Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-s22k5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T17:20:53.430Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The case for continuity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 May 2011

Rochel Gelman
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology and Center for Cognitive Science, Rutgers University, Piscataway, NJ 08854-8020. rgelman@ruccs.rutgers.eduruccs.rutgers.edu/faculty/GnG/gelman.html

Abstract

This article defends a continuity position. Infants can abstract numerosity and young preschool children do respond appropriately to tasks that tap their ability to use a count and cardinal value and/or arithmetic principles. Active use of a nonverbal domain of arithmetic serves to enable the child to find relevant data to build knowledge about the language and use rules of numerosity and quantity.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2011

Carey's book is an outstanding contribution to cognitive development (Carey Reference Carey2009). It reviews and updates findings that infants and young children have abstract or “core” representations of objects, agents, number, and causes. The number chapters feature the argument for discontinuity between infant and later cognitive development. They include evidence that infants use two separate number abstraction systems: an object-file, parallel system for the small numbers of 1 to 3 or 4; and a ratio-dependent quantity mechanism for larger numbers. This contrasts with adults, who use a ratio-dependent mechanism for all values (Cordes et al. Reference Cordes, Gelman, Gallistel and Whalen2001).

Further, Carey argues that verbal counting is first memorized without understanding and that the meaning of counting and cardinality is embedded in the learning of the quantifier system. She cites Wynn's (Reference Wynn1990; Reference Wynn1992) “Give X” and LeCorre and Carey's (Reference Le Corre and Carey2007) tasks that children aged 2 years, 8 months to 3 years, 2 months typically fail as well as analyses on quantifiers, including some and many.

An alternative account runs as follows. Infants possess a core domain for arithmetic reasoning about discrete and continuous quantity, necessarily including both mechanisms for establishing reference and mechanisms for arithmetic reasoning. The nonverbal domain outlines those verbal data and uses rules that are relevant to its growth. The development of adult numerical competence is a continuous and sustained learning involving the mapping of the cultural system for talking about quantity into the inherited nonverbal system for reasoning about quantity. Counting principles constitute one way to establish reference for discrete quantity because they are consistent with and subservient to the operations of addition and ordering, that is, they are consistent with basic elements of arithmetic reasoning. In this view, the Carey account focuses too much on reference and almost ignores the requirement that symbols also enter into arithmetic reasoning. The well-established ability of infants and toddlers to recognize the ordering of sequentially presented numerosities, including small ones, requires a counting-like mechanism to establish reference. If the symbols that refer to numerosities do not enter into at least some of the operations that define arithmetic (order, addition, subtraction), then they are not numerical symbols. However, there is evidence that beginning speakers recognize that counting yields estimates of cardinality about which they reason arithmetically.

  1. 1. Infants can represent numerosity in the small number range. Cordes and Brannon (Reference Cordes and Brannon2009) show that, if anything, numerosity is more salient than various continuous properties in the 1–4 number range. Converging evidence is found in VanMarle and Wynn (in press).

  2. 2. Cordes and Brannon (Reference Cordes and Brannon2009) also show that 7-month-old infants discriminate between 4:1 changes when the values cross from small (2) to larger (8) sets. These authors conclude that infants can use both number and object files in the small N range, a challenge to the view that there is a discontinuity between the small number and larger number range for infants.

  3. 3. Two-and-a-half-year-olds distinguish between the meaning of “a” and “one” when tested with the “What's on the card WOC?” task (Gelman Reference Gelman and Medin1993). When they reply to the WOC question with one item, they often say “a __”. When told “that's a one-x card”, the vast majority of 2½-year-olds both counted and provided the cardinal value on set sizes 2 and 3 and young 3-year-olds (≤3 years, 2 months) provide both the relevant cardinal and counting solution for small sets as well as some larger ones. Syrett et al. (in press) report comparable or better success rates for children in the same age ranges. The appearance of counting when cardinality is in question is good evidence that these very young children, who can be inconsistent counters, nonetheless understand that counting renders a cardinal value.

