Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-d8cs5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T06:22:21.581Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reconsidering the Tartarean Geography of the Iliad: Traces of a Far-Away Tartarus and the Narrative Significance of Localisation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 December 2022

Joel A. Gordon*
Affiliation:
University of Otago, New Zealand
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This paper argues for a novel conception of Iliadic Tartarus as a fluid liminal space which includes a superterranean context alongside its (traditionally realised) subterranean localisation. A close reading of Iliad 8.47781 reveals traces of superterranean imagery which, alongside the traditional subterranean reading of 8.136 and 14.198311, allows for the identification of a fluid, dual-model of Tartarean space within the background of the poem. Further, grounded in recent developments regarding dual localisation within Homeric narrative, this paper explores how localisation can reflect narrative and/or thematic concerns, rather than exclusively denoting spatial-physical realities. Thus, the use of geographical imagery within the three Tartarean passages is examined for its narrative/thematic significance, considering themes such as the hierarchy of the gods and narrative developments such as the relocation of Zeus’ positioning within the larger cosmos. The identification of such nuances, in turn, provides a precedent for retaining ‘conflicting’ or fluid geographical space(s) within the narrative despite the ‘contradictions’ that they embody.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Australasian Society for Classical Studies

When a literal reading of spatial geography is applied to the Homeric poems, the narrative quickly descends into chaos: the audience is presented with a jumbled mess of spatial and geographical contradictions that simply cannot exist in a physical reality. As a case in point, consider one of the more infamous instances of this issue: Hades’ localisation in the Odyssey. The epic's vision of Hades presents the realm of the dead as both a subterranean and superterranean locale at different points in the narrative.Footnote 1 Due to the discordant nature of such inconsistencies, these spatial contradictions tend (at least historically so) to be identified as the result of interpolation and thus ‘questionable’ passages are excised from the text.Footnote 2 But this need not be so: recent scholarship has recognised that spatial anomalies can result from the general fluidity of landscape creation in service to particular narrative demands from the act of poetic construction.Footnote 3 Within such a framework, epic topography can be read as hyperspatial and hyperphysical, resolving spatial inconsistences without requiring excisions to occur. To be clear, this is not to suggest that topographical inconsistencies be glossed over – far from it. Instead, the presence of such ‘contradictions’ can be accounted for via a deeper layer of meaning: meaning which is not strictly spatial in a this world-physical sense but is driven by a concern for narrative/thematic priority.Footnote 4

This paper seeks to further the study of epic topography's fluidity by considering a particular expression of dual localisation (whereby a single place might be located in two distinct spaces).Footnote 5 While there are many such instances within Homeric epic,Footnote 6 this paper has chosen a singular case study: Iliadic Tartarus. In doing so, this paper presents a novel hypothesis for consideration: the geographical descriptions of Tartarus in Books 8 and 14 present Tartarus as a fluid, liminal space by including alternative, superterranean imagery alongside its traditional subterranean localisation. The presence of these fluid topographies can be accounted for via a narrative/thematic reading of the text. Consequently, by removing the need for a strictly physical-spatial understanding of geography, a larger thesis is affirmed: descriptions of landscape can, in the hands of a skilled poet, serve as a tool to emphasise particular thematic or conceptual concerns and thus a more fluid understanding of spatiality must be brought to bear on such texts.Footnote 7

It must be acknowledged that this claim of a fluid, dual localisation is far from uncontroversial. The majority of scholarship has read the Iliad as presenting a singular and unified vision of Tartarus – i.e., as exclusively subterranean – including relatively recent work by Kirk, Albinus, and Wilson.Footnote 8 Yet, a minority has questioned this exclusivity of place: for example, Bowra specifically identifies Iliad 8.16 and 8.480 as providing contradictory localisations for Tartarus while, more recently, Jouanna has identified ‘ambiguous passages that may contradict the subterranean location of Tartarus in the Iliad’.Footnote 9 This paper builds upon such precedents in two significant ways: first, by providing a detailed reading of this ambiguous/contradictory material, in particular the presence of the superterranean imagery; and, second, rather than dismissing out of hand the issues that such duality raises – for example, Bowra was content to simply state that Homer ‘was not concerned with exactitude in such matters’Footnote 10 – to demonstrate how geographical fluidity is of narrative significance.

1. Iliad 8.1–27: Subterranean Tartarus and the Theme of Zeus’ Superiority

Iliad 8 provides the first extended description of Tartarus, its nature, and its locality. At the book's opening Zeus threatens the other Olympians in order to ensure that they adhere to his divine decree and do not interfere in the battle for Troy, outlining two potential consequences for those who dare to defy him (Il. 8.127). The first punishment is to be struck by lightning after which the offender, albeit in rather poor condition (οὐ κατὰ κόσμον), may return to Olympus (8.12).Footnote 11 The second fate, by comparison, is far worse:

ἤ μιν ἑλών ῥίψω ἐς Τάρταρον ἠɛρόɛντα,
τῆλɛ μάλ’, ἧχι βάθιστον ὑπὸ χθονός ἐστι βέρɛθρον,
ἔνθα σιδήρɛιαί τɛ πύλαι καὶ χάλκɛος οὐδός,
τόσσον ἔνɛρθ’ Ἀίδɛω ὅσον οὐρανός ἐστ’ ἀπὸ γαίης·
Hom. Il. 8.1316

Or I will grab hold of the culprit and throw them into murky Tartarus – far, far away – where the deep pit below the earth is located. That is the site of the gates of iron and the threshold of iron. It is as far below Hades as the heavens are distant from the earth.

The localisation presented here is unambiguously subterranean: Tartarus is explicitly described as below the earth (8.14: ὑπὸ χθονός) and even below Hades (8.16: τόσσον ἔνɛρθ’ Ἀίδɛω). Considering the equally clear subterranean localisation for Hades provided later in Book 20 (Il. 20.615) and given that this Tartarean localisation matches the Hesiodic description of the cosmos (according to which a bronze anvil would take ten days to fall from the sky to earth and then another ten from earth to Tartarus, Theog. 7215), this vertical structuring of the cosmos has been understood to reflect a ‘typical’ archaic worldview and cosmology:Footnote 12 Tartarus is beneath Hades and earth; οὐρανός is above earth; and the distance between Tartarus and Hades is equidistant to that which separates earth and οὐρανός.

This picture of a vertical, hierarchical cosmos continues throughout the remainder of Zeus’ speech of which the above threats form the first half (Il. 8.717; cf. 8.1827). While part one presents a sanguine attempt by Zeus to dissuade the other gods from challenging his wishes, the second part presents Zeus as a cynical figure against whom the other Olympians are an opposing force to be overcome.Footnote 13 Like its antecedent, this latter half utilises geographical imagery for rhetorical effect, retaining the hierarchical presentation of the cosmos albeit excluding any direct mention of Tartarus and is similarly focused on the theme of Zeus’ power. This theme is evident throughout both halves of Zeus’ speech since the god concludes each section by proclaiming himself to be ‘the strongest by far’ and ‘greatest of all the gods’ (8.17, 8.27), a boast which Athena confirms when she subsequently addresses her father as the ‘highest of lords’ (8.31: ὕπατɛ κρɛιόντων) and acknowledges his ‘irresistible might’ (8.32: τοι σθένος οὐκ ἐπιɛικτόν).

There is a clear relationship throughout the Iliad between powerful individuals and spatial height. In a general sense, height connotes regal power: for example, Mackie notes that the location of the houses of Priam and his family on the citadel of Pergamus is indicative of their social standing as the ruling family of Troy.Footnote 14 Further, of particular relevance to the divine sphere, the notion of ‘falling’ from the heavens equates to a quasi-death state for immortal beings within which the gods can be understood to ‘lose’ their immortality.Footnote 15 Thus, the act of throwing gods from extreme heights is a ‘favourite punishment’ of Zeus, one which comes to define Zeus’ superiority since he alone cannot be ‘pulled down’ towards the mortal condition.Footnote 16 This depiction of Zeus’ superiority is consistent with the Iliad's narrative concern in examining the relationship between Zeus’ divine providence and the events of the Trojan War (e.g., 1.5247).Footnote 17 Thus, in the context of 8.13–16, the cosmic (geographic) and divine hierarchies serve as parallel images of this main theme: Tartarus is the domain of those at the lowest rung of the divine hierarchy (i.e., those who oppose the will of Zeus) and it is likewise located at the lowest point of cosmic-geographic hierarchy.

