Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T08:44:14.834Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What's not music, but feels like music to you?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 September 2021

Vijay Iyer*
Affiliation:
Department of Music & Department of African and African American Studies, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA02138, USA. vijayiyer@fas.harvard.edu; www.vijay-iyer.com

Abstract

The category “music” as used in this area of science is inconsistent and unstable, and its logical relationship to the word “musicality” – used by scientists to denote the human capacity for music – is circular. Therefore, rather than pursue the question, “Why did music(ality) evolve?” let us ask more inclusively, “What experiences in humankind's deep past might have felt like music?”

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

I am a music-maker who likes to explore the limits of what I think music is (Iyer, Reference Iyer2017, Reference Iyer2021; Iyer & Smith, Reference Iyer and Smith2016; Iyer & Taborn, Reference Iyer and Taborn2019). I am also a music scholar, and I have offered critical perspectives on the music cognition since the 1990s (Iyer, Reference Iyer1998, Reference Iyer2002, Reference Iyer2004, Reference Iyer, Lewis and Piekut2016, Reference Iyer, Rehding and Rings2020a, Reference Iyer2020b). I have long argued for an embodied understanding of music as, first and foremost, human action: the sounds of bodies in motion. As composer-pianist Cecil Taylor once put it, music is “everything that you do” (Mann, Reference Mann1981).

I'm not here to assess the relative scientific merits of these papers. I am not an evolutionary scientist, nor am I invested in the research question of why music might have evolved. Instead, I wish to scrutinize some assumptions underlying both articles. I submit that (1) the category “music” as used in this area of science is inconsistent and unstable, (2) its logical relationship to the word “musicality” – used by scientists to denote the “human capacity for music” – is circular (Iyer & Born, Reference Iyer and Born2020), and (3) this circularity conceals a problem at the heart of this scientific enterprise, namely that its very object of study does not strictly exist, but rather is constructed and managed through scientific discourse.

An influential study by Mehr et al. (Reference Mehr, Singh, Knox, Ketter, Pickens-Jones, Atwood and Glowacki2019), cited in both papers, drew from a massive corpus of “human song”: field recordings described with tags such as “song,” “voice,” “vocal,” and so forth. Although its purview is immense, it expressly does not include purely instrumental music. Yet, the domain of this study has been routinely conflated with the larger category of “music,” as is done in Table 1 of the current study by Savage et al. This category called music, however, apparently does not include poetic or rhythmic speech: in their current study, for example, Mehr et al. assert that a coxswain (whose rhythmic chanting coordinates rowers) “does not sing” and should, therefore, be taken as an example of “an alternative to music,” namely, language. Meanwhile, Savage et al. posit that we should include dance as “a core part of music-making.”

The pattern here is that common human behaviors are freely added to or subtracted from the category of music by scientists as a matter of course. These unpredictable inclusions and exclusions are presented as if normal, even commonsensical. Such arbitrary assertions cause a humanist's ears to perk up, for they are a telltale sign of what Michel Foucault (Reference Foucault1972) called a discursive formation: an accumulation of statements insistently held together, less by facts than by language, desire, and power. By extension, if musicality is defined as the species-wide capacity for making music, and music is then defined as (an arbitrarily delimited subset of) the diverse range of outcomes of that capacity known as musicality, then these two definitions orbit, reinforce, and validate each other, but do not resolve onto a definable, consistent, or stable object of study.

We can historicize our contemporary use of the word “music,” analyzing it as a contingent, historically specific concept. Our understanding of music today is bound up with our technologically mediated, market-dependent listening experiences, which condition us to think of music as an object or substance that is nameable and consumable (see, e.g., Sterne, Reference Sterne2003). Our conception of music additionally depends on western epistemologies of aurality (Erlmann, Reference Erlmann2010; Ochoa Gautier, Reference Ochoa Gautier2014), instrumentality (Dolan, Reference Dolan2013), and humanity/animality (Jackson, Reference Jackson2020; Mundy, Reference Mundy2018; Wynter, Reference Wynter2003) that emerged in the last half-millennium of European imperialism, “exploration,” “enlightenment,” enslavement, genocide, and extraction. As European “explorers” encountered their racialized others, they believed indigenous people to be at the edge of the human category, and took their musical behaviors as noise; they, like today's scientists, discursively delimited what human music must and must not be (Mundy, Reference Mundy2018; Ochoa Gautier, Reference Ochoa Gautier2014).

Instead, we must listen beyond our last century of sound mediation, beyond the last five centuries of racial capitalism that undergird western science and reason (Robinson, Reference Robinson1983/2000), and reexamine what music might have been on the timescale of 100,000 years – the era of human sociality, as evidenced in the remains of Blombos Cave (Henshilwood et al., Reference Henshilwood, d'Errico, van Niekerk, Coquinot, Jacobs, Lauritzen, Menu and García-Moreno2011; Wynter & McKittrick, Reference Wynter, McKittrick and McKittrick2015).

Recently, I posed a question on Twitter (Iyer, Reference Iyer2020b): “What's not music, but feels like music to you?” This post received an avalanche of responses: “Cooking.” “A really good conversation.” “Longing.” “Dancing, weather, grandparents.” “People being insulted in Yoruba.” “Construction sites.” “Water droplets, door creaks, astrological planet alignments, white noise, difference tones.” “My youngest son's gentle snore, my older son's footsteps, my daughter's laughter.” “The wind through desiccating leaves.” “Dogs barking.” “The unfolding of an exquisite meal.” “Shafts of sunlight through slow-moving clouds.” “Astrology, Astrophysics, Poetry, the crunch of leaves on a crisp Chicago autumn day, looking deeply in the eyes of a lover, traffic.” “The groove a washing machine or dishwasher gets into.” “The ocean.” “Love.” “Memories.” “Rollercoasters.” “Touch.” “Thought.” “Everything.” Hundreds of people from around the planet offered examples of what “feels like music,” illuminating the contested edges of the category, tracing out a larger space of musical mattering: affectively charged attending to phenomenological experience. These included human and nonhuman actions, complex sensations, emotions, thoughts, and meaningful social relations among people. The category of music encompasses many behaviors, but it is also surrounded by a vast sea of experiences that “feel like” they belong in the category too.

Therefore, rather than pursue the question, “Why did music(-ality) evolve?” let us ask more inclusively, “What experiences in humankind's deep past might have felt like music, and how, and why?” Feelings are not scientifically trivial; they are ongoing bodily activation at the intersection of biology and culture. As the tweets revealed, virtually any experience can “feel like music” to somebody; and they cannot be proven wrong, for music is felt into being. We must, therefore, treat the category of music(ality) not as one that coheres as the direct effect of a specific cause (be it social bonding, credible signaling, or anything else), but instead as a sphere of experience, opening out endlessly to human possibility.

Financial support

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Conflict of interest

None.

References

Dolan, E. (2013). The orchestral revolution: Haydn and the technologies of timbre. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Erlmann, V. (2010). Reason and resonance: A history of modern aurality. Zone Books.Google Scholar
Foucault, M. (1972). The archaeology of knowledge and The discourse on language. Translated by A.M.S. Smith. Pantheon Books.Google Scholar
Henshilwood, C., d'Errico, F., van Niekerk, K. L., Coquinot, Y., Jacobs, Z., Lauritzen, S.-E., Menu, M., & García-Moreno, R., (2011). A 100,000-year-old ochre-processing workshop at Blombos Cave, South Africa. Science (New York, N.Y.), 334(6053), 219222.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Iyer, V. (1998). Microstructures of Feel, Macrostructures of Sound: Embodied Cognition in West African and African-American Musics. (Publication No. 9922889). Ph.D. Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley. ProQuest Dissertations & Theses Global.Google Scholar
Iyer, V. (2002). Embodied mind, situated cognition, and expressive microtiming in African-American music. Music Perception, 19(3), 387414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iyer, V. (2004). Improvisation, temporality, and embodied experience. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11(3–4), 159173.Google Scholar
Iyer, V. (2016). Improvisation, action understanding, and music cognition with and without bodies. In Lewis, G. E. & Piekut, B. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of critical improvisation studies (pp. 7490). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Iyer, V. (2017). Far from over (sound recording). ECM Records.Google Scholar
Iyer, V. (2020a). Beneath improvisation. In Rehding, A. & Rings, S. (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of critical concepts in music theory (pp. 761774). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Iyer, V. (2020b). What's not music but feels like music to you [Tweet]. Twitter. Retrieved from https://twitter.com/vijayiyer/status/1327294519457554432.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Iyer, V. (2021). Uneasy (sound recording). ECM Records.Google Scholar
Iyer, V., & Born, G. (2020). Of musicalities and musical experience: Vijay Iyer and Georgina Born in conversation. Wigmore Hall Podcasts. Retrieved from https://wigmore-hall.org.uk/podcasts/of-musicalities-and-musical-experience-vijay-iyer-and-georgina-born-in-conversation.Google Scholar
Iyer, V., & Smith, W. L. (2016). A cosmic rhythm with each stroke (sound recording). ECM Records.Google Scholar
Iyer, V., & Taborn, C. (2019). The transitory poems (sound recording). ECM Records.Google Scholar
Jackson, Z. I. (2020). Becoming human: Matter and meaning in an antiblack world. NYU Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mann, R. (1981). Imagine the sound (documentary feature film). Janus Films.Google Scholar
Mehr, S. A., Singh, M., Knox, D., Ketter, D. M., Pickens-Jones, D., Atwood, S., … Glowacki, L., (2019). Universality and diversity in human song. Science, 366(6468), 957970.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mundy, R. (2018). Animal musicalities: Birds, beasts, and evolutionary listening. Wesleyan University Press.Google Scholar
Ochoa Gautier, A. M. (2014). Aurality: Listening and knowledge in nineteenth-century Colombia. Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, C. (with Kelley, R. D. G.) (2000). Black marxism. University of North Carolina Press. (Original work published 1983).Google Scholar
Sterne, J. (2003). The audible past: Cultural origins of sound reproduction. Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Wynter, S. (2003). Unsettling the coloniality of being/power/truth/freedom: Towards the human, after man, its overrepresentation – an argument. CR: The New Centennial Review, 3(3), 257337. Coloniality's persistence (fall 2003).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wynter, S., & McKittrick, K. (2015). Unparalleled catastrophe for our species? Or, to give humanness a different future: Conversations. In McKittrick, K. (Ed.), Sylvia Wynter: On being human as praxis (pp. 989). Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar