Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-mzp66 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-10T15:36:55.810Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The nature of the semantic/episodic memory distinction: A missing piece of the “working through” process

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 June 2015

Stanley B. Klein
Affiliation:
Department of Psychological and Brain Sciences, University of California at Santa Barbara, Santa Barbara, CA 93106. stan.klein@psych.ucsb.eduhttps://www.psych.ucsb.edu/people/faculty/klein
Hans J. Markowitsch
Affiliation:
Physiological Psychology, University of Bielefeld, 33739 Bielefeld, Germany. hjmarkowitsch@uni-bielefeld.dehttp://www.uni-bielefeld.de/psychologie/personen/ae14/markowitsch.html Center of Excellence, Cognitive Interaction Technology, University of Bielefeld, 33739 Bielefeld, Germany.

Abstract

The relations between the semantic and episodic-autobiographical memory systems are more complex than described in the target article. We argue that understanding the noetic/autonoetic distinction provides critical insights into the foundation of the delineation between the two memory systems. Clarity with respect to the criteria for classification of these two systems, and the evolving conceptualization of episodic memory, can further neuroscientifically informed therapeutic approaches.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Lane et al. have done a valuable service analyzing therapeutic interventions that trade on the conceptual re-categorization of trauma experiences. Their work sheds new light on how memory-updating processes contribute to the mechanisms underlying positive therapeutic change.

Although we applaud their efforts, there are aspects of their model – in particular their conceptualization of memory – we feel merit attention. We focus on an issue we feel to be of critical importance – that is, to what do the authors refer by the terms episodic and semantic memory? Does their usage cut nature at its Platonic joints?

Because their model pivots on these constructs, conceptual precision is a matter of focal concern. We limit our critique to discussion of the conceptual criteria the authors adopt to differentiate the contributions of episodic and semantic memory to the therapeutic process. A salutary consequence of this focus is that, in the process, definitional concerns also are given a voice.

In 1985, Tulving found it necessary to downplay his original three-pronged criterion of memory-types (whereas episodic memory contains spatial and self-referential content, but semantic memory largely is devoid of such contextual content; Tulving Reference Tulving, Tulving and Donaldson1972) in favor of a partitioning predicated on the manner in which content is made available to consciousness (i.e., his autonoetic/noetic awareness distinction; e.g., Tulving Reference Tulving1985; Reference Tulving, Terrace and Metcalfe2005). One problem with the original criteria was that since the early 1980s it repeatedly had been demonstrated that self-referential, spatial, and temporal information can characterize both episodic and semantic memory (for recent review, see Klein Reference Klein2013). Accordingly, a dichotomy between semantic and episodic memory admits to considerable ambiguity when analysis of mental content serves as the basis for categorization. For example, I can know that I drove past a bookstore in Flagstaff, Arizona, on my way to the Grand Canyon in 1989 (i.e., knowledge contextualized with respect to time, space, and self) without being able to episodically recollect (i.e., re-live) the act of having done so.

Although Lane et al. mention Tulving's (Reference Tulving1985) experiential revision, they frequently revert to the idea that episodic and semantic memories are empirically separable in virtue of the content made available to awareness. This simply will not do. It is the manner in which autonoetic and noetic awareness are conjoined with content during the act of retrieval, not the content per se, which determines how a memory experience is categorized (Klein Reference Klein2013; Markowitsch & Staniloiu Reference Markowitsch and Staniloiu2011b).

Based on these concerns, it becomes apparent why a number of the authors' assertions – for example, that episodic memory (or as we currently favor to term it: episodic-autobiographical memory; Markowitsch & Staniloiu Reference Markowitsch and Staniloiu2011b; Reference Markowitsch and Staniloiu2012) entails recollection of “events” – appear unwarranted. For example, although “single events” can be the target content of recollection, mental states that do not entail memory of events can as well. Thus, I can episodically recollect that a word appeared on a list (as opposed to simply knowing that it appeared, or feeling it to be familiar). This hardly does justice to the meaning of “event.” Problems such as this stem from a failure to distinguish the content of an occurrent mental state from the manner in which that state is given to awareness (e.g., Klein Reference Klein2013, Reference Klein2014; Markowitsch & Staniloiu Reference Markowitsch and Staniloiu2011b): It is the autonoetic aspect of retrieval, not simply the content of retrieval, that makes a mental state an episodic (-autobiographical) experience (see Fig. 1).

Figure 1. Sketch of the division into semantic and episodic-autobiographical memory. The figure includes ideas from Klein and Nichols (Reference Klein and Nichols2012), Markowitsch and Staniloiu (Reference Markowitsch and Staniloiu2012), and Picard et al. (Reference Picard, Mayor-Dubois, Maeder, Kalenzaga, Abram, Duval, Eustache, Roulet-Perez and Piolino2013).

Consider, for example, individuals who suffer profound retrograde episodic-autobiographical amnesia, such as patient A. Z. (Markowitsch & Staniloiu Reference Markowitsch and Staniloiu2013). Despite of his inability to episodically recollect any personal experiences, he was able to re-learn specific temporal and spatial details of his personal past and also knew details about celebrities. However, he experienced this content as semantic facts rather than episodic-autobiographical recollections. Similarly, Klein and Nichols (Reference Klein and Nichols2012) presented patient R. B., who temporarily lost his ability to conjoin autoneotic awareness with occurrent mental content. He could remember richly contextual details of his past experiences, but he did not take those details to be personal memory (he stated his “memory” experiences felt unowned – they seemed like facts he had been told by others, lacking the warmth and intimacy associated with episodic-autobiographical recollection; (e.g., James Reference James1890). However, when his autonoetic abilities returned, these same details were now experienced as re-living personal memories.

To generalize, in both organic and dissociative amnesia there is overwhelming evidence for a differentiation between largely preserved semantic memory (see Fig. 1) and largely impaired episodic-autobiographical memory (Markowitsch & Staniloiu Reference Markowitsch and Staniloiu2012; Staniloiu & Markowitsch Reference Staniloiu and Markowitsch2014). This general observation furthermore strongly supports Tulving's (Reference Tulving1985) distinction between these two memory systems and speaks against the use of the term “‘declarative memory’” as an umbrella of the two (cf. also Tulving & Markowitsch Reference Tulving and Markowitsch1998).

Of course, Tulving's autonoetic/noetic criterion presents serious – though not intractable (e.g., the remember/know paradigm) – difficulties for empiricism, because it trades on the subjectivity of the remembering agent. However, current methodological limitations should not sanction avoidance of core properties of the construct(s) under scrutiny (e.g., Klein Reference Klein2014). If current methods are inadequate, the appropriate scientific move is to adapt method, not to excuse foundational aspects of a construct from empirical analysis.

In conclusion, the authors' model adds to existing work on the memorial underpinnings of traumatic disorders in important ways. Although other researchers have focused on the etiology and therapeutic resolution of the traumatic effects of disturbing memories (e.g., Brewin et al. Reference Brewin, Gregory, Lipton and Burgess2010; Ehlers & Clark Reference Ehlers and Clark2000; Rubin et al. Reference Rubin, Berntsen and Bohni2008), the reconsolidation hypothesis presents a more sophisticated treatment of the memorial contributions to both the trauma experience and the recovery process.

However, because the model is grounded by the notions of episodic(-autobiographical) and semantic memory, it is incumbent on the authors' to provide a conceptually coherent and empirically warranted treatment of these focal constructs. Absent such a clarification, the present model, though perhaps therapeutically efficacious, ultimately will be found limited in its generalizability by the failure to situate its foundational constructs in a solid theoretical framework.

References

Brewin, C. R., Gregory, J., Lipton, M. & Burgess, N. (2010) Intrusive images in psychological disorders: Characteristics, neural mechanisms, and treatment implications. Psychological Review 117:210–32. Available at: http://doi.org/10.1037/a0018113 Google Scholar
Ehlers, A. & Clark, D. M. (2000) A cognitive model of posttraumatic stress disorder. Behavior Research and Therapy 38:319–45.Google Scholar
James, W. (1890) Principles of psychology, vol. 1. Henry Holt.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, S. B. (2013) Making the case that episodic recollection is attributable to operations occurring at retrieval rather than to content stored in a dedicated subsystem of long-term memory. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience 7:3. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, S. B. (2014) The two selves: Their metaphysical commitments and functional independence. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Klein, S. B. & Nichols, S. (2012) Memory and the sense of personal identity. Mind 121:677702.Google Scholar
Markowitsch, H. J. & Staniloiu, A. (2011b) Memory, autonoetic consciousness, and the self. Consciousness and Cognition 20:1639.Google Scholar
Markowitsch, H. J. & Staniloiu, A. (2012) Amnesic disorders. Lancet 380(9851):1229–40.Google Scholar
Markowitsch, H. J. & Staniloiu, A. (2013) The impairment of recollection in functional amnesic states. Cortex 49(6):1494–510.Google Scholar
Picard, L., Mayor-Dubois, C., Maeder, P., Kalenzaga, S., Abram, M., Duval, C., Eustache, F., Roulet-Perez, E. & Piolino, P. (2013) Functional independence within the self-memory system: New insights from two cases of developmental amnesia. Cortex 49:1463–81.Google Scholar
Rubin, D. C., Berntsen, D. & Bohni, M. K. (2008) A memory-based model of posttraumatic stress disorder: Evaluating basic assumptions underlying PTSD diagnosis. Psychological Review 115:9851011.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Staniloiu, A. & Markowitsch, H. J. (2014) Dissociative amnesia. Lancet Psychiatry 1:226–41.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. (1972) Episodic and semantic memory. In: Organization of memory, ed. Tulving, E. & Donaldson, W., pp. 381403. Academic.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. (1985) How many memory systems are there? American Psychologist 40:385–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tulving, E. (2005) Episodic memory and autonoesis: Uniquely human? In: The missing link in cognition: Origins of self-selective consciousness, ed. Terrace, H. S. & Metcalfe, J., pp. 356. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tulving, E. & Markowitsch, H. J. (1998) Episodic and declarative memory: Role of the hippocampus. Hippocampus 8:198204.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1. Sketch of the division into semantic and episodic-autobiographical memory. The figure includes ideas from Klein and Nichols (2012), Markowitsch and Staniloiu (2012), and Picard et al. (2013).