2. Iliad 8.477–83: Superterranean Possibilities and a Thematic Shift

Later in Book 8 Tartarus is referenced again but, alongside the expected, traditional subterranean material, this description includes alternative imagery connoting a localisation at the horizontal edges of the earth. When Zeus confronts Hera – who has been plotting to assist the Greeks in blatant disregard of his earlier warning (Il. 8.350437) – he describes Tartarus via very different spatial language:

…σέθɛν δ’ ἐγὼ οὐκ ἀλɛγίζω
χωομένης, οὐδ’ ɛἴ κɛ τὰ νɛίατα πɛίραθ’ ἵκηαι
γαίης καὶ πόντοιο, ἵν’ Ἰάπɛτός τɛ Κρόνος τɛ
ἥμɛνοι οὔτ’ αὐγῇς ̓Υπɛρίονος Ἠɛλίοιο
τέρποντ’ οὔτ’ ἀνέμοισι, βαθὺς δέ τɛ Τάρταρος ἀμφίς:
οὐδ᾽ ἢν ἔνθ᾽ ἀφίκηαι ἀλωμένη, οὔ σɛυ ἐγώ γɛ
σκυζομένης ἀλέγω…
Hom. Il. 8.47783

I am not concerned with your anger, not even if you were to go to the most extreme edges of the earth and sea. That is where Iapetus and Cronus are, sitting frivolously, unable to enjoy the light of the sun, nor the wind. Instead, deep Tartarus surrounds them. Even if you go there on your wanderings, I am not concerned with your anger…

While notably still ‘deep’ (481: βαθύς; cf. 414: βαθίστον), Tartarus's localisation is accounted for via its spatial relationship with the figures Iapetus (the father of Prometheus) and Cronus (the father of Zeus) whom Tartarus surrounds (481: ἀμφίς). These figures, in turn, are described as being located at τὰ νɛίατα πɛίρατα (‘the most extreme boundaries’) of γαῖα and πόντος (‘land’ and ‘sea’). With πɛίρατα γαίης serving as a common formula to identify the ‘boundaries of earth/land’ and given that πɛῖραρ is itself ‘a particularly complex indicator of edge-space’ with a multiplicity of physical and conceptual applications,Footnote 18 this phrasing becomes an important aspect for any reading of Tartarus’ present localisation.

2.1. Locating Tartarus’ Superterranean Connotations

Scholarship favouring an exclusively subterranean Iliadic Tartarus presents a very specific reading of the phrase τὰ νɛίατα πɛίρατα… γαίης καὶ πόντοιο that must be addressed before moving forward with our thesis of fluidity. Such traditional readings interpret Iliad 8 (notably as a single unit, rather than two distinct descriptions) via the external text of Hesiod's Theogony. For example, according to Kirk, πόντος reveals an intertextual link with the springs and boundaries found in Hesiod's subterranean Tartarus (Theog. 7369, 80710) and thus ‘the addition of καὶ πόντοιο shows that νɛίατα, after all, has its strict sense of “lowest”’.Footnote 19 Albinus pushes this conclusion further, stating ‘[this] instance so closely reflect[s] the instances in Hesiod that one cannot help thinking of the possibility of interpolation in the Homeric case’, and thus since Hesiod is most clearly subterranean Homer must follow suit.Footnote 20 On the one hand, this line of argumentation is correct in noting how certain aspects of the Iliadic description (especially 8.136) present Homeric Tartarus via language and concepts similar to that of the Hesiodic account. Consider, for example, the repetition of the adjective ‘murky’ (ἠɛρόɛντα: Hom. Il. 8.13, cf. Hes. Theog. 119, 682); the presence of the gates and threshold of iron (τɛ πύλαι καὶ χάλκɛος οὐδός: Hom. Il. 8.15≈Hes. Theog. 811); and the tripartite division of the universe into sky, earth and Hades/Tartarus (Hom. Il. 8.16≈Hes. Theog. 7367 = 8078). However, when these similarities are pushed further to suggest that subterranean imagery is consistently and exclusively utilised throughout Iliad 8 several issues arise.

First, strict intertextuality is only one possible explanation for these texts' commonalities and thus the presence of shared material should not be taken to infer that both poems share an identical geographical paradigm. For example, the ‘sharing’ of topographical imagery between Homer and Hesiod can also be understood via Currie's notion of ‘connotative allusion’ rather than strict interpolation.Footnote 21 This framework allows for the acknowledgment of shared material while also leaving room for the Iliad to move beyond an exclusively subterranean presentation simply because that is what the ‘original’ text presents. Indeed, Purves’ examination of the Hesiodic-Homeric link concludes that ‘although Il. 8.1516 closely parallels Hes. Th. 811 and 720, the Theogony is much more interested than the Iliad in constructing an underground geography’.Footnote 22 Thus, while the Theogony's subterranean Tartarus reflects a deliberate choice on the part of that poet, embodying narrative and eschatological themes specific to that particular poem, it should not be expected that these are to be adopted automatically by the poet of the Iliad.Footnote 23

Another issue with approaches that are focused on strict intertextuality is that, while the presence of Hesiodic material is strongly felt within the first Iliadic description of Tartarus (Il. 8.1316), the second Iliadic description (8.47781) is less firm in its use of Hesiodic material. For example, Kirk places much emphasis upon the inclusion of καὶ πόντοιο (Il. 8.479) for his rendering of the otherwise flexible term νɛίατα.Footnote 24 Yet, from a strict intertextual perspective, it should be noted that the Theogony pairs πόντος with οὐρανός (Theog. 737) while the Iliad pairs πόντος with γαία (Il. 8.479). Thus, while both works clearly utilise a shared tripartite model of the cosmos, differing emphases are placed on certain aspects of said model at this point in the poem: it is not a given, as Kirk and Albinus suggest, that Homer's vision of space is strictly following Hesiod's ‘version’ of the tripartite model.Footnote 25 This further undermines the notion of a strict intertextual relationship according to which the Iliadic Tartarus at 8.47781 is to be identified as exclusively subterranean.

Finally, the most pressing issue against such lines of argumentation is that the Hesiodic presentation of Tartarus does not necessarily exclude superterranean imagery. Nakassis, following his identification of the co-existence of uni-polar and bi-polar models of sun-movement in Archaic epic, draws upon Bergren's study of πɛίραρ to conceive of Hesiod's Tartarus as both cosmologically central and yet also at the edges of the earth (Theog. 731: ἔσχατα γαίης).Footnote 26 Further, Nakassis’ study identifies not two but three potential threshold localisations within Hesiod's presentation of Tartarus, each located along a unique axis: the horizontal, the vertical, and the temporal.Footnote 27 Such a reading calls into question whether Iliadic Tartarus should be identified as exclusively subterranean due to its reliance upon/similarity to Hesiodic material since the localisation of the latter is itself fluid.Footnote 28

Putting intertextual arguments now to one side, there are numerous internal reasons for identifying superterranean connotations within the phrase τὰ νɛίατα πɛίρατα… γαίης καὶ πόντοιο (8.4789), beginning with the modifier νɛίατα. While commonly translated as ‘lowest’ and thus relating to positioning along the vertical axis (i.e., a subterranean reading), νɛίατος contains a broad semantic range within Homeric poetry which includes the more generic sense of ‘furthest’.Footnote 29 Indeed, elsewhere within the Iliad, νɛίατος consistently possesses a sense of ‘horizontal bounds’, rather than vertical distance, when utilised in geographical descriptions.Footnote 30 Consider the following examples. The first geographical use of νɛίατος occurs in a description of Zeleia during the catalogue of ships (2.8247). This city, from which Pandarus’ troops hail, is described as ὑπαὶ πόδα νɛίατον Ἴδης (2.824: ‘below the furthest foot of Mt. Ida’). The poet also locates this city via an association with the river Aesepus which suggests a position some 70 miles ENE from Troy which – even Kirk agrees – can only be considered a part of Mt. Ida ‘in a fairly loose sense’ (see fig. 1).Footnote 31 While this phrase might be translated as the ‘lowest foot of Mt. Ida’ – as per the translations of Murray and Wyatt and of KirkFootnote 32 – this use of νɛίατος is contextually superterranean since the poet is describing the extreme horizontal distance of the city in comparison to the mountain's location. The next geographical occurrence of νɛίατος is in reference to the seven cities which Agamemnon promised as a dowry for Achilles in his (failed) attempt to placate the hero: Cardamyle, Enope, Hire, Pherae, Antheia, Aepeia and Pedasus (9.14954, 2919). These cities are collectively described with the single hexameter line πᾶσαι δ’ ἐγγὺς ἁλός, νέαται Πύλου ἠμαθόɛντος (9.153 = 9.295: ‘All are near the sea, [at] the edges of Sandy Pylos’). It is hardly appropriate to translate νέαται here as ‘lowest’ for, as Hainsworth has noted, this would contradict the political geography of the region and thus ‘the word must signify “just beyond the borders of”’ – again, a superterranean/horizontal context.Footnote 33 This interpretive issue was known even during antiquity for the Alexandrians suggested that, instead of ‘lower’ which would make little sense, perhaps this particular inclusion of νέαται was to be read as the third person plural of the verb ναίω (in reference to place, ‘to be situated’; with a construction similar to κέαται < κɛῖμαι).Footnote 34 Again, this implies that during antiquity the passage was envisaged as connoting a horizontal context, rather than a vertical one, for otherwise there would be no interpretative issue for which a solution would be required. A final occurrence of νɛίατος appears in the description of the city of Thryoessa: τηλοῦ ἐπ’ Ἀλφɛιῷ, νέατη Πύλου ἠμαθόɛντος (11.712: ‘[it is] far away on the Alpheus [river], the edge of Sandy Pylos’). In addition to the above reasoning – for 9.153b = 9.295b≈11.712b – νɛίατος is here paired with the complementary adverb τηλοῦ (‘afar’) which is utilised elsewhere in reference to the ‘furthest’ ends of civilization on the horizontal plane.Footnote 35 Thus, these examples provide a strong internal precedent for reading τὰ νɛίατα πɛίρατα as indicating horizontal (superterranean) boundaries, rather than vertical (subterranean) ones.

Similarly, the combination of πɛίρατα with γαῖα and πόντος (‘the boundaries of land and sea’), rather than with πόντος with οὐρανός as in Hesiod (Theog. 737), contains echoes of the well-established tradition of localizing liminal superterranean space via bodies of water. Archaic poetry is full of spaces/places which are both identified as πɛίρατα γαίης and are located by, or near, water: Hesiod's Garden of the Hesperides (Theog. 335, 518) and Islands of the Blest (Op. 163); the Odyssey's Elysian plain (4.563); the shore where Dawn takes immortal Tithonus (Hom. Hymn Aph. 5.227); and fragments from both the Cypria (fr. 10 West) and Orphic poetry, notably describing where the sun leaps up from (fr. 238 Kern), pair Oceanus’ stream with πɛίρατα γαίης.Footnote 36 Indeed, such is the strength of this association that every Hesiodic example of the ‘ends of the earth’ is located on or near the ocean stream with Hesiodic Tartarus being the only exception to this ‘rule’.Footnote 37 Thus, it may also be of some significance that the Hesiodic terminology for Tartarus’ ‘ends of the earth’ is ἔσχατα γαίης (Theog. 731), rather than πɛίρατα.Footnote 38

Finally, the pairing of Cronus and Iapetus must also be considered for its connotative load, since it is these individuals’ presence upon which Tartarus’ localisation is hung. Beginning with the figure of Iapetus, there is little comparative material to go on given that he is quite a rare figure within the Greek mythic tradition and that the majority of his appearances in extant texts occur in genealogical accounts establishing Prometheus’ parentage.Footnote 39 Yet there are a small number of noteworthy spatial connections which highlight the Titan's spatial fluidity. First, there may be a connection between Iapetus and subterranean punishment via a potential etymology for his name as ‘the one hurled down’ (from ἰάπτɛιν) – but this issue remains equivocal.Footnote 40 More definitive is that, as a Titan, Iapetus shares a definitive (albeit generalised) connection both with Cronus – his brother and fellow Titan – and with Tartarus-the-prison since these elements consistently feature within tellings of the Titanomachy and the Titans’ failed revolt against Zeus which, in turn, are associated with negative, subterranean contexts.Footnote 41 Yet, while these associations affirm Tartarus’ subterranean localisation and may be considered the more traditional aspects of the two Titans’ characterisations, they do not represent the complete picture. In contrast, there is another specific instance of Iapetus and Cronus’ coupling within the opening invocation of Hesiod's Theogony (18) – the only other direct comparative of its kind in extant literature – which places the pair in a positive context divorced from any notion of punishment (subterranean or otherwise).Footnote 42 Furthermore, with regards to the figure of Cronus – for whom in comparison to all the other Titans there exists a wealth of mythic material and cultFootnote 43 – there are two recurrent spatial themes relating to horizontal edge-space: (1) an association with a sea/island at the western/northern edges of the earth (in some instances connected with banishment/punishment);Footnote 44 and, (2) an exclusively positive association with an ‘Isles of the Blest’ cum ‘Golden Age’/utopian setting and an accompanying ease of life which is overseen/ruled by Cronus at the (mythical) edges of the earth.Footnote 45

The concept of a peripheral Cronian sea/island is affiliated with various peoples and/or places (in both the ‘real’ and mythic worlds) which themselves have clear superterranean, liminal localisations. For example, in Apollonius of Rhodes’ Argonautica, the ‘Cronian sea’ (i.e., Κρονίης ἁλός: 4.327, 509, 548) is connected with the Colchian and Phaeacian peoples – both of whom have a long history of association with the horizontal periphery;Footnote 46 in Plutarch, the ‘island of Cronus’ is another name for Ogygia which has a similar history of liminality and is also localised here at the setting of the sun (De fac. 26.941A, C);Footnote 47 in Strabo, a temple of Cronus and Heracles is associated with the city Gadeira/Gades (i.e., the island of Erytheia) which, in geographical thought, was identified for a long time as the western edge of civilisation (3.5.3);Footnote 48 likewise, following Bilić, Cronus’ association with the Adriatic Sea could also be read in light of the contemporary understanding that this was the then known edge of the world.Footnote 49

The Cronian-utopic environ, by comparison, contains even stronger connections with superterranean liminality. Both Hesiod (Op. 17069) and Pindar (Ol. 2.708) utilise similar poetic imagery in describing a ‘blessed’ afterlife place that is associated with Cronus:Footnote 50 for Hesiod this is the ‘Islands of the Blessed’ (ἐν μακάρων νήσοισι) where Cronus is ‘king’ (τοῖσιν… ἐμβασιλɛύɛι); while for Pindar this is the ‘Isle of the Blessed’ (μακάρων νᾶσος) where the ‘tower of Cronus’ is located (Κρόνου τύρσιν).Footnote 51 While Hesiod is explicit in associating this place/space with the ends of the earth – literally, ἐς πɛίρατα γαίης (Op. 168) – Pindar should be understood as implicitly positioning this space likewise. Recent scholarship has interpreted Pindar's three afterlives as representing three distinct ‘levels’ within a geographical schema:Footnote 52 two linked subterranean (literally ‘beneath the earth’, κατὰ γᾶς: Ol. 2.59) underworld fates (‘a level of punishment, and a level of carefree existence’) and a third fate which, to quote Gazis, ‘appears to be located in a different space altogether’.Footnote 53 While the question of this latter group's localisation is certainly complex, there are good reasons for reading this as a superterranean, liminal setting. First, as Gazis notes, there is a clear contrast made between the former two groups who are explicitly positioned ‘beneath the earth’ and this third group whose mode of ‘living’ is unique and clearly resembles that of earth.Footnote 54 Further, there are numerous echoes here with other poetic/narrative descriptions of superterranean liminal phenomena:Footnote 55 e.g., the Homeric vision of the Elysian Plain (Od. 4.5619: Ἠλύσιον πɛδίον); and various accounts of a prior ‘heroic’/Golden Age under the rule of Cronus in the works of Hesiod (Op. 10920),Footnote 56 Cratinus (Ploutoi: frs. 172, 176, 363), and Plato (Plt. 271d72b). While encompassing a broad spectrum of thematic and mythic connections, these places are all clearly located upon the horizontal plane if not explicitly at its edges.Footnote 57 Thus, Cronus is a figure with very clear connections to a variety of horizontal edge-space traditions which may be associated with his positioning at τὰ νɛίατα πɛίρατα… γαίης καὶ πόντοιο in Iliad 8.

2.2. Reading 8.477–83 via a Fluid Localisation

What then of the relationship between these superterranean connotations and the larger thematic/narrative context within which this fluid spatiality occurs? On the one hand, there can be little doubt that 8.47783 is intended to recollect and renew Zeus’ earlier challenge(s) to the gods to test him (cf. 8.527) and the accompanying theme of cosmic/divine hierarchies. This second description of Tartarus occurs immediately after the climax of Book 8 wherein Hera and Athena unsuccessfully attempt to do exactly what Zeus had earlier prohibited (8.350484) and thus, as Kirk concludes, this passage provides ‘final confirmation of the book's central theme, namely that Zeus’ will is paramount’.Footnote 58 Within such a reading, the geographical description of Tartarus as πɛίρατα γαίης may be explained as a simple rhetorical hyperbole in service to the Iliad's theme of Zeus’ sovereignty:Footnote 59 i.e., regardless of the lengths to which Hera might go – even if she were to go to the very ends of the earth – she is unable to bend Zeus’ will for he is the supreme divinity.

Yet, on the other hand, the careful crafting of this Tartarean description is evident in that Zeus’ remarks form a chiastic pattern: ‘I am not concerned with your anger, not even if you were to go to the most extreme edges… even if you go there on your wanderings, I am not concerned with your anger’ (8.4778, 4823).Footnote 60 This structural device emphasises the middle section (within which the description of Iapetus, Cronus and Tartarus occur: 47981) and thus suggests not only that it is the result of deliberate compositional choices but also that it is of narrative significance.Footnote 61 This, in turn, affirms that these spatial inconsistencies do not need excision, but rather that further analysis is required as to identify their integration within the poem.

As already suggested, Tartarus, Iapetus and Cronus’ association with the πɛίρατα γαίης serves a rhetorical purpose; however, this is more than just acting as a radical hyperbole. These aspects of Zeus’ response to Hera colour the extremity of Hera's actions as negative in tone by connoting prior failed challenges against the sovereignty of Zeus.Footnote 62 While this connotative load does not relate directly to Tartarus’ localisation, that is itself significant: it illustrates that the emphasis here lies not in the geography's spatiality but in the thematic and mythic background that such imagery draws upon. This is notably different from the use of geographical imagery within the earlier description of Tartarus since, in that instance, spatiality was central to the image of mirrored cosmic and divine hierarchies. This change is what allows for the Tartarean localisation to ‘open up’ to superterranean imagery alongside the ‘traditional’ representation of ‘deep’ Tartarus.

A notable spatial-thematic shift has also occurred since Zeus’ earlier threats: the god is no longer situated on Mt. Olympus but has repositioned himself within the cosmos, far away from the other Olympians, on Mt. Ida (Il. 8.4752). This spot is a significant one both temporally and thematically: according to Mackie, Zeus spends as much as a third of the entire narrative at this location;Footnote 63 and it is when he is positioned here that Zeus lends his support to the Trojans against the Greeks, apparently in contradiction to his own orders that the gods not interfere in the battle (cf. 1.493527). On the one hand, Mt. Ida is an appropriate location for Zeus to enact such ‘patronage’ since it is the home of the Trojan cult to Zeus (8.4752), representing a sacred space/place wherein the spheres of the immortals and mortals not only meet but interact.Footnote 64 Thus this space is notably a liminal one in its own right, similar in many regards to other peripheral places such as the land of the Ethiopians where gods and mortals interact (which are themselves superterranean).Footnote 65 Further, as Mackie notes, this shift in localisation has also had narrative consequences, for Mt. Ida is a place at which Zeus’ actions reflect his cosmic positioning: Zeus has separated himself from the other gods both physically (for they remain on Mt. Olympus) and behaviourally (for they are prohibited from interfering in the Trojan war).Footnote 66 This is itself a reflection of the recurrent theme of Zeus’ superiority for, as the god himself stated previously, he is the ‘greatest of all the gods’ (8.27) but here he demonstrates this reality via his interaction with the human sphere (which he alone is entitled to do), rather than the geographical display of a divine/cosmic hierarchy.

3. Iliad 14 (198–210, 271–80, 301–11): Further Descriptions of Tartarus

As a final demonstration of how localisation and thematic concerns might interact, one further presentation of Tartarus ought to be considered. During the Dios apate episode (14.153377), Tartarus is described via subterranean imagery within a specific mythic content: the Titanomachy. The first two allusions to Tartarus are subtle and implicit, understood only after the fact, for the initial referent of the localisation is Cronus: first, Hera briefly relates how Cronus was ‘forced below (νέρθɛ καθɛῖσɛ) the earth and the unresting sea’ by Zeus (Il. 14.2034); then, this is reiterated by Hypnos when he requires Hera to swear an oath invoking Styx and ‘the gods below (οἱ ἔνɛρθɛ θɛοί) with Cronus’ (14.274). Yet, when the poet reprises the swearing of this oath, the earlier localiser ‘below with Cronus’ (14.274) is replaced with ‘beneath [in] Tartarus’ (14.2789: θɛοὺς… τοὺς ὑποταρταρίους). Not only does this firmly establish a connection between Cronus and Tartarus (14.27780; cf. 14.2716), but it defines the identity of ‘those below’ – the aforementioned θɛοί – as Titans (14.279: οἳ Τιτῆνɛω καλέονται) and provides a significant contextual reference to the Titanomachy.Footnote 67 This subterranean localisation is notable in that it reshuffles the positioning presented at 8.47783. Once again, however, this fluidity of space/place illustrates the poet's larger concern with narrative/thematic matters, rather than a strict adherence to a set geographical paradigm.

This reference to the Titanomachy serves to re-accentuate the earlier theme of Zeus’ sovereignty. This focus is not surprising given that many extra-textual depictions of the Titanomachy also address this theogonic theme, which often culminates in the division of the cosmos and the granting of attributes to Zeus, Poseidon and Hades.Footnote 68 It also makes narrative sense to highlight this theme at this point in the poem: by reminding the audience of the fate of those who opposed Zeus, the poet is creating narrative tension to once again question Hera's loyalty and fate. Such is the strength of the motif of Hera's loyalty that Bray has suggested that 14.198210 ‘almost form[s] an answer’ to the question posed by Zeus at 8.47881.Footnote 69 Yet Tartarus’ localisation within the Dios apate is complicated by this deliberate echo of 8.47781 since it draws attention to the contrasting localisation of Cronus himself.

As with Zeus’ speech in Book 8, Hera's use of the phrase πɛίρατα γαιῆς features as part of a carefully crafted rhetorical device. The poet describes Hera as acting δολοφρονέουσα (Il. 14.197: ‘with cunning intent’) which, as Budelmann and Haubold note, means that ‘we [should] expect a fair amount of rhetorical distortion’.Footnote 70 According to Hera, the reason for her visit to the edges of the earth is to fix Oceanus and Tethys’ marriage (14.20510, 3046). While the authenticity of the claims that this marriage is in jeopardy and of her intent to assist are questionable, elsewhere Hera's deceit is clearly identifiable: at 14.3078 she goes so far as to falsify a verifiable fact, the location of her chariot.Footnote 71 Thus Hera's rhetoric must be interpreted as an elaborate ploy, the purpose of which is to sway the hearer to give in to her ulterior requests. These requests, in turn, will establish Hera in a favourable position to discretely turn the tide of the war in the Greeks’ favour by seducing Zeus (14.35415.34): she first lies to Aphrodite (14.20010) in order to obtain her girdle (14.21421) and, following the success of this, to Zeus (14.30111) with the intent of distracting him from the events of the war by bedding him (14.31314).

What then is the rhetorical purpose of Cronus’ appearance within Hera's falsehoods, specifically that told to Aphrodite?Footnote 72 There is a symmetry between the two primordial couples that Hera references: Hera's birth parents, Rhea and Cronus; and the guardians who nursed her, Oceanus and Tethys.Footnote 73 These pairings set up a thematic contrast in light of the theogonic setting of the Titanomachy: those who threatened the Olympian order (or, in the case of Rhea, hark back to the prior rulership of the cosmos); and those who offer a safe haven and uphold it. There is, of course, an element of irony here since by her words Hera seeks to present herself as akin to Oceanus and Tethys – concerned with the state of their marriage and the impact this may have upon the status quo of the Olympian order; yet, in deed, she is far more like Cronus in that she seeks to actively challenge Zeus’ authority and will. Once again, this thematic contrast is expressed geographically, via the contrast of these primordial figures’ localisation. Oceanus and Cronus are both liminal figures located at the cosmic periphery; however, here their localisations occur on different cosmic axis. The traditional presentation of Oceanus is naturally a superterranean one, at the edges of the earth (cf. 18.6078);Footnote 74 while Cronus – for whom there are multiple localisations – is located under the earth as appropriate to his present association with the Titans and Tartarus as a figure of cosmic rebellion (a return to the hierarchical geography of 8.127). Thus, these thematic reasons require the (spatial) separation of Oceanus and Cronus (inviting the latter to be repositioned away from the superterranean πɛίρατα) rather than maintaining a shared positioning simply for the sake of spatial consistency ‘required’ by the echoing of 8.47783.

4. Tartarus’ Localisation in the Iliad: Deliberately Fluid

Each time Tartarus’ localisation is described within the Iliad the audience is presented not with a fixed geographical reality derived from an immutable space/place, but with a fluid realm that may draw upon multiple geographical traditions and associations depending upon the poet's present narrative requirements. Thus, a close reading of these descriptions uncovers Tartarus’ fluidity with traces of its displacement and (re)location across the vertical and horizontal axes of the cosmos – although notably always retaining a position at the periphery of these axes.

This paper has argued that, rather than deriving from a physical understanding of spatial geography, such examples of dual localisation are to be understood as resulting from narrative/thematic concerns. Thus, the traditional subterranean presentation of Tartarus at Iliad 8.1316 reflects a vertical model of the cosmos which, in turn, embodies the theme of divine hierarchy. As an expression of the ever-present theme of Zeus’ divine will and sovereignty, those who defy Zeus are found at the bottom of the cosmic hierarchy/vertical axis, imprisoned in Tartarus. Next, the description of Tartarus’ localisation at 8.477–83 includes superterranean connotations alongside the more traditional, subterranean material. These connotations are permitted to ‘creep to the surface’ as a result of Zeus’ shift in positioning within the cosmos: now located on Mt. Ida rather than Olympus. While the thematic interest of the poet remains the same (i.e., Zeus’ superiority), this is expressed via Zeus’ unique ability to interact with the human sphere. By expressing this theme thus, the poet has shifted his focus away from the cosmic imagery of the vertical axis and allows for alternative connotations to be read from the localisation. Finally, Book 14 returns to the more traditional depiction of Tartarus’ localisation as ‘below’. Once again, the theme of Zeus’ divine will and sovereignty is at play with echoes relating to both earlier Tartarean passages. Hera's present deceit is a significant point of narrative climax, recalling her rebellious intent at 8.477–83, which sees a return to the subterranean imagery of cosmic/geographical hierarchies. This time, however, there is an additional thematic contrast between the primordial figures of Oceanus and Cronus which predicates their geographical positioning along alternative cosmic axes.

The analysis of these narrative concerns as they relate to the usage of both sub- and super-terranean Tartarus affirms two larger theses relating to landscape use in Homeric epic: (1) a multiplicity of space and place can exist within a text without resorting to explaining such contradictions via claims of interpolation; and, (2) this multiplicity can be understood as logical, not within a ‘this world’ physical-spatial paradigm, but within a framework which places physical geography as subservient to narrative/thematic matters. Thus, it is not necessary to explain away fluid localisations as the result of either an inconsistent/incompetent poet or an inauthentic/inaccurate textual tradition. Rather these can be understood as reflecting deliberate poetic choices which, once brought to the fore, can only enrich current understandings of these narratives.

Footnotes

1 Burgess (Reference Burgess2016) identifies and categorises approaches to the study of Hades’ localisation. Cf., among others, Cousin (Reference Cousin2002) and (Reference Cousin2012), Jouanna (Reference Jouanna2015), Fowler (Reference Fowler and Hawes2017), Gazis (Reference Gazis, Marlow, Pollman and van Noorden2021a) 10811. On Hades as subterranean, in addition to the consensus of scholarship – e.g., Sourvinou-Inwood (Reference Sourvinou-Inwood1995) 59, Cousin (Reference Cousin2012) 83, Jouanna (Reference Jouanna2015) 45 – consider the metonymic descriptions and formulaic statements at Od. 10.175, 10.560, 11.57, 11.65, 11.164, 11.475, 11.625, 12.21, 12.383, 23.252, 24.204. On Hades as superterranean, consider the association with the πɛίρατα via Oceanus (e.g., Od. 11.13, 1559), and the peripheral, horizontal topoi found within both Circe's instructions (10.490540) and Odysseus’ description of the land of the Cimmerians (11.14–19). See further Gordon (Reference Gordon2019) 105, 1513, 186201.

2 While such a view is derived from the analytical giants of the 19th and 20th centuries – i.e., Kirchhoff (Reference Kirchhoff1879), Wilamowitz-Moellendorff (1884) and (1927), Page (Reference Page1955), Stanford (Reference Stanford1965) – it has persisted through to recent studies, as noted, by Clark (Reference Clark, Nagasawa and Matheson2017) 1–42, and Gee (Reference Gee2020) 2443. For a discussion and survey of relevant bibliography, see Gazis (Reference Gazis2018) 80–3.

3 E.g., Johnson (Reference Johnson1999), Haller (Reference Haller2007), Lye (Reference Lye2016), Defouw (Reference Defouw2018), Gazis (Reference Gazis2018), Gordon (Reference Gordon2019). On landscape creation generally, see Haller (Reference Haller2007), McIntyre (Reference McIntyre2009), Kostuch (Reference Kostuch2015) 178, McInerney and Sluiter (Reference McInerney, Sluiter, McInerney and Sluiter2016), Hawes (Reference Hawes and Hawes2017).

4 Gazis (Reference Gazis, Marlow, Pollman and van Noorden2021a: 106) describes a similar conceptualization regarding the poetic presentation of Hades and the land of the Ethiopians: such places are ‘cosmological juxtaposition(s)’ which cannot be described accurately since they lie outside of ‘Homer's poetic gaze’, thus serving as ‘spatial eschatologies par excellence’.

5 Nagy (Reference Nagy1973) and Ballabriga (Reference Ballabriga1986: 75146) identify this phenomenon as coincidentia oppositorum: Nagy (Reference Nagy1973: 1501) defines this as ‘two opposite places which add up to the same place’. This early treatment has since been considered outdated by Ballabriga (Reference Ballabriga1998) 51 and has been superseded by more recent scholarship such as Nakassis (Reference Nakassis2004) 216.

6 On particular types of narrative space in Homeric epic as inherently dualistic see Nakassis (Reference Nakassis2004) 21721, Purves (Reference Purves2010) 6596, Hammond (Reference Hammond2012) xixxxi, Fowler (Reference Fowler and Hawes2017) 24750, Gee (Reference Gee2020) 2352.

7 Although not dealing with spatial material per se, a similar conclusion regarding internal tensions and contradictions is affirmed by Tralau (Reference Tralau2018) 461 and n. 4.

8 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 334 s.v. 47783, Wilson (Reference Wilson1996) 178 s.v. 13, Albinus (Reference Albinus2000) 678, 68 n. 2.

9 Bowra (Reference Bowra1930) 264, Jouanna (Reference Jouanna2015) 23. Cf., more generally, Wender (Reference Wender1978) 26, Bilić (Reference Bilić2013) 248, Gee (Reference Gee2020) 2.

10 Bowra (Reference Bowra1930) 264. Contra Bowra, Gazis (Reference Gazis, Marlow, Pollman and van Noorden2021a: 105) has recently noted ‘space is an important concept in the Homeric epics. The poet goes to great lengths to ensure that his narrative is spatially accurate, and the audience can follow the action with ease, feeling confident in the familiarity of the frame in which it takes place’.

11 The Greek text of the Iliad is Murray and Wyatt (Reference Murray and Wyatt1999) and of the Theogony is Most (Reference Most2006); translations are my own.

12 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 27980 s.v. 15–16, Johnson (Reference Johnson1999) 13 n. 12, Purves (Reference Purves2006) 1978, Gazis (Reference Gazis, Marlow, Pollman and van Noorden2021a) 106. Harrell (Reference Harrell1991: 30910) notes ‘striking dictional similarities’ (albeit with ‘a certain degree of flexibility’) in other archaic descriptions of someone being hurled into Tartarus (i.e., Hom. Hymn Herm. 4.256, Hom. Il. 8.13, Hes. Theog. 868, fr. 30.22 M.-W., fr. 54a.4f M-W), and concludes that these archaic texts are drawing upon a common tradition.

13 Zeus opens by urging the Olympians to ‘accept’ his will (8.9: αἰνɛῖτ’) in order to bring a speedy resolution to the matter at hand (8.9: ὄφρα τάχιστα τɛλɛυτήσω τάδɛ ἔργα), appearing to consider the other divinities as equal partners in achieving his purpose. He then moves to challenge the gods openly and encourage them, if they dare (8.18: ɛἰ δ’ ἄγɛ πɛιρήσασθɛ), to test his resolve in bringing his will to pass. Despite this change of tact, there are clear structural similarities between these two halves: both open with an imperative address (8.79, 18) and a consequential clause (8.9: ὄφρα 8.18: ἵνα); this is then followed by an elaborate description of a threatened action(s) against disobedient gods (8.1016, 1926); before concluding with an explicit statement of Zeus’ superiority (8.17, 27).

14 Mackie (Reference Mackie2014) 5.

15 See Purves (Reference Purves2006). Cf. Il. 1.5904, 5.8978, 8.4025, 14.258, 15.1824, 18.3949, 19.1301. Regarding Hephaestus’ fall in Iliad 1 (5904) – the paradigmatic ‘falling god’ – see Purves (Reference Purves2006) 197201, Mackie (Reference Mackie2014) 56. Cf. Il. 15.1824: Zeus recalls a time when a similar punishment was enacted against Hera. On dying gods in Greek thought generally, see Gordon (Reference Gordon2017) 212 and bibliography at nn. 5, 6, 7.

16 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 296 s.v. 13, Harrell (Reference Harrell1991) 30810, 1519, Purves (Reference Purves2006) 2045. See Harrell (Reference Harrell1991) 317 for a list of Iliadic references to Zeus ejecting from Olympus those who disobey him.

17 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 327 s.v. 350–484. Harrell (Reference Harrell1991) emphasises the ‘theogonic’ scope of such poetic and epic narratives.

19 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 296 s.v. 13, 334 s.v. 47783.

20 Albinus (Reference Albinus2000) 678 (including n. 2).

21 Currie (Reference Currie2016: 35) identifies allusion as referring to the sharing of a general (poetic/mythic) idea/concept by multiple narratives, rather than the linear relationship of intertext to ‘original’.

22 Purves (Reference Purves2006) 182 n. 7. Harrell (Reference Harrell1991: 31517) presents a similar model of semantic and thematic similarities with regards to Hesiod and Il. 8.1316: ‘Instead of explaining these similarities as direct quotations, we should consider the possibility that both poets took these details… from a common tradition.’

23 Johnson (Reference Johnson1999).

24 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 296 s.v. 13, 334 s.v. 47783.

25 Consider further that neither Iliadic description references the πηγαί (‘sources’) of the cosmos despite these forming a foundational part of the Hesiodic account (Theog. 738, 809). Clay (Reference Clay1992: 137) argues for the presence of this element via Hypnos’ identification of Oceanus as ‘the source of all things’ (Hom. Il. 14.246: ὅς πɛρ γένɛσις πάντɛσσι τέτυκται); however, this reading is less than conclusive since the Homeric account differentiates itself by describing Oceanus as the source of all the gods, not just the waters and streams. Alternatively, consider the use of βέρɛθρον to describe Tartarus at Hom. Il. 8.14 which does not find a precedent in Hesiod.

26 Nakassis (Reference Nakassis2004) 21619.

27 Nakassis (Reference Nakassis2004) 219.

28 Bilić (Reference Bilić2013) expands further upon Nakassis (Reference Nakassis2004).

29 This is in direct response to the specifics of Kirk's claim (above) regarding the semantic sense of νɛίατα. Snell (Reference Snell2004, 305 s.v. νɛίατος, νɛάτος) identifies an equivalence with ἔσχατος in some passages.

30 These uses of νɛίατος are to be differentiated from biological descriptions of a battle-wound's location: e.g., ‘lower’ belly or ‘lower’ shoulder (Il. 5.293, 5.857, 11.381, 14.466, 15.341, 16.821, and 17.310). On these uses, see Garland (Reference Garland1981). The present analysis also excludes the ambiguous use of νɛίατος at Il. 6.295 (=Od. 15.108) which describes Hecuba (=Helen) choosing a robe which lay νɛίατος from the rest. Cf. νɛίατος at Od. 7.127 which describes the furthest/last row of vines in the garden of Alcinous.

31 Kirk (Reference Kirk1985) 2534 s.v. 824.

32 Kirk (Reference Kirk1985) 2534 s.v. 824; Murray and Wyatt (Reference Murray and Wyatt1999).

33 Hainsworth (Reference Hainsworth1993) 778 s.v. 14953.

34 Hainsworth (Reference Hainsworth1993) 78 s.v. 14953.

35 Hainsworth (Reference Hainsworth1993) 302 s.v. 712. E.g. Hom. Od. 13.249, 23.68.

36 Such examples do not include descriptions utilising ἔσχατος instead of πɛίρατα: e.g., Aeschylus describes Erytheia as being the ἐσχατιαὶ γαίας and requires Heracles to cross Oceanus in order to reach it (Aesch. fr. 74 Nauck).[36]

37 Zellner (Reference Zellner2008) 51.

38 Since the Theogony is a poetic composition, consideration of meter must also inform its construction and thus this point of difference should not be overemphasised.

39 E.g., aside from Hesiod (who calls Prometheus ‘son of Iapetus’ a total of eight times), see Apollod. Bibl. 1.2.3; Lycoph. 1283, Aesch. PV 18. The Titans generally do not receive detailed narrative treatment in early sources and are found only at Hom. Il. 5.898, 8.4789. 14.274, 279, 15.225, Hes. Theog. 392, 630, 648, 650, 663, 668, 674, 676, 697, 717 (cf. 1337), and the Epic cycles’ Titanomachy. See Bremmer (Reference Bremmer2008) 7480.

40 Bloch (Reference Bloch2006). Cf. Louden (Reference Louden2013) 6. There may also be a connection between Iapetus’ name and the biblical figure of Japheth, son of Noah: see Bremmer (Reference Bremmer2008) 81, Louden (Reference Louden2013).

41 Harrell (Reference Harrell1991) 316, Bremmer (Reference Bremmer2008) 73. For a detailed list on the ‘traditional’ theme of Cronus in Tartarus see Bilić (Reference Bilić2013) 252 and n. 28.

42 van der Valk (Reference van der Valk1985) 5–7.

43 On the cult of Cronus, see Bremmer (Reference Bremmer2008) 825, Tralau (Reference Tralau2018) 463.

44 Van der Valk (Reference van der Valk1985: 56) identifies a related theme locating the Κρονία θάλασσα on the northern borders of the earth; however, this is described as a sea of ice which reflects the ‘frozen waste of Tartarus’. Van der Valk does not identify the primary sources from which this claim may be affirmed. I instead follow Bilić (Reference Bilić2013: 2512) whose discussion of the ‘Sea of Cronus’ likewise finds no specific connection to Tartarus.

45 For a fuller treatment of the concept of utopias (including their placement at the extremities of space), see Evans (Reference Evans2003) and (Reference Evans2008), Gilchrest (Reference Gilchrest2012), and Burton (Reference Burton2016).

46 E.g. on Scheria (in Hom. Od.), see Gordon (Reference Gordon2019) 67–8; on Colchis, see Endsjø (Reference Endsjø1997).

47 Cf. Plut. De def. or. 18.419E–420A which describes Cronus as being confined on the island. In the Homeric tradition, Ogygia is the home of Calypso with clear superterranean liminality as noted by both the use of specific terminology (ἀπονόσφι(ν): 5.113; ἀπόπροθɛ(ν) 7.244; τηλόθɛν: 3.231, 5.55) and idiomatic descriptions: e.g., Hermes notes that Ogygia is distant from the cities of men (5.101: οὐδὲ τις ἄγχι βροτῶν πόλις) and Athena, that it is far from Odysseus’ philoi (5.113: φίλων ἀπονόσφιν) – a statement paralleling Halitherses’ earlier comment in Book 2 (2.164: ἀπάνɛυθɛ φίλων) and corroborating that of Proteus in Book 4 (4.498: ɛὐρέι πόντῳ κατɛρύκɛται, ‘[he is] being held back on the far-reaching sea’).

48 Camacho (Reference Camacho2015: 71) describes Greek and Latin geographical texts as ‘disguising the reality’ of Gadeira/Erytheia ‘though the mythologization of the space known as the Far Western edge of the world’, noting that this continued even in ‘proper [geographical] descriptions’ from the later Hellenistic and Imperial periods. Notably in Hesiod (Theog. 28894), Erytheia is associated with Oceanus and the pillars of Hercules; in Herodotus (4.8), Gadeira is associated with the shore of Oceanus and thus with the setting of the sun; and Strabo (3.5.4) traces the association of Erytheia and Gadeira back to Pherecydes in the fifth century. Camacho (Reference Camacho2015: 667) highlights a connection between Herodotus’ description of the wealth of this region (1.163, 4.152) and the mythical wealth of the edges of the world.

49 Bilić (Reference Bilić2013) 2501. Apollonius of Rhodes (4.5735) places Calypso's Island of Ogygia in the southern Adriatic Sea and thus may also indicate a merging of this tradition with the association of Cronus with the island.

50 As Gazis (Reference Gazis, Reid and Lewis2021c: 112) states: Cronus is ‘a mythic persona that goes hand-in-hand with the Isles of the Blessed’.

51 Gazis (Reference Gazis, Reid and Lewis2021c) 107. The ‘tower of Cronus’ is a landmark that finds no direct parallel anywhere else in Greek literature (likewise the ‘road of Zeus’ at l. 69). Further, Pind. Ol. 2 is the first appearance of τύρις in classical Greek literature, see further Gazis (Reference Gazis, Reid and Lewis2021c) 11213.

53 Edmunds (Reference Edmunds, Dill and Walde2009) 66972, Gazis (Reference Gazis, Gazis and Hooper2021b) 79. Trépanier (Reference Trépanier2017: 1546, 16678) argues for a similar differentiation but, following an Empedoclean and Pythagorean framework, locates the third group in the heavens.

55 This is not to suggest that Ol. 2's eschatology is not unique. As Gazis (Reference Gazis, Gazis and Hooper2021b: 77) notes ‘the image of post-mortem existence that Pindar is painting in this passage is unique in Greek literature and finds only partial parallels in Pythagorean, Orphic, or even Eleusinian contexts’ [emphasis mine].

56 The fate of Pindar's second group also recalls the imagery of the Islands of the Blessed at Hes. Op. 16673; however, Burton (Reference Burton2016: 8) draws a clear distinction between the Islands of the Blessed and the Golden Age: notably, the latter is not an afterlife inhabited by the dead and there is a very different approach to cultural-social elements such as property ownership and production.

57 Burton (Reference Burton2016) 7. This is not the place for an extended discussion on the multiple connections and shared topoi between utopias, loca amoena, blessed landscapes and positive afterlives. Suffice to say that all have commonalities with regards to a far-away localisation, a bountiful environment and a magical/more-than-mortal/otherworldly setting: see further, Burton (Reference Burton2016), Gordon (Reference Gordon2019) 617.

58 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 327 s.v. 350484. Cf. Harrell (Reference Harrell1991) 367, Wilson (Reference Wilson1996) 202 s.v. 47882.

59 This is supported by Bray's (Reference Bray and Felton2018: 489) conclusion that this formula only appears (in the Iliad) within hypothetical or dishonest contexts: i.e., no god or mortal visits the limits of the earth within the narrative.

60 Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 334 s.v. 47783.

61 de Jong (Reference de Jong2001) xvii.

62 Bray (Reference Bray and Felton2018: 47) notes that the unique combination of πɛίρατα γαίης with Tartarus, Iapetus and Cronus presents this ‘as a drastic measure that Hera might take to shock or perhaps blackmail Zeus into compliance with her plans for mortals’. Cf. Wilson (Reference Wilson1996) 202 s.v. 47882, Yasumura (Reference Yasumura2011) 1034.

63 Mackie (Reference Mackie2014) 3, 711.

64 Mackie (Reference Mackie2014) 24, 7, 12.

66 Mackie (Reference Mackie2014) 7–12.

67 On the connection between this phrasing and Hes. Theog., see Kirk (Reference Kirk1990) 2978 s.v. 1516. Cf. van der Valk (Reference van der Valk1985) 56. Likewise, Hom. Hymn. Ap. (3.3346) contains a similar description of the Titans. According to Pausanias (8.37.1), Homer was not only the first to introduce the Titans into poetry, but it was in this very passage.

68 On connection of the Titanomachy with the theme of Zeus’ sovereignty in other sources see, e.g., Hes. Theog. 8815, Aesch. PV 199233, Apollod. Bibl. 1. 67, Hyg. Fab. 150.

71 Janko (Reference Janko1992) 200 s.v. 3078.

72 It is notable that the latter version of Hera's lie which is told to Zeus only mentions Oceanus and Tethys and ignores any reference – both explicit and implicit – to Cronus or Tartarus (14.2004≈14.3013). This omission reflects Hera's change of audience and goal, as Janko (Reference Janko1992: 200 s.v. 3006) has noted: Hera now seeks to emphasise the concepts of marital harmony and the marriage bed (provided here through the proxy of her guardians) in order to ‘arouse’ the correct response in Zeus. This follows the narrative's internal logic: Hera must suppress any mention of Cronus here for he is an entirely inappropriate reference if she is to succeed in her seduction and copulation with Zeus.

73 While the only extant references to Hera having been nursed by Tethys are fragmentary – aside from the present Homeric passages, allusions can be found in Pl. Tht. 152c; Hyg. Fab. 177, Poet. astr. 2.1; Ov. Met. 2.508–11, 527 – it is likely that this relates to events surrounding the Titanomachy: within this context it follows that the maiden Hera would have been placed in the care of Oceanus and Tethys for her protection since Oceanus is named elsewhere as a ‘safe haven’ for divinities: e.g., Hephaestus (Il. 18.395403) and Thetis (24.5961), following Janko (Reference Janko1992) 182 s.v. 2034.

74 The paradigmatic exemplar of this is the shield of Achilles (Il. 18.6078) which places the ποταμός of Oceanus at its edges. On the pairing of Oceanus and πɛίρατα γαιῆς in archaic epic, see Romm (Reference Romm1992) 1216. On the exclusive association in Homeric epic of Oceanus with phenomena connected to the horizontal axis (e.g., the land of the Ethiopians, Il. 1.4234, 23.2056; the land of the Pygmaioi, Il. 3.36; the meadow where the harpy Podarge conceived horses to the West Wind, Il. 16.1502; and the spot where Penelope wishes that the ‘tempests’ would carry her, Od. 20.6179). See further, Gordon (Reference Gordon2019) 1937. By comparison, some of the cosmic rivers/streams connected to Oceanus are found ‘under’ the earth: e.g., Styx (Hes. Theog. 787ff); Acheron/Acherusian Lake (Pl. Phd. 112e).

References

Albinus, L. (2000), The House of Hades: Studies in Ancient Greek Eschatology. Aarhus.Google Scholar
Ballabriga, A. (1986), Le soleil et le tartare: L'image mythique du monde en grèce archaïque. Paris.Google Scholar
Ballabriga, A. (1998), Les fictions d'Homère: L'invention mythologique et cosmographique dans l'Odysée. Paris.Google Scholar
Bilić, T. (2013), ‘Locations of Mythical Exile: Two Mythical Models Accounting for the Phenomenon of Diurnal Solar Movement’, Mnemosyne 66, 247–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bloch, R., (2006), ‘Iapetus’, in H. Cancik et al. (eds.), Brill's New Pauly at https://referenceworks.brillonline.com/entries/brill-s-new-pauly/*-e521170Google Scholar
Bowra, C. M. (1930), Tradition and Design in the Iliad. Oxford.Google Scholar
Bray, C. (2018), ‘Limits of Dread: ἐσχατιά, πɛῖραρ, and Dangerous Edge-Space in Homeric Formulae’, in Felton, D. (ed.), Landscapes of Dread in Classical Antiquity: Negative Emotion in Natural and Constructed Spaces. Abingdon, 3857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bremmer, J. N. (2008), Greek Religion and Culture, the Bible and the Ancient Near East. Leiden.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Budelmann, F. and Haubold, J. (2007), ‘Reception and Tradition’, in Hardwick, L. and Stray, C. (eds.), A Companion to Classical Receptions. Oxford, 1325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgess, J. S. (2016), ‘Localization of the Odyssey's Underworld’, CEA 53, 1537.Google Scholar
Burton, D. (2016), ‘Utopian Motifs in Early Greek Concepts of the Afterlife’, Antichthon 50, 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Camacho, P. F. (2015), ‘A Space without Ethnology: Study of the Ideological Treatment of the West in Greek and Roman Literature through the Sources about the Island of Gades’, AC 84, 6373.Google Scholar
Clark, S. R. L. (2017), ‘Classical Mediterranean Conceptions of the Afterlife’, in Nagasawa, Y. and Matheson, B. (eds.), The Palgrave Handbook of the Afterlife. London, 4157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clay, D. (1992), ‘The World of Hesiod’, Ramus 21, 131–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cousin, C. (2002), ‘La situation géographique et les abords de l'Hadès homérique’, Gaia 6, 2546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cousin, C. (2012), Le monde des morts: Espaces et paysages de l'au-delà dans l'imaginaire grec d'Homère à la fin du Ve siècle avant J.-C: étude littéraire et iconographique. Paris.Google Scholar
Currie, B. (2016), Homer's Allusive Art. Oxford.Google Scholar
de Jong, I. J. F. (2001), A Narratological Commentary on the Odyssey. Cambridge and New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Defouw, R. J. (2018). The Subtlety of Homer. Boulder, CO.Google Scholar
Edmunds, L. (2009), ‘A Hermeneutic Commentary on the Eschatological Passage in Pindar Olympian 2 (57–83)’, in Dill, U. and Walde, C. (eds.), Antike Mythen. Berlin, 662–77.Google Scholar
Endsjø, D. O. (1997), ‘Placing the Unplaceable: The Making of Apollonius’ Argonautic Geography’, GRBS 38, 373–85.Google Scholar
Evans, R. (2003), ‘Searching for Paradise: Landscape, Utopia, and Rome’, Arethusa 36, 285307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, R. (2008), Utopia Antiqua: Readings of the Golden Age and Decline at Rome. London.Google Scholar
Fowler, R. L. (2017), ‘Imaginary Itineraries in the Beyond’, in Hawes, G. (ed.), Myths on the Map: The Storied Landscapes of Ancient Greece. Oxford, 243–60.Google Scholar
Garland, R. (1981), ‘The Causation of Death in the Iliad: A Theological and Biological Investigation’, BICS 28, 4360.Google Scholar
Gazis, G. (2018), Homer and the Poetics of Hades. Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gazis, G. A. (2021a), ‘Beyond the Stream of the Ocean: Hades, the Aethiopians and Homeric Eschata’, in Marlow, H., Pollman, K. and van Noorden, H. (eds.), Eschatology in Antiquity: Forms and Functions. Abingdon and New York, 105–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gazis, G. A. (2021b), ‘What is your Lot?: Lyric Pessimism and Pindar's Afterlife’, in Gazis, G. A. and Hooper, A. (eds.), Aspects of Death and the Afterlife in Greek Literature. Liverpool, 6988.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gazis, G. A. (2021c), ‘Dying (?) in Pindar's Sicily: Olympian 2 and the Isle of the Blessed’, in Reid, H. L. and Lewis, V. M. (eds.), Pindar in Sicily. Sioux City, IA, 97118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gee, E. R. G. (2020), Mapping the Afterlife: from Homer to Dante. Oxford and New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilchrest, E. J. (2012), The Topography of Utopia: Revelation 21–22 in Light of Ancient Jewish and Greco-Roman Utopianism. PhD thesis. Baylor University.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gordon, J. A. (2017), ‘When Superman Smote Zeus: Analysing Violent Deicide in Popular Culture’, CRJ 9, 211–36.Google Scholar
Gordon, J. A. (2019), ‘Opening up the World below’: A New ‘Reading’ of Ancient Greek Eschatological Topography. Phd Thesis. University of Otago.Google Scholar
Hainsworth, J. B. (1993), The Iliad: A Commentary. Vol. 3 (Books 9–12). Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haller, B. S. (2007), Landscape Description in Homer's Odyssey. PhD thesis. University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
Hammond, R. (2012), Islands in the Sky: The Four-dimensional Journey of Odysseus Through Space and Time. Newcastle.Google Scholar
Harrell, S. E. (1991), ‘Apollo's Fraternal Threats: Language of Succession and Domination in the Homeric Hymn to Hermes’, GRBS 32, 307–29.Google Scholar
Hawes, G. (2017), ‘Of Myths and Maps’ in Hawes, G. (ed.), Myths on the Map: The Storied Landscapes of Ancient Greece. Oxford, 113.Google Scholar
Janko, R. (1992), The Iliad: A Commentary. Vol. 4 (Books 13–16). Cambridge.Google Scholar
Johnson, D. M. (1999), ‘Hesiod's Descriptions of Tartarus (Theogony 721-819)’, Phoenix 53, 828.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jouanna, D. (2015), Les Grecs aux enfers: d'Homère à Épicure. Paris.Google Scholar
Kirchhoff, A. (1879) Die homerische Odyssee. Berlin.Google Scholar
Kirk, G. S. (1985), The Iliad: A Commentary. Vol. 1 (Books 1–4). Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kirk, G. S. (1990), The Iliad: A Commentary. Vol. 2 (Books 5–8). Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kostuch, L. (2015), ‘Between Rivers and the Sea: The Hellenic Aquatic Divisions’, International Journal of Maritime History 27, 177–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Louden, B. (2013), ‘Iapetus and Japheth: Hesiod's Theogony, Iliad 15.18793, and Genesis 910’, ICS 38, 122.Google Scholar
Lye, S. (2016), The Hypertextual Underworld: Exploring the Underworld as an Intertextual Space in Ancient Greek Literature. PhD thesis. University of California.Google Scholar
Mackie, C. J. (2014), ‘Zeus and Mount Ida in Homer's Iliad’, Antichthon 48, 113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McInerney, J. and Sluiter, I. (2016), ‘General Introduction’, in McInerney, J. and Sluiter, I. (eds.), Valuing Landscape in Classical Antiquity: Natural Environment and Cultural Imagination. Leiden, 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McIntyre, J. S. (2009), Written into the Landscape: Latin Epic and the Landmarks of Literary Reception. PhD thesis. University of St. Andrews.Google Scholar
Most, G. W. (ed.) (2006), Hesiod. Theogony, Works and Days, Testimonia. Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Murray, A. T. and Wyatt, W. F. (eds.) (1999), Homer: Iliad. 2 vols. rev. edn. Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
Nagy, G. (1973), ‘Phaethon, Sappho's Phaon, and the White Rock of Leukas’, HSCPh 77, 13777Google Scholar
Nakassis, D. (2004), ‘Gemination at the Horizons: East and West in the Mythical Geography of Archaic Greek Epic’, TAPhA 134, 215–33.Google Scholar
Page, D. L. (1955), The Homeric Odyssey: The Mary Flexner Lectures Delivered at Bryn Mawr College, Pennsylvania. Westport, CT.Google Scholar
Purves, A. C. (2006), ‘Falling into Time in Homer's Iliad’, ClAnt 25, 179209.Google Scholar
Purves, A. C. (2010), Space and Time in Ancient Greek Narrative. New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Romm, J. S. (1992), The Edges of the Earth in Ancient Thought: Geography, Exploration, and Fiction. Princeton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snell, B. (ed.) (2004), Lexikon des frühgriechischen Epos. Band 3 (Μ-Π). Göttingen.Google Scholar
Sourvinou-Inwood, C. (1995). ‘Reading’ Greek Death: To the End of the Classical Period. Oxford.Google Scholar
Stanford, W. B. (1965), ‘The Ending of the Odyssey: An Ethical Approach’, Hermathena 100, 520.Google Scholar
Trépanier, S. (2017), ‘From Hades to the Stars: Empedocles on the Cosmic Habitats of Soul’, ClAnt 36, 130–82.Google Scholar
Tralau, J. (2018), ‘Hesiod, Ouranos, Kronos, and the Emasculation at the Beginning of Time’, CW 111, 459–84.Google Scholar
van der Valk, M. (1985), ‘On the God Cronus’, GRBS 26, 511.Google Scholar
Wender, D. (1978), The Last Scenes of the Odyssey. Leiden.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U. v. (1884), Homerische Untersuchungen. Berlin.Google Scholar
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, U. v. (1927), Die Heimkehr des Odysseus: neue homerische Untersuchungen. Berlin.Google Scholar
Wilson, C. H. (1996), Homer Iliad VIII and IX. Warminster.Google Scholar
Yasumura, N. (2011), Challenges to the Power of Zeus in Early Greek Poetry. London.Google Scholar
Zellner, H. (2008), ‘Argument in the New Sappho’, CB 84, 4755.Google Scholar