement they agreed with more (0 = clear preference for the first statement and 3 = clear preference for the second statement). To capture human benevolence–selfishness, we used three paired comparisons:

  • ‘People naturally compete rather than cooperate’ vs.

    ‘People naturally cooperate rather than compete’

  • ‘People will seek their own interest, rather than what is morally right’ vs.

    ‘People will do what is morally right, rather than seek their own interest’

  • ‘People try to get as much for themselves as they can, even if it is morally wrong’ vs. ‘People try to do what is morally right, even if they have to sacrifice’

To measure progress idealism–skepticism, we used four paired comparisons:

  • ‘The world can be made better if we work together’ vs.

    ‘The world is what it is and will remain so’

  • ‘Humans can change and improve with each new generation’ vs.

    ‘People in each generation are essentially the same’

  • ‘Efforts to improve our society have generally led to good outcomes’ vs.

    ‘Efforts to improve our society have generally led to bad outcomes’

  • ‘Human society can be perfected’ vs.

    ‘Human society is essentially fixed and cannot be perfected’

To measure social stability–fragility, we used three paired comparisons:Footnote 17

  • ‘Our society is vulnerable to losing our place of strength to other nations’ vs.

    ‘Our society does not need to worry about declining strength compared to other nations’

  • ‘The American Way is in danger’ vs.

    ‘The American Way is changing but there is nothing to worry about’

  • ‘The decline of personal character in our society is weakening us’ vs.

    ‘The personal character of Americans is as strong as ever’

Measuring value conflicts

We chose to include four sets of value conflicts as predictors in the models. In keeping with our discussion in the previous section, the first three correspond directly to the economic, cultural and foreign policy dimensions of liberalism–conservatism: collectivism–individualism, humanism–theism and pacifism–militarism. We also measured nurturance–punitiveness as an additional ‘catch-all’ value, because it is highly associated with political attitudes across the board and with ideological constraint (Barker and Tinnick Reference Barker and Tinnick2006). Thus its inclusion represents an effort on our part to go ‘above and beyond’ in accounting for other confounds that may be related to our premise disputes.

To measure the first three value conflicts, we presented respondents with sets of competing values and asked them to indicate ‘Which is more important?’ The sets of competing norms were as follows: ‘Cooperation & Helping Others … or Self-Reliance & Personal Responsibility’ (collectivism–individualism), ‘Peace … or Protecting America with Force, if Necessary’ (pacifism–militarism), ‘Scientific Knowledge … or Religious Faith’ (humanism–theism).Footnote 18 To measure nurturance–punitiveness, we asked respondents, ‘If you had to define what it means to be a ‘good person,’ which quality would you say is more important? Discipline & Self-Control or Kindheartedness?’ We captured responses on a four-point scale (0 = strong preference for the first option, 3 = strong preference for the second option).

Measuring other confounds

Finally, to round out our models, we include covariates for Race (1 = non-White), Gender (1 = Female), Year of Birth (1920–1995), Gross Family Income (0 = 0; <10k = 1; 10–19k = 2; 20–29k = 3; 30–39k = 4; 40–49k = 5; 50–59k = 6; 60–69k = 7; 70–79k = 8; 80–99k = 9; 100–119k = 10; 120–149k = 11; 150–199k = 12; 200–249k = 13; 250k + = 14) and Educational Attainment (‘What is the highest level of schooling you have completed?’; 0 ≤ HS; 1 = HS only; 2 = some college; 3 = 2-year college degree; 4 = 4-year college degree; 5 = post-graduate).Footnote 19

Validating the Model: Confirmatory Factor Analysis

To evaluate our chosen model specification – and the theory underlying it that treats premise disputes and value constructs as related but distinct elements of political cognition – we performed a series of confirmatory factor analyses within a structural equation modeling environment (maximum-likelihood estimation) to ascertain the degree to which our theoretically derived measurement model fits the data compared to alternative theoretical specifications (see Bentler Reference Bentler1990). Specifically, we compared the theoretical measurement model that we described above to (a) a model that uses all of the premise indicators to form a single Human Nature Optimism–Pessimism index and (b) a model that uses all of the premise indicators and all of the value indicators to form a single belief system index. As the Comparative Fit and Tucker-Lewis Fit Indices reveal below, our theoretical measurement model fits the data better than the others (LR Test p < 0.001).

Predictive Modeling Results

Tables 2 and 3 display the results of our general ordered logit and linear regression analyses. Table 2 displays the results as they pertain to the single-dimension ideological constructs, whereas Table 3 displays the results related to different dimensions of ideology.Footnote 20 For simplicity, we do not include the demographic covariates in the table; the full models are available in Appendix Section I, Table A1, 1).

Table 1. Confirmatory factor analyses: model comparison

Note: comparison of model fit statistics (on 0–1 scales) between (a) the theoretical model we have described here, which distinguishes between three premise disputes (Model 1), (b) a second model that presumes all premise dispute indicators contribute to a single latent concept of premise beliefs but that distinguishes value conflicts (Model 2), and (c) a third model that presumes all premise and value indicators contribute to a single underlying belief structure (Model 3). All differences are statistically significant (p < 0.001).

Table 2. Premise disputes, value conflicts and liberalism–conservatism

Note: the left-hand model is a generalized ordinal logistic regression estimate; coefficients are differences in the odds of identifying as a ‘conservative’ relative to a ‘liberal’, associated with minimum-to-maximum differences in the explanatory variables. The right-hand model is an ordinary least squares regression estimate. Coefficients are differences in policy liberalism–conservatism (conservatism coded high and converted to 0–1 scales) associated with minimum-to-maximum differences in each independent variable. In both models, the p-values correspond to two-tailed tests.

Table 3. 2014 Linear regression analyses of ideological sub-dimensions (Economic, Cultural, Security)

Note: the coefficients are differences in economic, cultural and security liberalism–conservatism (conservatism coded high and converted to 0–1 scales) associated with minimum-to-maximum differences in each independent variable. The probabilities that the null hypothesis in question is true in the population are in parentheses (two-tailed tests).

Starting with Table 2, the first results column focuses on the differences in the odds of identifying as a ‘conservative’, vs. a ‘liberal’, associated with minimum-to-maximum differences in each premise belief or value priority (we omit the estimates relating to the likelihood of identifying as a moderate, relative to either of the other two categories). We see that two of the three premise disputes account for symbolic liberalism–conservatism to a highly substantial degree. Those who were most inclined to believe that American society is fragile and those who were most skeptical that society can be improved through human efforts both tended to be over seven times more likely to identify as a conservative, relative to a liberal, than those who are most convinced that society is stable (p < 0.001) or those who are the most idealistic about society being perfectible (p < 0.001). The only premise that is not statistically related to ideological identification is human benevolence or selfishness: those who strongly indicated that human nature is intrinsically selfish did not appear any more conservative, on average, than those who believe it is intrinsically benevolent.Footnote 21

The right-hand column shows that, with respect to policy-based ideology, respondents who were most inclined to believe that American society is fragile tended to score about 24 points higher (more conservative) on the 0–1 scale than those who were most convinced that society is stable (p < 0.001). Moreover, we see that those who were most skeptical that society can be improved through human efforts also tended to be about 24 points more conservative on the 0–1 scale than those who are the most idealistic (p < 0.001). Finally, those who are most convinced that human nature is intrinsically selfish tended to express about five points greater conservatism on the 0–1 scale than those who are the most sanguine about human nature (p < 0.09).

As anticipated, Table 3 demonstrates that when it comes to different dimensions of policy liberalismconservatism, the predictive capacity of perceived social fragility appears to be stronger than that of skepticism regarding human progress with respect to cultural conservatism and security conservatism, but the opposite is true for economic conservatism. Finally, a pessimistic view of human nature is associated with policy conservatism in the economic and security realms, but not the cultural realm.Footnote 22

Collectively, these models suggest that premise disputes are powerful correlates of liberalism–conservatism, comparable in both substantive and statistical significance to prominent value conflicts. Both the 2014 analysis (presented above) and the 2013 study (presented in the Appendix) illustrate the same conclusions.Footnote 23

In our final study, which we describe below, we attempt to augment the internal validity of these findings by revealing the latent premises of liberals and conservatives through a priming experiment.

Study 3: Revealing Liberal and Conservative Premises through Priming

To gain greater purchase on the question of whether premises about human nature are relevant ingredients of liberalism–conservatism, we conducted a randomized controlled experiment using a non-probability sample of politically interested respondents that we drew from Amazon's online Mechanical Turk (MTurk) labor market (n = 1,588).Footnote 24 We prompted the survey respondents with claims from a (fake) research study purporting to demonstrate that human nature is either good or bad. We then observed the relative propensities of liberals and conservatives to agree with the claim to which they had been exposed, as reflected by their own expressed views on human nature.Footnote 25

We lean on priming theory, which demonstrates that latent beliefs can be made more or less salient to judgments depending on whether they have been ‘primed’ to the front of someone's consciousness. Importantly, priming is different from persuasion: whereas persuasion changes a person's mind, priming makes some existing beliefs or attitudes more salient than others when people are forming a judgment.Footnote 26 Thus priming only works if the beliefs or attitudes in question are already present in the back of a person's mind (for example, Tesler Reference Tesler2015).

If our logic and evidence from Studies 1 and 2 are correct, and premises regarding human nature are indeed ideologically infused, then the experimental treatments should produce a priming effect, but not a persuasive effect. That is, a priming effect would indicate that people react favorably to new ‘information’ that appears to validate their ideological perspective, but not to information that seems to contradict that perspective (for an extended summary of the vast literature on motivated reasoning, confirmation bias and cognitive dissonance, see Marietta and Barker Reference Marietta and Barker2019).Footnote 27 By contrast, a persuasion effect would indicate that respondents change their minds in response to any new information provided by an experimental treatment, regardless of their ideological point of view, which would suggest that premises are not necessarily related to ideology. Likewise, null results would also suggest that premises are not necessarily related to ideology. Either a persuasion effect or null results would weaken our theory.

To summarize and reiterate:

Hypothesis 4a (Liberals): When prompted with information pointing to a positive appraisal of human nature, ideological liberals tend to express greater sanguinity toward human nature than control group respondents. By contrast, progressives are not persuaded by information pointing to a cynical view of human nature.

Hypothesis 4b (Conservatives): When prompted with information pointing to a cynical appraisal of human nature, ideological conservatives tend to express greater cynicism about human nature than control group respondents. By contrast, conservatives are not persuaded by information pointing to a sanguine view of human nature.

Experimental Procedures and Measurement

We randomly assigned survey respondents to one of three messages. Respondents in the control group received the following message:

Researchers from the Rand Corporation, Stanford University and Brigham Young University recently published a ten-year study of 30,000 infants and toddlers across four continents. Several publications (including The New York Times, The Wall Street Journal, MSNBC and Fox News) have praised the research for its rigor, transparency and lack of bias.Footnote 28

Respondents in the Humanity Good treatment group saw the same thing, but also saw the following sandwiched in between the first and second sentences: ‘The results consistently suggest that human beings are, more often than not, naturally generous, disciplined, and trustworthy.’ Finally, respondents in the Humanity Bad treatment group saw a different sentence sandwiched between the control group sentences: ‘The results consistently suggest that human beings are, more often than not, naturally selfish, undisciplined, and devious.’

