Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T19:06:19.499Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The urge to judge: Why the judgmental attitude has anything to do with the aesthetic enjoyment of negative emotions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 November 2017

Elvira Brattico
Affiliation:
Center for Music in the Brain (MIB), Department of Clinical Medicine, Aarhus University, The Royal Academy of Music Aarhus/Aalborg, 8000 Aarhus C, Denmark. elvira.brattico@clin.au.dkpv@musikkons.dkmusicinthebrain.au.dk
Peter Vuust
Affiliation:
Center for Music in the Brain (MIB), Department of Clinical Medicine, Aarhus University, The Royal Academy of Music Aarhus/Aalborg, 8000 Aarhus C, Denmark. elvira.brattico@clin.au.dkpv@musikkons.dkmusicinthebrain.au.dk

Abstract

Based on arguments from both philosophical and empirical aesthetics, we hereby propose that the enjoyment of negative emotions in art and fiction is distinct from the immediate pleasure deriving from sensory features, because it requires a conscious, intentional attitude toward the object. This attitude is linked with the compelling goal of providing a judgment of liking, beauty, perfection, or similar.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2017 

The model proposed by Menninghaus et al. is well constructed and comprehensive toward explaining the paradoxical phenomenon of enjoyment of negative emotions in art. They put forward two processing factors, each including several components. The Distancing factor, consisting of the cognitive schemata of art, representation, and fiction, modifies the appraisal of negative emotions, keeping them at some “psychological distance.” The Embracing factor, consisting of the interplays of positive and negative feelings, mixed emotions, aesthetic virtues, meaning construction, and genre scripts, is what allows the integration of negative emotions into the aesthetic experience, modifying them into a pleasurable and rewarding affective outcome.

But what kind of pleasure or enjoyment is derived from or co-occurs with negative emotions? Kant has already described the aesthetic pleasure that we take in beauty as essentially different from the pleasure of mere sensory gratification, such as in eating or drinking (Kant Reference Kant and Bernard1951; Zangwill Reference Zangwill and Zalta2014). More recently, within the field of empirical aesthetics the pleasure from art has been linked with our “knowledge instinct” (Perlovsky Reference Perlovsky2010; Reference Perlovsky2014), namely, an inborn drive for cognition that “compels us to constantly improve our knowledge of the world” (Perlovsky Reference Perlovsky, Perlovsky and Kozma2007, p. 73). In the broader field of affective neuroscience, pleasure has been distinguished into “core” and “conscious” pleasures (Brattico Reference Brattico, Nadal, Houston, Agnati, Mora and Conde2015; Kringelbach & Berridge Reference Kringelbach and Berridge2009). We have proposed a similar distinction for the type of pleasure that is experienced as a consequence of exposure to art objects (Brattico Reference Brattico, Nadal, Houston, Agnati, Mora and Conde2015). Core or sensory pleasure is immediately and involuntarily activated by the sensory properties of the stimulus, and it is associated with the fast firing of dopaminergic neurons of the mesolimbic and nigrostriatal pathways, which, in turn, modulate the neuroendocrine, visceral, and muscle responses of the autonomous nervous system, hence altering the bodily state. A slower, voluntary pathway, recruiting frontal lobe structures, mediates instead conscious pleasure or enjoyment. Also, in philosophical aesthetics, scholars postulate the pivotal role of contemplation, intentionality, and cognition in explaining aesthetic pleasure (Bundgaard Reference Bundgaard2015; Fenner Reference Fenner1996; Kemp Reference Kemp1999). In our previous work, we put forward a spatiotemporal road map of aesthetic processes related to music in particular, discerning between involuntary, low-level perceptual-emotional stages and reflective processes involving cognitive control and leading to the three main outcomes of an aesthetic experience: aesthetic emotion, preference or conscious liking, and aesthetic judgment (Brattico Reference Brattico, Nadal, Houston, Agnati, Mora and Conde2015; Brattico & Jacobsen, Reference Brattico and Jacobsen2009; Brattico et al. Reference Brattico, Brattico and Jacobsen2009–2010; Brattico et al. Reference Brattico, Bogert and Jacobsen2013; Nieminen et al. Reference Nieminen, Istok, Brattico, Tervaniemi and Huotilainen2011; Reybrouck & Brattico Reference Reybrouck and Brattico2015). These early and late processes are guided by what has been termed “focus” (Hodges Reference Hodges, Hallam, Cross and Thaut2016), “aesthetic stance” (Bundgaard Reference Bundgaard2015), and “aesthetic attitude” (Fenner Reference Fenner1996), namely, the intentional act of paying attention and preparing oneself for the contemplation and judgment of a work of art.

In cognitive neuroscience, experiments in which two tasks are contrasted with each other have probed the discernible neural mechanisms underlying aesthetic versus nonaesthetic modes of stimulus processing. For instance, the use of a visual paradigm comprising a task in which participants passively viewed abstract black and white patterns and another task in which participants were asked to contemplate the patterns aesthetically (to reflect on their beauty, but without giving an overt judgment) revealed that evaluative processes occurred during contemplation only and not during mere viewing, as indexed by the late positive electric brain response visible only in the contemplation condition (Höfel & Jacobsen Reference Höfel and Jacobsen2007). Furthermore, in this experiment the “not beautiful” patterns did not elicit the early frontocentral negative electric response indexing impression formation that has previously been observed in tasks involving overt aesthetic judgments (Brattico et al. Reference Brattico, Jacobsen, De Baene, Glerean and Tervaniemi2010; Jacobsen & Höfel Reference Jacobsen and Höfel2003). These findings point to a separation between mechanisms for aesthetic mode, namely, the central processes of thinking about aesthetic value, and those related to deciding on an aesthetic judgment. In other neurophysiological experiments using auditory dual-task paradigms, early negative neural responses to aesthetic versus nonaesthetic tasks differed significantly from each other even before a cognitive judgment of correctness or an aesthetic judgment of beauty or liking was provided, and despite the fact that the same sound stimuli were listened to in both tasks (Brattico et al. Reference Brattico, Jacobsen, De Baene, Glerean and Tervaniemi2010; Muller et al. Reference Muller, Höfel, Brattico and Jacobsen2010). These results indicate that an initial mode or attitude toward the object to be judged is taken, and this attitude conditions the neural mechanisms that prepare for subsequent aesthetic decisions. Similarly, neuroimaging studies consistently have demonstrated that the brain structures recruited during voluntary enjoyment of artworks, such as the orbitofrontal cortex, ventral striatum, thalamus, insula, and cingulate cortex, are separated from those associated with either unconscious pleasure or other basic emotions (sadness, happiness) (Brattico et al. Reference Brattico, Bogert, Alluri, Tervaniemi, Eerola and Jacobsen2016).

Hence, based on these arguments and empirical evidence, it is reasonable to propose that the intentional act to immerse in an art experience is a precondition for the enjoyment that might co-occur or follow negative emotions. Moreover, we suggest that this enjoyment is intrinsically judgmental; namely, it is glued with the compelling goal of providing a final judgment of liking, beauty, perfection, or similar. Without a proper attitude aimed at providing a final judgment on a work of art or fiction, the immediate response to a negative emotion could be a quick withdrawal, even when taking into account the Distancing factor. In the best cases, the outcome of this situation is a liking or aesthetic judgment, that can be (in various degrees) felt in the body and brain. In other cases, the outcome can even be detached from any feelings, namely, from any change in bodily state linked to neural activation of dopaminergic reward pathways, but instead be restricted to a mere cognitive decision of aesthetic value of an artwork, resulting in the willingness to repeat the experience in the future. And sometimes, a (positive) judgment is already taken even before looking at the (emotionally negative) painting, watching the (horror) movie, or listening to a (dissonant) musical piece, because of prior attitudes, culture, preferences (Gebauer et al. Reference Gebauer, Kringelbach and Vuust2012), and group belonging (Wohl Reference Wohl2015).

References

Brattico, E. (2015) From pleasure to liking and back: Bottom-up and top-down neural routes to the aesthetic enjoyment of music. In: Art, aesthetics, and the brain, ed. Nadal, M., Houston, J. P., Agnati, L., Mora, F. & Conde, C. J. Cela, pp. 303–18. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brattico, E., Bogert, B., Alluri, V., Tervaniemi, M., Eerola, T. & Jacobsen, T. (2016) It's sad but I like it: The neural dissociation between musical emotions and liking in experts and laypersons. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9:676. Available at: http://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2015.00676.Google Scholar
Brattico, E., Bogert, B. & Jacobsen, T. (2013) Toward a neural chronometry for the aesthetic experience of music. Frontiers in Psychology 4:206. Available at: http://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00206.Google Scholar
Brattico, E., Brattico, P. & Jacobsen, T. (2009–2010) The origins of the aesthetic enjoyment of music – A review of the literature. Musicae Scientiae, Special Issue 2009–2010:1531.Google Scholar
Brattico, E. & Jacobsen, T. (2009) Subjective appraisal of music: Neuroimaging evidence. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1169:308–17. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1749-6632.2009.04843.x.Google Scholar
Brattico, E., Jacobsen, T., De Baene, W., Glerean, E. & Tervaniemi, M. (2010) Cognitive vs. affective listening modes and judgments of music – An ERP study. Biological Psychology 85(3):393409. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.biopsycho.2010.08.014.Google Scholar
Bundgaard, H. (2015) Feeling, meaning, and intentionality – A critique of the neuroaesthetics of beauty. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 14:781801.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fenner, D. (1996) The aesthetic attitude. Humanities.Google Scholar
Gebauer, L. K., Kringelbach, M. L. & Vuust, P. (2012) Ever-changing cycles of musical pleasure: The role of dopamine and anticipation. Psychomusicology 22(2):152–67.Google Scholar
Hodges, D. A. (2016) The neuroaesthetics of music. In: The Oxford handbook of music psychology, ed. Hallam, S., Cross, I. & Thaut, M., pp. 247–72. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Höfel, L. & Jacobsen, T. (2007) Electrophysiological indices of processing aesthetics: Spontaneous or intentional processes? International Journal of Psychophysiology 65(1):2031.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Jacobsen, T. & Höfel, L. (2003) Descriptive and evaluative judgment processes: Behavioral and electrophysiological indices of processing symmetry and aesthetics. Cognitive, Affective, and Behavioral Neuroscience 3:289–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kant, I. (1951) Critique of judgement, trans. & ed. Bernard, J. H.. Hafner.Google Scholar
Kemp, G. (1999) The aesthetic attitude. British Journal of Aesthetics 39(4):392–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kringelbach, M. L. & Berridge, K. C. (2009) Towards a functional neuroanatomy of pleasure and happiness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13(11):479–87.Google Scholar
Muller, M., Höfel, L., Brattico, E. & Jacobsen, T. (2010) Aesthetic judgments of music in experts and laypersons – An ERP study. International Journal of Psychophysiology 76(1):4051. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2010.02.002.Google Scholar
Nieminen, S., Istok, E., Brattico, E., Tervaniemi, M. & Huotilainen, M. (2011) The development of aesthetic responses to music and their underlying neural and psychological mechanisms. Cortex 47(9):1138–46. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.cortex.2011.05.008.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. (2007) Neural dynamic logic of consciousness: The knowledge instinct. In: Neurodynamics of cognition and consciousness, ed. Perlovsky, L. & Kozma, R., pp. 73108. Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perlovsky, L. (2010) Musical emotions: Functions, origins, evolution. Physics Life Reviews 7(1):227. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1016/j.plrev.2009.11.001.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. (2014) Aesthetic emotions, what are their cognitive functions? Frontiers in Psychology 5:98. Available at: http://doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00098.Google Scholar
Reybrouck, M. & Brattico, E. (2015) Neuroplasticity beyond sounds: Neural adaptations following long-term musical aesthetic experiences. Brain Sciences 5(1):6991. Available at: http://doi.org/10.3390/brainsci5010069.Google Scholar
Wohl, H. (2015) Community sense: The cohesive power of aesthetic judment. Sociological Theory 33(4):299326.Google Scholar
Zangwill, N. (2014) Aesthetic judgment. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy, Fall 2014 edition, ed. Zalta, E. N.. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/aesthetic-judgment/.Google Scholar