  4. 4. Arithmetic abilities appear alongside early counting. Two-and-a-half-year-old children transferred an ordering relation between 1 versus 2 to 3 versus 4 (Bullock & Gelman Reference Bullock and Gelman1977). When these children encountered the unexpected change in numerosities, they started to use count words in a systematic way. This too reveals an understanding of the function of counting well before they can do the give-N task. Carey's claim that “originally the counting routine and the numeral list have no numerical meaning” (p. 311) is simply false.

  5. 5. Gelman's magic show was run in a number of different conditions and with 3-year-old children. Children this age distinguished between operations that change cardinal values (numerosities) and those that do not, across a number of studies. Moreover, when the cardinality of the winner comes into question, they very often try to count the sets, which are in the range of 2–4, and occasionally 5.

  6. 6. Further evidence that 3-year-olds understanding of cardinality comes from the Zur and Gelman (Reference Gelman2006) arithmetic–counting task. Children started a round of successive trials with a given number of objects, perhaps doughnuts, to put in their bakery shop. They then sold and acquired 1–3 doughnuts. Their task was to first predict – without looking – how many they would have, and then to check. Their predictions were in the right direction, if not precise. They counted to check their prediction and get ready for the next round. They never mixed the prediction–estimation phase and the checking phase. Counts were extremely accurate and there was no tendency to make the count equal the prediction. Totals could go as high as 5.

  7. 7. The idea that understanding of the exact meaning of cardinal terms is rooted in the semantics of quantifiers is challenged in Hurewitz et al. (Reference Hurewitz, Papafragou, Gleitman and Gelman2006). They found that children in the relevant age range were better able to respond to exact number requests (2 vs. 4) than to “some” and “all.”

  8. 8. An expanded examination of the Childes database with experiments with the partitive frame (e.g., zav of Y) and modification by the adverb very (e.g., very zav) reveal that the Bloom and Wynn analysis of semantics is neither necessary nor sufficient to accomplish the learnability challenge (Syrett et al., in press).

The preverbal arithmetic structure can direct attention to and assimilate structurally relevant verbal data and their environments.

References

Bullock, M. & Gelman, R. (1977) Numerical reasoning in young children: The ordering principle. Child Development 48:427–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carey, S. (2009) The origin of concepts. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cordes, S. & Brannon, E.M. (2009) Crossing the divide: Infants discriminate small from large numbers. Developmental Psychology 45:1583–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cordes, S., Gelman, R., Gallistel, C. R. & Whalen, J. (2001) Variability signatures distinguish verbal from non-verbal counting – even in the small number range. Psychonomics Bulletin and Review 8(4):698707.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelman, R. (1993) A rational-constructivist account of early learning about numbers and objects. In: The psychology of learning and motivation, vol. 30, ed. Medin, D., pp. 6196. Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gelman, R. (2006) The young child as natural-number arithmetician. Current Directions in Psychological Science 15:193–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hurewitz, F., Papafragou, , Gleitman, L. R. & Gelman, R. (2006) Asymmetries in the acquisition of numbers and quantifiers. Language learning and development 2:7796.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Corre, M. & Carey, S. (2007) One, two, three, four, nothing more: An investigation of the conceptual sources of the counting principles. Cognition 105:395438.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Syrett, K., Musolino, J. & Gelman, R. (in press) Can children use syntax to learn about number word meaning. Language, learning and development Google Scholar
VanMarle, K. & Wynn, K. (in press) Tacking and quantifying objects and non-cohesive substances. Developmental Science.Google Scholar
Wynn, K. (1990) Children's understanding of counting. Cognition 36:155–93.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wynn, K. (1992) Children's acquisition of the number words and the counting system. Cognitive Psychology 24:220–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zur, O. & Gelman, R. (2004) Doing arithmetic in preschool by predicting and checking. Early Childhood Quarterly Review 19:121–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar