Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T02:58:04.027Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Language as a mental travel guide

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 June 2020

Charles P. Davis
Affiliation:
Department of Psychological Sciences, University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT06269charles.davis@uconn.edu gerry.altmann@uconn.edu eiling.yee@uconn.edu http://charlespdavis.com http://altmann.lab.uconn.edu http://yeelab.uconn.edu Connecticut Institute for the Brain and Cognitive Sciences, University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT06269
Gerry T. M. Altmann
Affiliation:
Department of Psychological Sciences, University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT06269charles.davis@uconn.edu gerry.altmann@uconn.edu eiling.yee@uconn.edu http://charlespdavis.com http://altmann.lab.uconn.edu http://yeelab.uconn.edu Connecticut Institute for the Brain and Cognitive Sciences, University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT06269
Eiling Yee
Affiliation:
Department of Psychological Sciences, University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT06269charles.davis@uconn.edu gerry.altmann@uconn.edu eiling.yee@uconn.edu http://charlespdavis.com http://altmann.lab.uconn.edu http://yeelab.uconn.edu Connecticut Institute for the Brain and Cognitive Sciences, University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT06269

Abstract

Gilead et al.'s approach to human cognition places abstraction and prediction at the heart of “mental travel” under a “representational diversity” perspective that embraces foundational concepts in cognitive science. But, it gives insufficient credit to the possibility that the process of abstraction produces a gradient, and underestimates the importance of a highly influential domain in predictive cognition: language, and related, the emergence of experientially based structure through time.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2020. Published by Cambridge University Press

Transcending the present moment – referred to by Gilead et al. as “mental travel” – is indisputably central to human thought: It encompasses not only predicting the future, but also traversing distance on several other psychological dimensions. In order to predict, we need to abstract, and in order to abstract, Gilead et al. argue, we rely on a diverse toolkit comprising three distinct levels of representation. We are skeptical that there exist qualitatively distinct levels of a representational hierarchy, and instead suggest a graded continuum from “modality-specific” to “categorical” representations. Further, we contend that a key factor in promoting development of this gradient – underappreciated in the proposed toolkit – is language.

As Gilead et al. suggest, a consequence of the drive to reduce prediction error is the emergence of representation at multiple levels of abstraction. But, these levels need not be qualitatively distinct: for example, evidence suggests that conceptual knowledge is represented on a posterior-to-anterior gradient along the temporal lobe, with modality-specific information becoming less salient more anteriorly (e.g., beagle–dog–animal; for a review, see Davis & Yee Reference Davis and Yee2019). Critically, the role language plays in processes of abstraction and prediction deserves greater recognition (for discussion, see Yee Reference Yee2019). Language is perhaps the quintessential example from human cognitive behavior of (levels of) abstraction, prediction, and the relationship between them. Both language comprehension and production may build on more general predictive mechanisms involved in action planning and understanding (e.g., Pickering & Garrod Reference Pickering and Garrod2013; see also Altmann & Ekves Reference Altmann and Ekves2019), and language is, by definition, abstracted away from objects and events. And in addition to providing a useful model of prediction and abstraction at multiple levels of representation, language plays a functional role in facilitating these functions, and thus, “mental travel.”

Many formal models of abstraction in language exist, but here we focus on work describing prediction and the emergence of abstract category structure as a function of accumulating knowledge of the contexts in which experience is grounded (Elman Reference Elman1990; see also Altmann Reference Altmann1997). Jeff Elman's work with the simple recurrent network (SRN) is the quintessential example from a computational standpoint of abstraction, prediction, and the relationship between the two (Elman Reference Elman1990; Reference Elman1993). Through accumulated experience of sequences of words, categorical distinctions such as between parts of speech (e.g., noun and verb), and between classes of nouns and verbs (e.g., edible objects and intransitive verbs) emerge in a network given the task of predicting the next word in the sequence.

Gilead et al. perceive an insufficiency in models exhibiting an “undifferentiated, continuous hierarchy of mental representations of different levels of abstractness.” Yet Elman's SRN was undifferentiated computationally (hidden layer units all functioned identically). After learning though, it was not undifferentiated functionally. Similarity relationships in its equivalent of the external world (language input to the SRN) were maintained in its acquired internal representations, and these allowed the SRN to predict the space of possible inputs at the next point in time. Hierarchy was only categorical to the extent that hierarchical clustering is categorical (different clusters would exhibit different hierarchies). Abstraction in Elman's work was graded, meaning generalization was graded also – a desirable property in a probabilistic world. Importantly, and unlike Gilead et al.'s framework, which have since been shown, in deep recurrent neural networks, are general principles of learning and development (Elman et al. Reference Elman, Bates, Johnson, Karmiloff-Smith, Parisi and Plunkett1996).

