Introduction
Does the environment shape – or determine – human action or does human agency play a vital role in the events that come to pass (see Arponen et al. Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019)? Perhaps we can simply put a stance on the matter down to opinion, but a significant problem arises when one discourse negates the possibility of the other. In their article ‘Environmental determinism and archaeology. Understanding and evaluating determinism in research design’, Arponen et al. indicate that certain discourses (for example, the ‘parallelistic form of research design’) are prohibiting the growth of the idea that human actions co-constitute the ‘human–environment relation’ (ibid., 8). They observe that different discursive methods yield different narratives for the same event (ibid., 9), noting, on one hand, that there is environmental determinism and how humans respond to ‘external events’, and, on the other, that there are socially produced vulnerabilities at community level before the ‘external event’ (ibid., 9). One thought-provoking example offered in the paper is the case of the 2010 Haiti earthquake; the researchers refer to the work of Oliver-Smith (Reference Oliver-Smith2010), who argues that colonialism and capitalism had created a ‘grave state of vulnerability’ that was unequally distributed amongst the Latin American and Caribbean populations (Arponen et al. Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019, 8). Oliver-Smith describes how undernourishment and inadequate building codes, for example, ‘led to the construction of extreme vulnerability’ in Haiti (Arponen et al. Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019, 8). In response to this research, Arponen et al. observe how the anthropology of hazards examines the social situation before the event, whereas archaeological research ‘takes primary interest in the social system after’ (ibid., 9, their emphasis).Footnote 1 In their paper, they argue that what the researcher takes to be ‘the crux of the matter’ (the most important point) meaningfully impacts upon the analysis and interpretation of the event (ibid., 9). Thus analytical models are ethically loaded because they directly correlate with what the researcher identifies as the ‘crux’. This issue – which, from my perspective, could be framed as the representationalist issue – is crucial, and is the aspect I shall attend to in this reaction via three points.
First, I will tackle the ‘crux of the matter’ by outlining how Karen Barad’s (Reference Barad2007) theory of agential realism avoids the issue of representationalism by theoretically incorporating the position of the researcher in the analysis of the event. Second, using the language and theory of Foucault (Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972), I will highlight how Arponen et al., in their discussion of the anthropology of hazards and palaeo-environmental archaeology, draw into high contrast two ‘discursive formation[s]’ (Foucault Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972, 38), and these appear to highlight a contemporary rupture in the discourse. Third, having observed the rupture, I shall critically reflect on how ‘polymorphous’ causal models liberate academic discourse from perpetuating systems of oppression that are fundamentally rooted in ‘sameness’ (Foucault Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972, 21).
Representationalism and performativity
Representationalism is increasingly becoming a subject of much debate in archaeology (see Arponen and Ribeiro Reference Arponen and Ribeiro2018). Despite a general movement towards an anti-representationalist stance in the field, there are several different hypotheses outlining how we might move past this predicament (on ‘holism’ see Arponen and Ribeiro Reference Arponen and Ribeiro2014; on a ‘more-than-representationalist archaeology’ see Harris Reference Harris2018). Representationalism is linked to Newtonian physics and born out of a Cartesian mindset that begins with the assumption that there are separate entities that we can measure without interfering with them, and that said entities (or traditionally ‘objects’) can be located through a ‘measurement procedure’ (Barad Reference Barad2007, 106). Underlying this assumption is the understanding that we can obtain representations through our knowledge-making practices that confirm the ‘intrinsic properties’ of the object (ibid., 106). I argue that if we take representationalism to be an ontological (and not just epistemological) issue, it is possible to theoretically explain the relationship between discourses that antagonize each other (see Harris Reference Harris2018, 88; Barad Reference Barad2007, 28).
When Arponen et al. (Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019, 2, their emphasis) argue that ‘disciplinary preferences relating to the dominant or emerging paradigms’ are linked to ‘methodological choice’, they highlight the role of the researcher who actively shapes the event through their research design and interpretation. Agential realism is a theory that actively acknowledges the conditions of emergence and the role the analyst plays in the interpretation of the event by asserting that ‘matter and meaning are mutually’ and co-productively ‘articulated’ (Barad Reference Barad2007, 152). The theory indicates that we should consider ‘the practices or performances of representing’ in conjunction with ‘the productive effects of those practices and the conditions for their efficacy’ (ibid., 49). I argue that Arponen et al. detect two different ‘practices’ of representation, and whilst they indicate the efficacy of environmental determinism through the observation that ‘the drivers of change in human societies’ are externalized in such models (Arponen et al. Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019, 4), they actively challenge this discursive formation through the description of an alternative means of interpretation (the anthropology of hazards). To understand the wider implications of this observation, I shall unpack the discursive formation using Barad (Reference Barad2007) and Foucault (Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972; Reference Foucault, Burchell, Gordon and Miller1991) in the next section.
The discursive formation
When we can detect a pattern of statements emerging such that we might recognize a ‘discourse’, we identify a ‘discursive formation’ (Foucault Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972, 38). By highlighting how the researcher who focuses on humans responding to an external event produces a different narrative to the researcher who acknowledges the sociocultural situation that informed the same event, Arponen et al. illustrate two fundamentally different approaches that yield very different interpretations – two discursive formations. In both methods the event is not simply being described but defined – and here I mean (using the language of Barad) that the boundaries of the event are being drawn by the researcher in relation to the event through the analytical model (or apparatus) they employ (Barad Reference Barad2007, 147). I propose that a Baradian-inspired analysis would view the different approaches (for example, anthropology of hazards and palaeo-environmental archaeology) as different types of ‘measurement’; she explains that ‘there is something fundamental about the nature of measurement interactions such that, given a particular measuring apparatus, certain properties become determinate, while others are specifically excluded’ (ibid., 19). Reflecting on this point, it seems that the anthropology of hazards brings forth vulnerabilities at community level whereas environmental determinism spotlights the key role changing climates have on humans, while actively excluding the impact of variable human experiences.
Whilst both analyses occur retrospectively, one measurement places the crux after the event, and the other places the crux before the event (Arponen et al. Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019, 8–9); both commit to Newtonian causality (cause–effect). I propose that a polymorphous causal model (as outlined by Foucault Reference Foucault, Burchell, Gordon and Miller1991, 58) would recognize both discourses. It seems important to state that how these interpretations are produced and relate to each other should also be considered (as a ‘system of dispersion’ – Foucault Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972, 37–38); it is not a matter of either/or, but of how the ‘patterns of difference’ in the discourse emerged (Barad Reference Barad2007, 50; see also Foucault Reference Foucault, Burchell, Gordon and Miller1991, 62). These two different approaches to the same event reveal ‘dispersed events’ (Foucault Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972, 22) that are collectively valuable to our understanding of the matter at hand. Rather than one model being apolitical and the other political (cf. Arponen et al. Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019, 20) – I maintain that all discourse is political (see Barad Reference Barad2007, 146).
On determinism
Clearly, the Arponen et al. (Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019) paper demonstrates that there is a dispersion of events that can help us understand the matter at hand; there is a cluster of correlative events that are entwined, and it would seem foolish to portray the matter through slicing and compartmentalizing the events arbitrarily. Foucault queries determinism and unmasks Newtonian causality as problematic, offering instead a polymorphous structure of relations (Foucault Reference Foucault, Burchell, Gordon and Miller1991, 58; polymorphous here means ‘many forms’); he writes, ‘I would like to substitute this whole play of dependencies for the uniform, simple notion of allocating causality; and by suspending the indefinitely extended privilege of the cause, to render apparent the polymorphous interweaving of correlations’ (ibid., 58). In response to Arponen et al., I suggest that by embracing a polymorphous causal framework that accommodates entwined correlational clusters (a system of dispersion), we can ensure that the complexities of a situation are not oversimplified. We might consider that there are different methods of analysis entwined with particular discourses (as identified by Arponen et al.) and that these discourses tend to be focused on continuities – sameness – and are organized by a ‘principle of coherence’ (Foucault Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972, 22). By drawing these two discourses into high contrast, I propose that Arponen et al. have hit upon a rupture (or a ‘discontinuity’) in the archaeological discourse, and this observation is a good thing, as it means we are not perpetuating a ‘total history’ that falsely links events in a seamless unilinear fashion. Rather, by recognizing a dispersion of events (a correlation of clusters) – instead of a crux – we can begin to reveal the complexities of the situation.
Conclusion
Failing to acknowledge the integral role the researcher plays in the (re)production of grand narratives (or, to quote Foucault Reference Foucault and Sheridan-Smith1972, 9, ‘total histories’) built on the foundations of Newtonian causality is an issue that we can frame as representationalism. Arponen et al. (Reference Arponen, Dörfler, Feeser, Grimm, Groß, Hinz and Ribeiro2019, 3) forgivingly interpret environmental determinism as a methodology that has a ‘weakness or blind spot’. It seems pertinent to state that offering a hypothesis for the existence, flux and flow of past communities is one thing; monopolizing human stories through the reproduction of dominant discourses that restrict the circulation of alternative narratives is another. This is by no means a symptom of weakness, but an expression of power, and one that should not go unchallenged.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Oliver Harris for reading an early draft of this paper and offering insightful comments. This paper is the result of my own research and so any errors are my own.