Next, we asked all respondents to answer four questions regarding the nature of human character/capacity, which corresponded to the information in the treatments:Footnote 29

  • Do you tend to think that human nature is naturally selfish or generous (generous or selfish), generally speaking? (0 = definitely generous; 4 = definitely selfish)

  • Do you tend to think that human nature is naturally devious or trustworthy (trustworthy or devious), generally speaking? (0 = definitely trustworthy; 4 = definitely devious)

  • Do you tend to think that human nature is naturally disciplined or undisciplined (undisciplined or disciplined), generally speaking? (0 = definitely disciplined; 4 = definitely undisciplined)

  • Given human nature, would you say that collective public efforts to improve society tend to eventually succeed or fail (fail or succeed)? (0 = definitely succeed; 4 = definitely fail)

Using factor analysis (maximum-likelihood extraction), we created a Human Nature Sanguinity–Cynicism index of the four human nature questions listed above (Cronbach's α = 0.69; Eigenvalue = 1.49), and converted it to a 0–1 scale for analysis (mean = 0.47; standard deviation = 0.37). This index serves as the outcome variable in our model (the results from binary probit models using each individual premise dispute as the outcome variable (collapsing the definitely and probably categories and eliminating the ‘don't know’ middle categories) are available in Appendix Section IV, Table A10, 17).Footnote 30

Then we asked respondents to report their Ideological Identification (three-point, rescaled to 0–1; 0 = liberal; 1 = conservative; mean = 0.38; s.d. = 0.42). The model's explanatory variables are (a) both experimental treatments (the control group is the reference category), (b) Ideological Identification and (c) interaction terms that multiply Ideological Identification by each of the treatments.Footnote 31

We rounded out our models with the following demographic covariates: White (77 per cent of sample), Female (50 per cent of sample), Age (18–85; mean = 42; s.d. = 13.25), Annual Household Income (mean = $39,900; s.d. = $27,000) and Education (6-point ≤ high-school; 6 = post-graduate degree (converted to 0–1; mean = 0.66; s.d. = 0.25)).Footnote 32

Results

As Figure 1 displays (Appendix Table A3 contains the full statistical results), among liberals (illustrated in the lower half of the figure), the Humanity Bad treatment produced no boost in cynicism relative to the control group, but the Humanity Good treatment generated a drop in cynicism (or a boost in sanguinity) from 0.46 to 0.30 on the 0–1 scale (p < 0.001). Likewise, among conservatives, the Humanity Good treatment did not reduce respondents’ stated cynicism regarding human nature, but the Humanity Bad treatment boosted such cynicism (or reduced sanguinity) from 0.5 to 0.68 on the 0–1 scale (p < 0.001).Footnote 33 In other words, ideologues readily embraced information that comported with what we and others have suggested is their instinctual point of view, but resisted information that contradicted that point of view.Footnote 34 This evidence is consistent with a priming effect but not a persuasion effect, and thereby suggests that liberals and conservatives have different latent premises about human nature that they may not necessarily think about until they are primed to do so, but they are not easily persuaded to think otherwise. Another interpretation is that the liberals and conservatives in our sample applied different confirmation biases when they encountered the treatment (that is, they respond more favorably to information that is consistent with their prior beliefs), irrespective of priming theory.

Figure 1. Premise prompts and cynicism toward human nature among liberals and conservatives

Note: differences in human nature sanguinity-cynicism associated with exposure to the experimental treatments, among liberals and conservatives.

Conclusion

In this investigation, we have considered the role that premises – abstract descriptive beliefs – play in the formation of political ideology. We have described three studies. The first and second studies use two rounds of observational data to analyze the capacity of premise disputes relating to human benevolence–selfishness, progress idealism–skepticism and social stability–fragility to predict ideological identification and policy ideology, independent of prominent value conflicts. The third study uses a randomized controlled priming experiment to identify the degree to which citizens respond favorably to ‘evidence’ regarding human nature that is consistent with their ideological perspective while rejecting such information when it contradicts that ideological perspective.

The results suggest that these premises are important components of ideology, which should be incorporated into standard models of attitudinal and ideological formation – alongside party identification, identities and values. These observations are important because they (1) provide overdue empirical validation to centuries-old theories from classical philosophy, (2) empirically complement the theoretical arguments of several contemporary theories, (3) explain variance in ideology that has heretofore been present in residual terms and (4) boost the theoretical leverage in models of ideology since premises are positive, rather than normative, dispositions – and are thus immune to criticism that the constructs on either side of the equation are the same.

There are at least two fruitful avenues for future research. First, sorting out the causality between values and premises was beyond the scope of this article, but doing so is an important next step towards understanding the potential for premises to influence ideology indirectly via values (and vice versa).

Secondly, several additional premise disputes remain to be explored as ideological determinants, including the extent to which (1) human nature varies across individuals (regardless of whether it is, on balance, ‘good’ or ‘bad’), (2) various human characteristics are grounded in ‘nature’ vs. ‘nurture’, (3) fate determines outcomes, (4) the ‘invisible hand’ of the free market produces efficient outcomes in the long run, (5) karma is operative (that is, whether ‘what goes around comes around’ is empirically accurate), as well as premises about God and religion such as (6) whether God exists, and if so, (7) how active God is in human events, (8) the extent to which God is merciful or punitive and (9) whether Heaven and/or Hell exists. We also think it could be useful to explore more specific premises such as (10) when human life begins (at conception? at birth?) and (11) the nature/dynamics of gender and sexual differences (to what extent are they intrinsic or socially constructed, and to what extent are gender and sex related?) We encourage others to examine the extent to which these premises predict liberal–conservative issue attitudes, identification and constraint, and how they relate to various psychological needs and motives that underscore ideological differences.

Supplementary material

Data replication sets are available in Harvard Dataverse at: https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/2GWLWP and online appendices are available at https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123420000460.

Acknowledgements

The authors are grateful to Justin Gross, Elizabeth Suhay, and the members of the Political Communication Working Group at UMass Lowell (John Cluverius, Joshua Dyck, Mona Kleinberg, and Jenifer Whitten-Woodring) as well as three anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments on earlier drafts.

Footnotes

1 Other definitions include ‘cognitive representations of desirable, trans-situational goals’ (e.g., Rokeach Reference Rokeach1973; Schwartz Reference Schwartz1992), ‘crowning postures that guide political judgment’ (Goren Reference Goren2012; Peffley and Hurwitz Reference Peffley and Hurwitz1985), ‘definitions of what is “good” and “bad” in the world’ (Jacoby Reference Jacoby2006) and ‘innate, universal psychological systems that are the “intuitive ethics” from which culture then constructs virtues, narratives, and institutions’ (e.g., Graham, Haidt and Nosek Reference Graham, Haidt and Nosek2009).

2 Recognizing at least two (overlapping) dimensions of liberalism–conservatism is typical among political psychologists (e.g., Alford, Funk and Hibbing Reference Alford, Funk and Hibbing2005; Duckitt Reference Duckitt2001, Feldman and Johnston Reference Feldman and Johnston2014; Gastil et al. Reference Gastil2011; Jackson Reference Jackson2014; Ripberger et al. Reference Ripberger2012; Treier and Hillygus Reference Treier and Sunshine Hillygus2009). However, unifying frameworks are not uncommon either (e.g., Barker and Tinnick Reference Barker and Tinnick2006, and Jacoby Reference Jacoby1995; Jost et al. Reference Jost2003; Tomkins Reference Tomkins and White1964). Perhaps the most prominent of those frameworks is that of ‘motivated social cognition’, which suggests that the essential difference between liberals and conservatives is the heightened need among conservatives to manage uncertainty and threat, which motivates resistance to change and justification of inequality (e.g., Jost et al. Reference Jost2003).

3 A.k.a. ‘care’ (e.g., Haidt Reference Haidt2012, also see Swedlow and Wyckoff Reference Swedlow and Wyckoff2009).

4 Many of the values we delineate in this section overlap conceptually. See Maleki and de Jong (Reference Maleki and de Jong2014) for a summary of labels used to denote similar constructs.

5 Tomkins (Reference Tomkins and White1964) makes a similar distinction between ‘humanistic’ and ‘normative’ scripts, which can be thought of as corresponding to the competing moral perspectives of Jean Valjean and Javert in Hugo's Les Miserables (1862).

6 However, premises are unlike ordinary fact perceptions (e.g., the official unemployment rate or the scientific veracity of anthropogenic climate change) in that they operate at higher levels of abstraction and are essentially non-falsifiable, empirically.

7 See Marietta and Barker (Reference Marietta and Barker2019) for a comprehensive overview of how selection bias and motivated reasoning drive people to see the world in ways that are consistent with their preferences, and see Jost et al. (Reference Jost2003) for more discussion of how normative and descriptive orientations are not mutually exclusive.

8 Relatedly, the profusion of Cultural Cognition (CC) studies by Daniel Kahan et al. have provided important insights about how normative orientations influence fact perceptions and causal attributions (e.g., Kahan Reference Kahan2013; Kahan Reference Kahan, Scott and Kosslyn2016; Kahan and Braman Reference Kahan and Braman2006), but they have not sought to understand the extent to which higher-order premises might underlie the normative orientations in the first place.

9 Space constraints preclude us from elaborating further on the connections between classical theories and CT. For more, see Ellis (Reference Ellis1993) and Wildavsky (Reference Wildavsky1998).

10 Premises about human decency may also underlie progress idealism-skepticism. If humans are fundamentally weak, the potential for social progress is limited, regardless of whether that weakness reflects moral depravity, incompetence or both. If humans are selfish but competent (as CT's individualists believe), progress might be achieved through laissez-faire economics or Madisonian institutions.

11 For more details, see Ellis Reference Ellis1993; Wildavsky Reference Wildavsky1998. To be clear, CT does not discuss ‘cultural biases’ pertaining to intrinsic human capacity, per se. It does, however, differentiate between such biases with respect to whether human nature is mutable or fixed, which we view as related.

12 However, CT studies have observed that different cultural types (hierarchists, individualists, egalitarians and fatalists) – and thus liberals and conservatives – perceive risk differently depending on the type of risk (e.g., Johnson and Swedlow Reference Johnson and Swedlow2019; Steg and Sievers Reference Steg and Sievers2000; Tansey and Rayner Reference Tansey, Rayner, Heath and O'Hair1992; Wildavsky and Dake Reference Wildavsky and Dake1990; Xue et al. Reference Xue2014). By no means do we consider risk assessment, threat perceptions and premises regarding social stability–fragility to be synonymous, but we do view them as inter-related, and so the CT researchers’ nuanced findings regarding ideology and risk perceptions are worth noting.

13 CT also describes ‘cultural myths of physical nature’ (see especially Grendstad and Selle Reference Grendstad and Selle2000). These myths address the inherent precariousness or stability of the physical environment, rather than the cultural environment, as our social stability–fragility premise does.

14 For an elaboration of this theoretical argument, see Marietta (Reference Marietta2011).

16 As we alluded to previously, there are reasons to expect that belief in social stability–fragility is more strongly associated with cultural and security conservatism than with economic conservatism, and that progress idealism–skepticism is more strongly associated with economic conservatism than with cultural or security conservatism.

17 The Appendix contains descriptive statistics, factor loadings and communalities. Some of the indicators we use to construct our premise dispute indexes differ slightly in the 2013 models, reflecting evolution in our thinking from 2013 to 2014.

18 Humanism–theism has received less scholarly validation than other cultural value conflict indicators. As such, to demonstrate robustness, Study 2 uses a different measure (sexual progressivism–traditionalism) to capture the culture war value conflict differences. We describe this variable and present those results in Appendix Section III, 10–14.

19 We do not include Party ID due to concerns about post-treatment bias (e.g., Montgomery, Nyhan and Torres Reference Montgomery, Nyhan and Torres2018). In alternative model specifications in which we do include it (three-point, with Independent leaners coded as partisans), it does not alter our conclusions (see Appendix Section I, Tables A3 and OA4, 4–5).

20 The differences in sample size are attributable to the fact that there is missing data associated with each issue attitude in the Policy Liberalism–Conservatism Index that, collectively, reduces the overall sample size.

21 However, premise beliefs about benevolence versus selfishness were related to ideological identification in Study II, though it was the weakest of the three relationships (see Appendix Table A7).

22 A separate structural equation model reveals that the premises are also significant predictors of value priorities (see Appendix Section II, 7–9).

23 The 2013 study employs slightly different wording for the three premises (see Appendix Part III), which provides a robustness check on variations in measurement. Likewise, the values are somewhat different, focusing on collectivism–individualism and pacifism–militarism as in Study 1, but replacing humanism–theism (which focuses on normative predispositions toward religion) with sexual progressivism–traditionalism (which focuses on normative predispositions toward family arrangements). This study finds the same pattern of consistent and strong independent relationships between premises and ideology, on par with the role of values (see Table A7).

24 For evidence that samples using MTurk respondents are useful for predictive modeling, see Berinsky, Huber and Lenz (Reference Berinsky, Huber and Lenz2012); Levay, Freese and Druckman (Reference Levay, Freese and Druckman2016); and Clifford, Jewell and Waggoner (Reference Clifford, Jewell and Waggoner2015).

25 At the survey's conclusion, respondents learned that the study was not real.

26 For an elaboration of the psychology of priming, see Tversky and Kahneman (Reference Tversky and Kahneman1973). For more on how it affects survey responses, see Zaller and Feldman (Reference Zaller and Feldman1992).

27 Furthermore, Cultural Cognition Theory has successfully shown that cultural biases and psychological processes interact to cause people to (1) fit their views to those of people with whom they share critical self-identifying commitments (Cohen Reference Cohen2003; Finucane et al. Reference Finucane2000; Kahan et al. Reference Kahan2007a; Kahan et al. Reference Kahan2007b), (2) notice and prioritize vivid and catastrophic incidents that support cultural predispositions (Kahan Reference Kahan2011; Kahan and Braman Reference Kahan and Braman2003), (3) credit information sources that seem to share their values (Kahan et al. Reference Kahan2010) and (4) be more open to culturally threatening information if it affirms their worldviews (Braman et al. 2007; Cohen Reference Cohen, Aronson and Steele2000; Cohen Reference Cohen2007).

28 To enhance the claim's credibility, we included an elite university (Stanford), an elite think tank (RAND), and a well-respected university known for its religious affiliation and ideological conservatism (Brigham Young). We hoped to mitigate the likelihood that conservative respondents would dismiss the claims made by the hypothetical researchers as a byproduct of supposed liberal academic bias. This means that some of the effects we report below may be understated.

29 We randomized (a) the order of the questions, (b) their framing (positive or negative) and (c) whether the response options ranged from positive to negative or negative to positive.

30 We did not use ideology as our outcome variable in this model because the point of the experiment is not to provide evidence that human nature premises are causally prior to ideology, but rather to assess how the stability of premise beliefs is reflected by those beliefs’ correspondence with ideology.

31 In this instance, we are not concerned about post-treatment bias (e.g., Montgomery, Nyhan and Torres Reference Montgomery, Nyhan and Torres2018), because ideological identification is not a confound; if the experimental treatments were to prompt differences in ideological identification, it would represent even stronger evidence in support of our argument.

32 In an alternative model specification, we remove the covariates from the model. The substantive and statistical relationships of interest are very similar (see Appendix Section IV, Tables A8, A15).

33 We calculated these values and confidence intervals using methods outlined in Brambor, Clark and Golder (Reference Brambor, Clark and Golder2006) and Berry, Golder and Milton (Reference Berry, Golder and Milton2012).

34 It is also worth noting that, as expected, in simple models that do not take account of the experimental treatments, conservatives tend to score about twelve points higher on the cynicism scale than progressives (p < 0.001), holding the demographic covariates constant. See Appendix Tables A9, A16.

References

Abramowitz, AI and Saunders, KL (1998) Ideological realignment in the US electorate. Journal of Politics 32(3), 634652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alford, JR, Funk, C and Hibbing, JR (2005) Are political orientations genetically transmitted? American Political Science Review 99(2), 153167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Altemeyer, RA (1988) Enemies of Freedom: Understanding Right-Wing Authoritarianism. Mississauga: Jossey-Bass.Google Scholar
Altemeyer, RA (1998) The other ‘authoritarian personality.’ Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 30, 4792.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ansolabehere, S Jonathan, R and Snyder, JM Jr (2008) The strength of issues: using multiple measures to gauge preference stability, ideological constraint, and issue voting. American Political Science Review 102(2), 215232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Augustine of Hippo. ~400. The City of God.Google Scholar
Ball, T, Dagger, R and O'Neill, DI (2016) Political Ideologies and the Democratic Ideal. New York: Pearson.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, D and Marietta, M (2020) “Replication Data for “Premise Disputes and Political Ideology””, https://doi.org/10.7910/DVN/2GWLWP, Harvard Dataverse, V1, UNF:6:VBdzHM2sKCMz/mRktukWaw==[fileUNF].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barker, DC and Tinnick, JL II (2006) Competing visions of parental roles and ideological constraint. American Political Science Review 100(2), 249263CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bentler, PM (1990) Comparative fit indexes in structural models. Psychological Bulletin 107(2), 238246.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Berinsky, AJ, Huber, GA and Lenz, G. (2012) Evaluating online labor markets for experimental research: Amazon.com's Mechanical Turk. Political Analysis 20, 351368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berry, WD, Golder, M and Milton, D (2012) Improving tests of theories positing interaction. Journal of Politics 74(03), 653667.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bobbio, N (1997) Left and Right: The Significance of a Political Distinction. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Braithwaite, V (1997) Harmony and security value orientations in political evaluation. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 23(4), 401414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brambor, T, Clark, WR and Golder, M (2006) Understanding interaction models: improving empirical analyses. Political Analysis 14, 6382.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brewer, P and Steenbergen, M (2002) All against all: beliefs about human nature shape foreign policy opinions. Political Psychology 23(1), 3958.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burke, E (1790) Reflections on the Revolution in France. London: J. Dodsley in Pall Mall.Google Scholar
Clifford, S, Jewell, RM and Waggoner, PD (2015) Are samples drawn from Mechanical Turk valid for research on political ideology? Research and Politics 2(4). DOI: 10.1177/2053168015622072.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, GL, Aronson, J and Steele, CM (2000) When beliefs yield to evidence: reducing biased evaluation by affirming the self. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 26(9), 11511164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, GL (2003) Party over policy: the dominating impact of group influence on political beliefs. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 85(5), 808822.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cohen, GL et al. (2007) Bridging the partisan divide: self-affirmation reduces ideological closed-mindedness and inflexibility in negotiation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93(3), 415430.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Conover, PJ and Feldman, SJ (1981) The origins and meaning of liberal/conservative self-identifications. American Journal of Political Science 25(4), 617645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Converse, PE (1964) The nature of belief systems in mass publics. In Apter D, (ed.), Ideology and Discontent. London: Free Press of Glencoe, pp. 206261.Google Scholar
Coughlin, RM and Lockhart, C (1998) Grid-group theory and political ideology: a consideration of their relative strengths and weaknesses for explaining the structure of mass belief systems. Journal of Theoretical Politics 10(1), 3358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
David, CB and Morgan, M (2020) “Replication Data for: Premise Disputes and Political Ideology”, https://dataverse.harvard.edu/dataverse/BJPolS, Harvard Dataverse, V1.Google Scholar
de St. Aubin, . (1996) Personal ideology polarity: its emotional foundation and its manifestation in individual value systems, religiosity, political orientation and assumptions about human nature. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 71, 152165.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Douglas, M (1982) The effects of modernization on religious change. Daedalus 111(1), 119.Google Scholar
Duckitt, J (2001) A dual-process cognitive-motivational theory of ideology and prejudice. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 33, 41113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duckitt, J and Fisher, K (2003) The impact of social threat on worldview and ideological attitudes. Political Psychology 24(1), 199222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellis, C and Stimson, JA (2012) Ideology in America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellis, RJ (1993) American Political Cultures. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Federico, C, Hunt, CV and Ergun, D (2009) Political expertise, social worldviews, and ideology: translating ‘competitive jungles and dangerous worlds’ into ideological reality. Social Justice Research 22(2–3), 259279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, S (1988) Structure and consistency in public opinion: the role of core beliefs and values. American Journal of Political Science 5(1), 416440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, S and Johnston, C (2014) Understanding the determinants of ideology: implications of structural complexity. Political Psychology 35(3), 337358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, S and Steenbergen, M (2001) The humanitarian foundation of support for social welfare. American Journal of Political Science 7(1), 658677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, S and Stenner, K (1997) Perceived threat and authoritarianism. Political Psychology 18(4), 741770.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finucane, ML et al. (2000) Gender, race, and perceived risk: the ‘white male’ effect. Health, Risk, and Society 3(2), 159172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gastil, J et al. (2011) The cultural orientation of mass political opinion. PS: Political Science & Politics 44(4), 711714.Google Scholar
Golding, W (1954). Lord of the Flies. London: Faber and Faber.Google Scholar
Goren, P (2012) On Voter Confidence. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Graham, J, Haidt, J and Nosek, BA (2009) Liberals and conservatives rely on different sets of moral foundations. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 96(5), 10291046.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grendstad, G and Selle, P (2000) Cultural myths of human and physical nature: integrated or separated? Risk Analysis 20(1): 2740.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Haidt, J (2012) The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion. New York: Vintage.Google Scholar
Hetherington, MJ and Weiler, JD (2009) Authoritarianism and Polarization in American Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hibbing, JR, Smith, KB and Alford, JR (2014) Differences in negativity bias underlie variations in political ideology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 297307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hobbes, T (1651) Leviathan.Google Scholar
Hofstede, G (2001) Culture's Consequences: Comparing Values, Behaviors, Institutions and Organizations across Nations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage (co-published in the PRC as Vol. 10 in the Shanghai Foreign Language Education Press SFLEP Intercultural Communication Reference Series, 2008).Google Scholar
Hunter, JD (1992) Culture Wars: The Struggle to Define America. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Hurwitz, J and Peffley, M (1987) How are foreign policy attitudes structured? A hierarchical model. American Political Science Review 81(4), 10991120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, NM (2014) A theory of preference formation among ideologues and non-ideologues. Social Science Quarterly 96(1), 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacoby, WG (1991) Ideological identification and issue attitudes. American Journal of Political Science 35(1), 178205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacoby, WG (1995) The structure of ideological thinking in the mass public. American Journal of Political Science 5(1), 314335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jacoby, WG (2006) Value choices and American public opinion. American Journal of Political Science 50(3), 706723.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jefferson, T (1776) The Unanimous Declaration of the Thirteen United States of America. Washington, DC: United States Congress, National Archives and Records Administration.Google Scholar
Johnson, BB and Swedlow, B (2019) Comparing cultural theory and cultural cognition theory survey measures to each other and as explanations for judged risk. DOI:10.1080/13669877.2019.1646310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jost, JT (2006) The end of the end of ideology. American Psychologist 61(7), 651670.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jost, JT, Federico, CM and Napier, JL (2009) Political ideology: its structure, functions, and elective affinities. Annual Review of Psychology 60, 307337.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jost, JT et al. (2003) Political conservatism as motivated social cognition. Psychological Bulletin 129(3), 339375.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jost, JT et al. (2007) Are needs to manage uncertainty and threat associated with political conservatism or ideological extremity? Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 33(7), 9891007.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahan, DM (2011) Jenkins-Smith, Hank, and Donald Braman. Cultural cognition of scientific consensus. Journal of Risk Research 14, 147174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahan, DM (2013) A risky science communication environment for vaccines. Science 342, 5354.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahan, DM (2016) The politically motivated reasoning paradigm, part 1: what politically motivated reasoning Is and How to measure It. In Scott, R and Kosslyn, S (eds), Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences: An Interdisciplinary, Searchable, and Linkable Resource. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.Google Scholar
Kahan, DM and Braman, D (2003) More statistics, less persuasion: a cultural theory of gun-risk perceptions. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 151, 12911327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahan, DM and Braman, D (2006) Cultural cognition and public policy. Yale Law and Policy Review 24, 147.Google Scholar
Kahan, DM et al. (2007a) Culture and identity-protective cognition: explaining the white-male effect in risk perception. Journal of Empirical Legal Studies Research Paper, 826.Google Scholar
Kahan, DM et al. (2007b) The Second National Risk and Culture Study: Making Sense of – and Making Progress In – the American Culture War of Fact. Washington, DC: George Washington University.Google Scholar
Kahan, DM et al. (2009) Cultural cognition of the risks and benefits of nanotechnology. Nature Nanotechnology 4(87–90).CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahan, DM et al. (2010) Who fears the HPV vaccine, who doesn't, and why? An experimental study of the mechanisms of cultural cognition. Law and Human Behavior 34, 501516.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kahan, DM et al. (2006) Fear of democracy: a cultural critique of Sunstein on risk. Harvard Law Review 119, 10711109.Google Scholar
Kinder, DR and Kalmoe, NP (2017) Neither Liberal nor Conservative: Ideological Innocence in the American Public. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Knight, K (1985) Ideology in the 1980 election: ideological sophistication does matter. The Journal of Politics 47(3), 828853.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kruglanski, AW (1999) Motivation, cognition, and reality: three memos for the next generation of research. Psychological Inquiry 10, 5458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G (1996) Moral Politics: How Liberals and Conservatives Think. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Lane, RE (1962) Political Ideology: Why the American Common Man Believes What He Does. Oxford: Free Press of Glencoe.Google Scholar
Layman, G (2001) The Great Divide: Religious and Cultural Conflict in American Party Politics. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Layman, G and Green, JC (2006) Wars and rumours of wars: the contexts of cultural conflict in American political behavior. British Journal of Political Science 36(1), 6189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levay, KE, Freese, J and Druckman, JN (2016) The demographic and political composition of Mechanical Turk samples. Sage Open 6(1), 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levendusky, M (2009) The Partisan Sort: How Liberals Became Democrats and Conservatives Became Republicans. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, J (2015). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (Vol. 1668). London.Google Scholar
Madison, J (1787) Federalist 10, or the utility of the union as a safeguard against domestic faction and insurrection. The Advertiser (22 November).Google Scholar
Maleki, A and de Jong, M (2014) A proposal for clustering the dimensions of national culture. Cross Cultural Research 48(2), 107143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mandeville, B (1732) The Fable of the Bees: or, Private Vices, Publick Benefits.Google Scholar
Marietta, M (2011) A Citizen's Guide to American Ideology: Conservatism and Liberalism in Contemporary Politics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Marietta, M and Barker, DC (2019) One Nation, Two Realities: Dueling Facts in American Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marx, K and Engels, F (1848) The Communist Manifesto. London: WEA.Google Scholar
McAdams, DP et al. (2008) Family metaphors and moral intuitions: how conservatives and liberals narrate their lives. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 95(4), 978990.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
McCleary, DF and Williams, RL (2009) Sociopolitical and personality correlates of militarism in democratic societies. Peace and Conflict: Journal of Peace Psychology 15(2), 161187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCloskey, H and Zaller, J (1984) The American Ethos: Public Attitudes Toward Capitalism and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montgomery, JM, Nyhan, B and Torres, M (2018) How conditioning on post-treatment variables can ruin your experiment and what to do about It. American Journal of Political Science 62(3), 760775.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pedersen, WS, Muftuler, T and Larson, CL (2017) Conservatism and the neural circuitry of threat: economic conservatism predicts greater amygdala-BNST connectivity during periods of threat vs. safety. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 13(1), 4351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peffley, M and Hurwitz, J (1985) A hierarchical model of attitude constraint. American Journal of Political Science 29(4), 871890.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, S (2018) Enlightenment Now: The Case for Reason, Science, Humanism, and Progress. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
Pjurko, Y, Shalom, H and Davidov, E (2011) Basic personal values and the meaning of political orientations in 20 countries. Political Psychology 32(4), 537561.Google Scholar
Plato (375 BCE) The Republic.Google Scholar
Pratto, F et al. (1994) Social dominance orientation: a personality variable predicting social and political attitudes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 67(4), 741763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rawls, J (1971) A Theory of Justice. New York: Belknap.Google Scholar
Ripberger, JT et al. (2012) Reconsidering the relationship between cultural theory, political ideology, and political knowledge. Social Science Quarterly 93(3), 713731.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rokeach, M (1973) The Nature of Human Values. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Rousseau, JJ (1762) The Social Contract, or Of the Social Contract, or Principles of Political Right.Google Scholar
Schwartz, S (1992) Universals in the content and structure of values: theoretical advances and empirical tests in 20 countries. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 25, 165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, S, Caprera, GV and Vecchione, M (2010) Basic personal values, core political values, and voting: a longitudinal analysis. Political Psychology 31(3), 421452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sears, DO, Huddy, L and Schaffer, L (1986) A schematic variant of symbolic politics theory, as applied to racial and gender equality. Political Cognition, 159202.Google Scholar
Sibley, CG, Wilson, MS and Duckitt, J (2007) Effects of dangerous and competitive worldviews on right-wing authoritarianism and social dominance orientation over a five-month period. Political Psychology 28(3), 357371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidanius, J and Pratto, F (1999) Social Dominance: An Intergroup Theory of Social Hierarchy and Oppression. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, A (1776) An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. London: Strahan and Cadell.Google Scholar
Steg, L and Sievers, I (2000) Cultural theory and individual perceptions of environmental risks. Environment and Behavior 32(2), 250269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stenner, K (2005) The Authoritarian Dynamic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stone, WF and Schaffner, PE (1988) The Psychology of Politics. New York: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, JL, Piereson, J and Marcus, GE (1981) Political Tolerance and American Democracy. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Swedlow, B (2011) A cultural theory of politics. PS: Political Science and Politics 44(4), 703710.Google Scholar
Swedlow, B et al. (2016) Assessing the Validity of Different Approaches to Operationalizing Cultural Theory in Survey Research. SSRN. Available from https://ssrn.com/abstract=2860961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Swedlow, B and Wyckoff, ML (2009) Value preferences and ideological structuring of attitudes in American public opinion. American Politics Research 37(6), 10481087.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tansey, J and Rayner, S (1992) Cultural theory and risk. In Heath, RL and O'Hair, HD (eds), Handbook of Risk and Crisis Communication. New York: Taylor and Francis.Google Scholar
Tesler, M (2015) Priming predispositions and changing policy positions: an account of when mass opinion is primed or changed. American Journal of Political Science 59(4), 806824.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tetlock, PE (1986) A value pluralism model of ideological reasoning. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 50(4), 819827.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, M, Ellis, R and Wildavsky, A (1990) Cultural Theory. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Thucydides. 404 BCE (1910) The Peloponnesian War. The Classic Translation by Richard Crawley. London: J. M. Dent.Google Scholar
Tomkins, SS (1964) Left and right: a basic dimension in personality and ideology. In White, RW (ed.), The Study of Lives. New York: Atherton.Google Scholar
Treier, S and Sunshine Hillygus, D (2009) The nature of ideology in the contemporary electorate. Public Opinion Quarterly 73(4), 679703.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tversky, A and Kahneman, D (1973) Availability – heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology 5, 207232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wildavsky, A (1998) Culture and Social Theory. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.Google Scholar
Wildavsky, A and Dake, K (1990) Theories of risk perception: who fears what and why? Daedalus 119(4), 4160.Google Scholar
Will, GF (2019) The Conservative Sensibility. New York: Hachette Books.Google Scholar
Williams, P (2008) America's Religions, 3rd Edn, Urbana-Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
Wittkopf, ER (1990) Faces of Internationalism: Public Opinion and American Foreign Policy. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Xue, W et al. (2014) Cultural worldviews and environmental risk perceptions: a meta-analysis. Journal of Environmental Psychology 40, 249258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoon, KI (2014) Political psychology of individualism and collectivism. Journal of International and Area Studies 21(2), 4564.Google Scholar
Zaller, J and Feldman, S (1992) A simple theory of the survey response: answering questions versus revealing preferences. American Journal of Political Science 36(3), 579616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Confirmatory factor analyses: model comparison

Figure 1

Table 2. Premise disputes, value conflicts and liberalism–conservatism

Figure 2

Table 3. 2014 Linear regression analyses of ideological sub-dimensions (Economic, Cultural, Security)

Figure 3

Figure 1. Premise prompts and cynicism toward human nature among liberals and conservativesNote: differences in human nature sanguinity-cynicism associated with exposure to the experimental treatments, among liberals and conservatives.

Supplementary material: Link

Barker and Marietta Dataset

Link
Supplementary material: File

Barker and Marietta Supplementary Materials

Barker and Marietta Supplementary Materials

Download Barker and Marietta Supplementary Materials(File)
File 99.3 KB