The emergence of increasingly abstract representations (not just in language) may rely on domain-general neurobiological mechanisms for tracking systematicities across space and time (for discussion of how one such mechanism may apply to abstract concepts, see Davis et al. Reference Davis, Altmann and Yee2020). However, a problem for any experience-based model of abstraction is how we sample enough of the world to track those systematicities and converge on shared meaning. Here, language comes in again: It allows us to experience more of the world than we could via direct experience alone. Experiencing spoken, signed, and written words – and their distributional patterns of co-occurrence both with other words in sentences and with the real world – opens a window into other people's (embodied) experiences. Distributional language statistics are a rich source of knowledge (e.g., Louwerse Reference Louwerse2008), enabling us to make predictions about things not directly experienced.

Language also facilitates prediction and abstraction in ways non-linguistic thought does not. For example, labels may penetrate through the representational gradient by operating directly on mental states (Elman Reference Elman2009). Although classical thinking holds that language is merely a means to communicating our thoughts, more recent work has shown that language has a functional role not only in higher-order thought, but also perception (for a review, see Lupyan Reference Lupyan2012). A consequence of language's influence across the gradient of abstraction is that concepts do not operate only at the modality-specific level: labels may (among other things) help integrate modality specific information in higher-order association areas. Gilead et al. cite meta-analytic findings that lexical-semantic tasks tend to activate higher-order brain regions far removed from modality-specific areas (Binder et al. Reference Binder, Desai, Graves and Conant2009) as “compelling evidence” against distributed, modality-specific models of cognition. But, these activated higher-order regions are integral to multimodal integration and conceptual access via labels. Furthermore, because there is diversity in the modalities in which different things are experienced (e.g., sunsets visually, vs. thunder auditorily), conceptual representations reflect that diversity (e.g., Davis et al. Reference Davis, Joergensen, Boddy, Dowling and Yeein press). Thus, when experiments average over dozens of diverse concepts, activity in the various modalities that contribute to each one is likely to be washed out.

Abstraction is a process, and this process engenders a gradient, not qualitatively distinct levels in a representational hierarchy. Moreover, an account emphasizing “representational diversity” to address how humans use prediction and abstraction to transcend the present moment should recognize the ubiquitous role of language. Not only does the scientific study of language processing offer well-tested, formalized frameworks for understanding how abstract structure emerges (e.g., Elman Reference Elman1990; see also Altmann Reference Altmann2017), but language itself plays a functional role in facilitating “mental travel” via its integral role in prediction and abstraction.

References

Altmann, G. T. M. (1997) The ascent of Babel: An exploration of language, mind, and understanding. OUP.Google Scholar
Altmann, G. T. M. (2017) Abstraction and generalization in statistical learning: Implications for the relationship between semantic types and episodic tokens. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 372(1711):20160060.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Altmann, G. T. M. & Ekves, Z. (2019) Events as intersecting object histories: A new theory of event representation. Psychological Review 126(6):817–40.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Binder, J. R., Desai, R. H., Graves, W. W. & Conant, L. L. (2009) Where is the semantic system? A critical review and meta-analysis of 120 functional neuroimaging studies. Cerebral Cortex 19(12):2767–96. https://doi.org/10.1093/cercor/bhp055.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davis, C. P., Altmann, G. & Yee, E. (2020) Situational systematicity: A role for schema in understanding the differences between abstract and concrete concepts. Cognitive Neuropsychology. https://doi.org/10.1080/02643294.2019.1710124.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Davis, C. P., Joergensen, G. H., Boddy, P., Dowling, C. & Yee, E. (in press) Making it harder to “see” meaning: The more you see something, the more its conceptual representation is susceptible to visual interference. Psychological Science.Google Scholar
Davis, C. P. & Yee, E. (2019) Features, labels, space, and time: Factors supporting taxonomic relationships in the anterior temporal lobe and thematic relationships in the angular gyrus. Language, Cognition and Neuroscience 34(10):1347–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elman, J. L. (1990) Finding structure in time. Cognitive Science 14(2):179211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elman, J. L. (1993) Learning and development in neural networks: The importance of starting small. Cognition 48(1):7199.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elman, J. L. (2009) On the meaning of words and dinosaur bones: Lexical knowledge without a lexicon. Cognitive Science 33(4):547–82.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Parisi, D. & Plunkett, K. (1996) Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspective on development. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Louwerse, M. M. (2008) Embodied relations are encoded in language. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 15(4):838–44.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lupyan, G. (2012) Linguistically modulated perception and cognition: The label-feedback hypothesis. Frontiers in Psychology 3:54.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Pickering, M. J. & Garrod, S. (2013) An integrated theory of language production and comprehension. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(4):329–47.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yee, E. (2019) Abstraction and concepts: When, how, where, what and why? Language, Cognition and Neuroscience 34(10):1257–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar