Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T21:06:14.607Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Emotions of “higher” cognition1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 May 2012

Leonid Perlovsky
Affiliation:
Harvard University, Athinoula A. Martinos Center for Biomedical Imaging, Charlestown, MA 02129; and the Air Force Research Laboratory WPAFB, OH 45433. leonid@seas.harvard.eduhttp://leonid-perlovsky.com/

Abstract

The target article by Lindquist et al. considers discrete emotions. This commentary argues that these are but a minor part of human emotional abilities, unifying us with animals. Uniquely human emotions are aesthetic emotions related to the need for the knowledge of “high” cognition, including emotions of the beautiful, cognitive dissonances, and musical emotions. This commentary touches on their cognitive functions and origins.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2012

The target article by Lindquist et al. contributes a wealth of information to studies of emotions, and to psychology in general. However, I would expect such an in-depth article on emotions to address specifically human, “higher” cognitive emotions. Whereas in the past emotions were often considered irrelevant or opposite to cognition, recent research emphasizes closed relations between the two (Adolphs et al. Reference Adolphs, Damasio and Tranel2002; Bechara & Damasio Reference Bechara and Damasio2002; Bradley et al. Reference Bradley, Codispoti, Cuthbert and Lang2001; Damasio Reference Damasio1995; Duncan & Barrett Reference Duncan and Barrett2007; Grossberg & Levine 1987; Mayer et al. Reference Mayer, Salovey and Caruso2008; Ochsner & Phelps Reference Ochsner and Phelps2007; Perlovsky Reference Perlovsky2006c). Discrete emotions discussed in the article are limited in number and thus represent only a minor part of human emotional abilities. Specifically human emotions are related to “high” cognition. As discussed later, their number is very large, and this is why they are called “continuous.” Musical emotions (Juslin & Västfjäll Reference Juslin and Vastfjall2008) are an example of “continuous” emotions that set humans apart from the animal kingdom. Yet, the entire target article is devoted exclusively to discrete emotions that appear in the perception of concrete objects. Here are a few quotes from the article to support this point:

“Emotions emerge when people make meaning out of sensory input from the body and from the world.” (sect. 3, para. 2);

“Emotions are ‘situated conceptualizations’… because the emerging meaning is tailored to the immediate environment.” (sect. 3, para. 2);

“Core affect… is a term used to describe the mental representation of bodily changes.” (sect. 3, para. 4)

These statements might almost equally refer to animals or humans. The target article does not consider emotions related to abstract concepts. No emotion of pleasure from understanding is discussed; for example, that understanding an object to be food might be emotionally pleasant for a hungry animal or human. But understanding is also pleasant in itself, otherwise there would be no motivation to understand abstract concepts. Understanding the meaning of one's life is emotionally pleasant; a simplified reason is that this is necessary for concentrating one's efforts on the most important goals. This emotion, according to Kant (Reference Kant and Bernard1790), is related to emotions of the beautiful. Kant explained that aesthetic emotions are related to knowledge.

Specifically human “higher” cognitive emotions, especially musical emotions, have been called “mysterious” by thinkers from Aristotle to Darwin and by contemporary evolutionary psychologists (Aristotle Reference Aristotle and Barnes1995; Ball Reference Ball2008; Darwin Reference Darwin1871; Masataka Reference Masataka2008). Yet, “higher” cognitive emotions have been studied by many authors. I will mention just a few references: emotions of cognitive dissonance (Cabanac et al., in press; Festinger Reference Festinger1957; Haidt Reference Haidt2001; Levine Reference Levine2009; Levine & Perlovsky Reference Levine and Perlovsky2010; van Veen et al. Reference van Veen, Krug, Schooler and Carter2009), musical emotions (Cross & Morley Reference Cross, Morley, Malloch and Trevarthen2008; Juslin & Västfjäll Reference Juslin and Vastfjall2008; Levitin Reference Levitin2006; Panksepp & Bernatzky Reference Panksepp and Bernatzky2002; Patel Reference Patel2008; Perlovsky Reference Perlovsky2010d; Reference Perlovsky2010c; Purwins et al. Reference Purwins, Herrera, Grachten, Hazan, Marxer and Serra2008; Sloboda & Juslin Reference Sloboda, Juslin, Juslin and Sloboda2001; Trainor Reference Trainor2008 ), and emotions of language prosody (Buchanan et al. Reference Buchanan, Lutz, Mirzazade, Specht, Shah, Zilles and Jäncke2000; Davis et al. Reference Davis, Zhang, Winkworth and Bandler1996; Deacon Reference Deacon1989; Perlovsky Reference Perlovsky2006a; Reference Perlovsky2006b; Reference Perlovsky2009b).

Even when discussing emotions in voices, Lindquist et al. do not recognize them as possibly different from discrete emotions. Yet the voice of human languages carries a significant emotional load different from that of discrete emotions. Emotions in language sounds are similar to emotions in poetry and songs, and (among other things) motivate us to relate language sounds to their meanings (Perlovsky Reference Perlovsky2009b; Reference Perlovsky2010c). Animals relate sounds of voice to meanings automatically; in an animal's mind the sounds of voice are inseparable from the meanings. Humans have to be motivated to do this (Deacon Reference Deacon1989; Seyfarth & Cheney Reference Seyfarth and Cheney2003a). Emotions related to knowledge of abstract concepts have been discussed in Cacioppo et al. (Reference Cacioppo, Petty, Feinstein and Jarvis1996), Levine and Perlovsky (Reference Levine and Perlovsky2008; Reference Levine and Perlovsky2010), Perlovsky (Reference Perlovsky2009b; Reference Perlovsky2010c), and Perlovsky et al. (Reference Perlovsky, Bonniot-Cabanac and Cabanac2010), and emotions related to creativity discussed in Levine and Perlovsky (Reference Levine and Perlovsky2010), Lubart and Getz (Reference Lubart and Getz1997), and Pfenninger and Shubik (Reference Pfenninger and Shubik2001). “Emotions of the beautiful” are discussed in Biederman and Vessel (Reference Biederman and Vessel2006), Dorfman et al. (Reference Dorfman, Locher and Martindale2006), Perlovsky (Reference Perlovsky2002; Reference Perlovsky2006c; Reference Perlovsky2010b; Reference Perlovsky2010a), Tooby and Cosmides (Reference Tooby and Cosmides2001), and in Silvia (Reference Silvia2005). Yet the “beautiful” is mentioned only once in the target article: “A painting is beautiful” (sect. 3, para. 5). Emotions pertaining to the beautiful are not mentioned.

In the Perlovsky studies cited above, I have discussed evidence and other studies relating “emotions of the beautiful,” as discussed by Kant, to the need for knowledge; aesthetic emotional mechanisms are essential in every act of perception and cognition; at the level of perception they are autonomous and below the threshold of consciousness, at “higher” levels of cognition they could be experienced as conscious emotions; they are in complicated interaction with cultural discussions of these emotions in language (which usually are more conscious). The origin of aesthetic emotional mechanisms is in the need to adapt mental representations to concrete conditions around us. Contradictions between basic drives and knowledge, as well as within the system of knowledge, cause emotions of cognitive dissonances. A need to resolve these contradictions emotionally is related to the origin of music. (These emotions are usually “continuous” because the number of contradictions, and therefore the number of emotions, is combinatorially large; Spinoza [Reference Spinoza and Curley1677/2005] was the first one to mention that emotions differ depending on the object of reference.)

Lindquist et al. mention in conclusion that emotions and cognition might be a unified process:

[W]e might not assume that emotion and cognition battle it out in the brain … or that consumer decisions are predicated on competing affective and rational representations …. Instead, we might assume that affect and executive attention are merely different sources of attention in the brain …. Feeling and seeing might not be as distinct as is typically assumed. (target article, sect. 7, para. 1)

But no discussion was devoted to emotions related to cognition “above” perception of concrete objects. An opportunity to study specifically human “high” cognitive emotions has been lost.

Footnotes

1.

This is a work of the U.S. Government and is not subject to copyright protection in the United States.

References

Adolphs, R., Damasio, H. & Tranel, D. (2002) Neural systems for recognition of emotional prosody: A 3-D lesion study. Emotion 2(1):2351.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Aristotle, . (1995) The complete works of Aristotle. The revised Oxford translation, ed. Barnes, J.. Princeton University Press. (Original work written in VI BCE).Google Scholar
Ball, P. (2008) Facing the music. Nature 453:160–62.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bechara, A. & Damasio, A. R. (2002) The somatic marker hypothesis: A neural theory of economic decision. Games and Economic Behavior 52(2005):336–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biederman, I. & Vessel, E. A. (2006) Perceptual pleasure and the brain. American Scientist 94:248–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bradley, M. M., Codispoti, M., Cuthbert, B. N. & Lang, P. J. (2001) Emotion and motivation I: Defensive and appetitive reactions in picture processing. Emotion 1(3):276–98.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Buchanan, T. W., Lutz, K., Mirzazade, S., Specht, K., Shah, N. J., Zilles, K. & Jäncke, L. (2000) Recognition of emotional prosody and verbal components of spoken language: An fMRI study. Cognitive Brain Research 9:227–38.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cabanac, M., Fontanari, F., Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C. & Perlovsky, L. I. (in press) Emotions of cognitive dissonance. IEEE Proceedings IJCNN 2011.Google Scholar
Cacioppo, J. T., Petty, R. E., Feinstein, J. A. & Jarvis, W. B. G. (1996) Dispositional differences in cognitive motivation: The life and times of individuals varying in need for cognition. Psychological Bulletin 119(2):197253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cross, I. & Morley, I. (2008) The evolution of music: Theories, definitions and the nature of the evidence. In: Communicative musicality, ed. Malloch, S. & Trevarthen, C., pp. 6182. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damasio, A. R. (1995) Review: Toward a neurobiology of emotion and feeling: Operational concepts and hypotheses. Neuroscientist 1(1):1925.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darwin, C. R. (1871) The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. John Murray.Google Scholar
Davis, P. J., Zhang, S. P., Winkworth, A. & Bandler, R. (1996) Neural control of vocalization: Respiratory and emotional influences. Journal of Voice 10:2338.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Deacon, T. (1989) The neural circuitry underlying primate calls and human language. Human Evolution Journal 4(5):367401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorfman, L., Locher, P. & Martindale, C., eds. (2006) New directions in aesthetics, creativity, and the arts. Baywood Press.Google Scholar
Duncan, S. & Barrett, L. F. (2007) Affect is a form of cognition: A neurobiological analysis. Cognition and Emotion 21(6):1184–211. Available at: http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2396787/.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Festinger, L. (1957) A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haidt, J. (2001) The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 108(4):814–34.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Juslin, P. N. & Vastfjall, D. (2008) Emotional responses to music: The need to consider underlying mechanisms. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31:559621.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Kant, I. (1790) The critique of judgment, trans. Bernard, J. H.. Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
Levine, D. S. (2009) Brain pathways for cognitive-emotional decision making in the human animal. Neural Networks 22(3):286–93.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levine, D. S. & Perlovsky, L. I. (2008) Neuroscientific insights on biblical myths: Simplifying heuristics versus careful thinking: Scientific analysis of millennial spiritual issues. Zygon, Journal of Science and Religion 43(4):797821.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, D. S. & Perlovsky, L. I. (2010) Emotion in the pursuit of understanding. International Journal of Synthetic Emotions 1(2):111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levitin, D. J. (2006) This is your brain on music: The science of a human obsession. Dutton.Google Scholar
Lubart, T. I. & Getz, I. (1997) Emotion, metaphor, and the creative process. Creativity Research Journal 10(4):285301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Masataka, N. (2008) The origins of language and the evolution of music: A comparative perspective. Physics of Life Reviews 6:1122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, J. D., Salovey, P. & Caruso, D. R. (2008) Emotional intelligence. New ability or eclectic traits? American Psychologist 63(6):503–17.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ochsner, K. N. & Phelps, E. (2007) Emerging perspectives on emotion–cognition interactions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11(8):317–18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Panksepp, J. & Bernatzky, G. (2002) Emotional sounds and the brain: The neuro-affective foundations of musical appreciation. Behavioural Processes 60:133–55.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Patel, A. D. (2008) Music, language, and the brain. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2002) Aesthetics and mathematical theory of intellect. Russian Academy of Sciences, Iskusstvoznanie, Journal of History and Theory of Art 2:558–94. (In Russian).Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2004) Integrating language and cognition. IEEE Connections 2(2):812. (Feature Article).Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2006a) Joint evolution of cognition, consciousness, and music. Lectures in Musicology, School of Music, University of Ohio, Columbus.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2006b) Music – The first principle. Musical Theatre. Available at: http://www.ceo.spb.ru/libretto/kon_lan/ogl.shtml.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2006c) Toward physics of the mind: Concepts, emotions, consciousness, and symbols. Physics of Life Reviews 3(1):2255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2006a) Joint evolution of cognition, consciousness, and music. Lectures in Musicology, School of Music, University of Ohio, Columbus.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2006b) Music – The first principle. Musical Theatre. Available at: http://www.ceo.spb.ru/libretto/kon_lan/ogl.shtml.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2006c) Toward physics of the mind: Concepts, emotions, consciousness, and symbols. Physics of Life Reviews 3(1):2255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2007) Symbols: Integrated cognition and language. In: Semiotics and intelligent systems development, ed. Gudwin, R. & Queiroz, J., pp. 121–51. Idea Group.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2009a) Language and cognition. Neural Networks 22(3):247–57.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Perlovsky, L. I. (2009b) Language and emotions: Emotional Sapir-Whorf hypothesis. Neural Networks 22(5–6):518–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Perlovsky, L. I. (2010a) Beauty and art. Cognitive function, evolution, and mathematical models of the mind. WebmedCentral PSYCHOLOGY 1(12): WMC001322.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2010b) Intersections of mathematical, cognitive, and aesthetic theories of mind. Psychology of Aesthetics, Creativity, and the Arts 4(1):1117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2010c) Joint acquisition of language and cognition. WebmedCentral BRAIN 1(10): WMC00994. (Online publication). Available at: http://www.webmedcentral.com/article_view/994.Google Scholar
Perlovsky, L. I. (2010d) Musical emotions: Functions, origin, evolution. Physics of Life Reviews 7(1):227.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Perlovsky, L. I., Bonniot-Cabanac, M.-C. & Cabanac, M. (2010) Curiosity and pleasure. WebmedCentral PSYCHOLOGY 1(12): WMC001275.Google Scholar
Pfenninger, K. H. & Shubik, K. R. (2001) The origins of creativity. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Purwins, H., Herrera, P., Grachten, M., Hazan, A., Marxer, R. & Serra, X. (2008) Computational models of music perception and cognition I: The perceptual and cognitive processing chain. Physics of Life Reviews 5:151–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seyfarth, R. M. & Cheney, D. L. (2003a) Meaning and emotion in animal vocalizations. Annual New York Academy of Science 1000:3255.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Silvia, P. J. (2005) Emotional responses to art: From collation and arousal to cognition and emotion. Review of General Psychology 9(4):342–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sloboda, J. A. & Juslin, P. N. (2001) Psychological perspectives on music and emotion. In: Music and emotion: Theory and research, ed. Juslin, P. N. & Sloboda, J. A., pp. 71104. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spinoza, B. (1677/2005) Ethics, trans. Curley, E.. Penguin. (Original work published in 1677).Google Scholar
Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (2001) Does beauty build adapted minds? Toward an evolutionary theory of aesthetics, fiction and the arts. SubStance 94/95, 30(1):627.Google Scholar
Trainor, L. (2008) The neural roots of music. Nature 453(29):598–99.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
van Veen, V., Krug, M. K., Schooler, J. W. & Carter, C. S. (2009) Neural activity predicts attitude change in cognitive dissonance. Nature Neuroscience 12(11):1469–74.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed