Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T15:21:29.908Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How does consciousness for action relate to attention for action?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 November 2016

Elizabeth A. Franz*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of Otago, Dunedin 9016, New Zealand. lfranz@psy.otago.ac.nzhttp://www.otago.ac.nz/psychology/research/otago028082.html

Abstract

The interesting target article by Morsella et al. addresses critical issues that impact our understanding of consciousness. It is surprising, however, to see no treatment of the relationship between attention and consciousness, particularly given available models. Whether olfaction is most suitable as a model system to study consciousness for action also seems questionable. These issues are elaborated in the present commentary.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

The article by Morsella et al. is an interesting and thought-provoking review. Two primary issues kept coming to mind during my reading, both of which seem critical to address. The first is that the review avoids mentioning anything about the relationship between attention and consciousness. The second concerns whether the olfactory system in all of its simplicity is suitable as a model system to study consciousness for action (particularly in humans).

Cited in the target article but not elaborated, Keller (Reference Keller2011) emphasizes the relation between attention and consciousness when considering olfactory consciousness. In a similar vein, work in my lab has considered the link between consciousness and attention; however, the focus is not on olfaction, but on conflict situations between the limbs (bimanual actions) in an allocation of attention to action (AAA) framework (Franz Reference Franz2012). As in the target article by Morsella et al., the AAA framework was inspired by the earlier writings of Sperry (Reference Sperry1952) and James (Reference James1890/1918), and a major tenet is ideomotor theory (Hommel Reference Hommel and Bruya2010). Thus, the similarities across approaches are quite remarkable.

Higher levels of the 3-level AAA framework incorporate examples of bimanual conflict in actions such as drawing a circle and a line, or circle and square (Franz Reference Franz1997; Reference Franz and Johnston-Frey2003; Reference Franz2012; Franz & Ramachandran Reference Franz and Ramachandran1998; Franz et al. Reference Franz, Zelaznik and McCabe1991; Reference Franz, Eliassen, Ivry and Gazzaniga1996), or reaching with one hand to a far target and one hand to a near target (Franz & McCormick Reference Franz and McCormick2010; Kelso et al. Reference Kelso, Southard and Goodman1979). The “empirical proof” of integration (of lower and higher levels of processing) comes from additional examples in which the two hands produce a unified action rather than conflicting actions as a result of the presence of visual perceptual features or specific verbal instructional commands (Franz & McCormick Reference Franz and McCormick2010; Franz et al. Reference Franz, Waldie and Smith2000; Reference Franz, Zelaznik, Swinnen and Walter2001); this propensity to unify information at the highest level possible is proposed as a fundamental property of the “economical brain” (Franz Reference Franz2010; Reference Franz2012; Franz & McCormick Reference Franz and McCormick2010). Higher levels are further discussed in terms of automatic or conscious processes of activation and inhibition (level 2: AAA), and action selection (level 3: AAA), with all levels implicating a mix of conscious and unconscious processing.

Consider a specific point of overlap found in the target article, which states that “there must be a (unconscious) mechanism by which one action plan can influence behavior more than other activated action plans” (sect. 3.3, para. 3). AAA argues the same, building on an action selection model (Mink Reference Mink1996) in which activation of an action plan occurs from among other prepotent action plans that must be inhibited (akin to action options). This process implicates basal-ganglia (striatal) and thalamic-cortical (primarily frontal) circuits as being key (Franz Reference Franz and Bezard2006; Reference Franz2012; Mink Reference Mink1996) and can occur automatically through activation functions.

The target article focuses primarily on what most resembles the lowest level of AAA. In level 1 of AAA (see Figure 1 in Franz Reference Franz2012), primarily exogenous inputs capture awareness of an organism transiently (and automatically), leading eventually to trial-and-error learning which results in formation of a perceptual-action code akin to ideomotor theory (Hommel Reference Hommel and Bruya2010); recent experimental support comes from studies using evoked response potentials (Bednark et al. Reference Bednark, Reynolds, Stafford, Redgrave and Franz2013; Bednark & Franz Reference Bednark and Franz2014).

Three differences are clear across frameworks: (1) the focus on attention and its relation to consciousness (Franz Reference Franz2012; Keller Reference Keller2011) not present in Morsella et al.; (2) the focus on “in the service of action” (Franz Reference Franz2012; Morsella et al.) not present in Keller (Reference Keller2011); and (3) the focus on olfaction (Keller Reference Keller2011; Morsella et al.) not present in Franz (Reference Franz2012).

Furthermore, the work of Grossberg, although briefly cited, seems far more relevant than suggested in the target article. Grossberg (Reference Grossberg1999) addresses the question of “how an intelligent being can autonomously adapt to a changing world” (p. 4, emphasis in original). Grossberg (Reference Grossberg1999) suggests that top-down expectation selectively amplifies some features of bottom-up input while suppressing others, and bottom-up signals reactivate those same top-down expectations (p. 10). This reactivation leads to a resonant state which is necessary for the brain to achieve consciousness (a conscious percept). Without it, there is no conscious percept. Furthermore, Grossberg (Reference Grossberg1999) suggests that a form of automatic attention can operate at very low levels of processing (p. 32). Perhaps this also suggests that the distinction between “passive” and “active” becomes rather blurry within the context of a process model?

According to AAA, increasingly embedded levels of processing are built upon a basic sensorimotor system as a result of evolved adaptations. This enables representation (possibly similar to conscious content), and re-representation in a hierarchical neural system, which has evolved through embodied actions, consistent with the very early views of John Hughlings Jackson (Reference Hughlings Jackson1884; cf. Franz & Gillett Reference Franz and Gillett2011; Gillett & Franz Reference Gillett and Franz2013). A statement in section 5 of the target article seems to capture the essence of this idea: “All influences on skeletomotor behavior, from the highest-level processes (e.g., language) to the lowest-level processes (e.g., pain withdrawal), must engage the skeletomotor output system” (para. 4).

If olfaction is being proposed as a model system for studying consciousness, and consciousness is for action, then what about the implied olfaction for action link? The skeletal action system is highly adaptive with growth of the organism (the limbs increase in size with age), and is controlled by numerous cognitive and perceptual processes together with influences of a dynamically changing environment (Franz Reference Franz2012; Grossberg Reference Grossberg1999). Limb systems respond with fast simple reaction times to visual and auditory stimuli (often between 200 and 300 milliseconds; Greenwald Reference Greenwald1972; Hughes & Franz Reference Hughes and Franz2007; Shen & Franz Reference Shen and Franz2005; Tassinari & Berlucchi Reference Tassinari and Berlucchi1993). Visual stimuli are experienced as uninterrupted, whereas olfactory experience is discontinuous due to sniffs occurring with gaps between them (1.6 seconds is cited as the gap; Laing Reference Laing1983; Mainland & Sobel Reference Mainland and Sobel2006; cited in Keller Reference Keller2011). Thus, olfactory experience is temporally unstructured, and olfaction is essentially a slower sense (Keller Reference Keller2011). Gottfried and Dolan (Reference Gottfried and Dolan2003) report a mean olfactory reaction time of 1.539 seconds, and further elaborate that “the nose smells what the eye sees” (p. 375), that is, odor perception is largely affected by interactions with vision. Is an olfaction to action link all that consistent with available evidence?

In sum, while I have no reason to disagree with the suggestion that olfaction is an ideal system to study consciousness, I am less convinced that olfaction is a suitable model system for an approach aimed at informing our understanding of “consciousness for action.”

References

Bednark, J. G. & Franz, E. A. (2014) Agency attribution: Event-related potentials and outcome monitoring. Experimental Brain Research 232:1117–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bednark, J. G., Reynolds, J. N. J, Stafford, T., Redgrave, P. & Franz, E. A. (2013) Creating a movement heuristic for voluntary action: Electrophysiological correlates of movement-outcome learning. Cortex 49(3):771–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Franz, E. A. (1997) Spatial coupling in the coordination of complex actions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology A 50A:684704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franz, E. A. (2003) Bimanual action representation: A window to human evolution. In: Taking action: Cognitive neuroscience perspectives on intentional acts, ed. Johnston-Frey, S. H., pp. 259–88. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franz, E. A. (2006) Converging evidence of the basal ganglia's role in focused action selection and inhibition of competing information. In: Recent breakthroughs in basal ganglia research, ed. Bezard, E., Ch. 18, pp. 227–39. Nova Science.Google Scholar
Franz, E. A. (2010) A framework for conceptual binding of bimanual actions: Possible applications to neurology and neuro-rehabilitative therapies. Current Trends in Neurology 4:122.Google Scholar
Franz, E. A. (2012) The allocation of attention to learning of goal-directed actions: A cognitive neuroscience framework focusing on the basal ganglia. Frontiers in Psychology 3, article 535:115. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00535.Google Scholar
Franz, E. A., Eliassen, J., Ivry, R. B. & Gazzaniga, M. S. (1996) Dissociation of spatial and temporal coupling in the bimanual movements of callosotomy patients. Psychological Science 7:306–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franz, E. A. & Gillett, G. (2011) John Hughlings Jackson's evolutionary neurology: A unifying framework for cognitive neuroscience. Brain 134(10):3114–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franz, E. A. & McCormick, R. (2010) Conceptual unifying constraints on anticipatory bimanual control. Experimental Brain Research 205(2):273–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franz, E. A. & Ramachandran, V. S. (1998) Bimanual coupling in amputees with phantom limbs. Nature Neuroscience 1:443–44. doi:10.1038/2161.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Franz, E. A., Waldie, K. & Smith, M. (2000) The effect of callosotomy on novel versus familiar bimanual actions: A neural dissociation between controlled and automatic processes? Psychological Science 11(1):8285.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Franz, E. A., Zelaznik, H. N. & McCabe, G. (1991) Spatial topological constraints in a bimanual task. Acta Psychologica 77(2):137–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Franz, E. A., Zelaznik, H. N., Swinnen, S. & Walter, C. (2001) Spatial conceptual influences on the coordination of bimanual actions: When a dual task becomes a single task. Journal of Motor Behavior 33(1):103–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gillett, G. & Franz, E. A. (2013) John Hughlings Jackson: Bridging theory and clinical observation. The Lancet 381(9866):528–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gottfried, J. A. & Dolan, R. J. (2003) The nose smells what the eye sees: Crossmodal visual facilitation of human olfactory perception. Neuron 39(2):375–86.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Greenwald, A. G. (1972) On doing two things at once: Time sharing as a function of ideomotor compatibility. Journal of Experimental Psychology 94(1):5257.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Grossberg, S. (1999) The link between brain learning, attention, and consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 8(1):144.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hommel, B. (2010) Grounding attention in action control: The intentional control of selection. In: Effortless attention: A new perspective in the cognitive science of attention and action, ed. Bruya, B. J., pp. 121–40. MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hughes, C. M. L. & Franz, E. A. (2007) Experience-dependent effects in unimanual and bimanual reaction time tasks in musicians. Journal of Motor Behavior 39(1):38.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hughlings Jackson, J. (1884) On affectations of speech from disease of the brain (Part 2). British Medical Journal 12:703707.Google Scholar
James, W. (1890/1918) The principles of psychology, vols. 1 and 11. Dover. (Original work published in 1890).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, A. (2011) Attention and olfactory consciousness. Frontiers in Psychology 2, article 380. (Online journal). doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2011.00380.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kelso, J. A. S., Southard, D. L. & Goodman, D. (1979) On the nature of human interlimb coordination. Science 203(4384):1029–31.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Laing, D. G. (1983) Natural sniffing gives optimum odour perception for humans. Perception 12:99117.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Mainland, J. D. & Sobel, N. (2006) The sniff is part of the olfactory percept. Chemical Senses 31:181–96.Google Scholar
Mink, J. W. (1996) The basal ganglia: Focused selection and inhibition of competing motor programs. Progress in Neurobiology 50:381425.Google Scholar
Shen, Y. C. & Franz, E. A. (2005) Hemispheric competition in left-handers on bimanual reaction time tasks. Journal of Motor Behavior 37:39.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sperry, R. W. (1952) Neurology and the mind-brain problem. American Scientist 40:291312.Google Scholar
Tassinari, G. & Berlucchi, G. (1993) Sensory and attentional components of slowing of manual reaction time to non-fixated visual targets by ipsilateral primes. Vision Research 33(11):1525–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed