Hostname: page-component-686fd747b7-mrck6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-13T14:24:42.690Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Labor Migration and Climate Change Adaptation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  06 December 2021

JAMIE DRAPER*
Affiliation:
University of Oxford, United Kingdom
*
Jamie Draper, Postdoctoral Prize Research Fellow in Politics, Nuffield College, University of Oxford, United Kingdom, jamie.draper@nuffield.ox.ac.uk.
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Social scientific evidence suggests that labor migration can increase resilience to climate change. For that reason, some have recently advocated using labor migration policy as a tool for climate adaptation. This paper engages with the normative question of whether, and under what conditions, states may permissibly use labor migration policy as a tool for climate adaptation. I argue that states may use labor migration policy as a tool for climate adaptation and may even have a duty to do so, subject to two moral constraints. First, states must also provide acceptable alternative options for adaptation so that the vulnerable are not forced to sacrifice their morally important interests in being able to remain where they are. Second, states may not impose restrictive terms on labor migrants to make accepting greater numbers less costly for themselves because doing so unfairly shifts the costs of adaptation onto the most vulnerable.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the American Political Science Association

In rural Ethiopia, smallholding farmers are battling with droughts of increasing frequency and intensity. Ethiopian smallholders have developed a range of methods for managing drought risks, such as diversifying crops and participating in the collective risk-sharing practice of iddir (Aredo Reference Aredo2010; Porter Reference Porter2012). The adverse impacts of climate change, however, are stretching the capacity of these risk-management strategies. Changes in temperature and precipitation associated with climate change have significantly detrimental effects on crop yields in Ethiopia (Deressa and Hassan Reference Deressa and Hassan2009). The evidence suggests that existing strategies of risk-management are insufficient in the face of newer, “extreme” rainfall shortages (Porter Reference Porter2012, 1216).

One alternative to these traditional risk-management strategies is labor migration. When members of a household engage in labor migration, they can generate an additional, stable stream of income through remittances. In Ethiopia, the greater the risk of food insecurity, the more likely it is that community members will migrate abroad to assist relatives (Ezra and Kiros Reference Ezra and Kiros2001). The case of Amina, a smallholder in South Wollo, is illustrative:

Amina is 60 years of age and owns two oxen, nine other cattle, and 15 shoats … She and her husband (who died around 1996) lost most of their cattle in the 1983–84 drought but were able to rebuild by the late 1980s. During the 1983–84 drought she sent two children (sons) to neighbouring Djibouti to work and one of them still sends cash remittances. Amina depends heavily on this source of cash, to buy food and livestock … In the post-drought period of 2000 to 2003 she was able to increase herds from 13 to 15 cattle and three to 23 sheep, and actually was better off in 2003 than in 1997. (Little et al. Reference Little, Stone, Tewodaj Mogues and Negatu2006, 217)

Here, labor migration enabled Amina’s household to diversify its sources of income and invest in productive assets.

This pattern is not unique to the case of Ethiopia. Around the world, those who rely on their environment for their livelihoods or subsistence face growing threats from the impacts of climate change. Climate change impacts are detrimental to livelihoods, lead to food insecurity, exacerbate inequalities, worsen existing poverty, and trigger new poverty traps (IPCC Reference Field, Barros, Dokken, Mach, Mastrandrea, Bilir and Chatterjee2014, 796–7). A key part of the project of tackling climate change is facilitating adaptation so that such harmful outcomes can be avoided.

Recently, some academics, policy makers, and international institutions have suggested that international labor migration should be promoted as a strategy of adaptation to climate change (Asia Development Bank 2012; Black, Adger, et al. Reference Black, Adger, Arnell, Dercon, Geddes and Thomas2011; de Moor Reference de Moor2011; Webber and Barnett Reference Webber and Barnett2010). As the case of Amina—and a growing body of social scientific evidence—shows, labor migration can make it possible for some people living in precarious environments threatened by climate change to survive, and perhaps even to thrive. Advocates of using labor migration policy as a tool for climate change adaptation argue that if high-income states were to open their borders to more labor migrants from regions affected by climate change, then the most vulnerable would be better-placed to protect themselves against its worst outcomes.

This paper examines the prospects and pitfalls of using labor migration policy as a tool for climate change adaptation. Paul Baer (Reference Baer, Neil Adger, Paavola, Huq and Mace2006, 131) distinguishes two central questions about justice in climate change adaptation: “what actions should be taken to prevent or reduce harm to be caused by anthropogenic climate change, and who should carry the costs of those actions?” This paper engages with both of these questions through an analysis of the normative question of whether, and under what conditions, states may permissibly use labor migration policy as an instrument of climate change adaptation.

I argue that states may permissibly use labor migration policy as a tool for climate change adaptation and that they may even have a duty to do so in some contexts, but that they are subject to two important moral constraints. The first constraint relates to the voluntariness of labor migration. If states are to use labor migration as a tool for climate adaptation, then they must also provide acceptable alternative options for adaptation that enable those who do not wish to migrate to adapt where they are. This is so that those vulnerable to climate impacts are not forced to migrate and thereby to sacrifice their morally significant interests in being able to remain where they are. The second constraint relates to the fairness of labor migration. Receiving states may not impose restrictive terms on would-be migrants to make accepting greater numbers of labor migrants less costly for themselves. This is because in the context of climate change adaptation, offering such terms represents an unfair attempt to shift the costs of adaptation onto the most vulnerable.

In making these arguments, the paper brings together two literatures in political theory, the climate justice literature and the migration justice literature, in a new way.Footnote 1 The paper draws on existing arguments in the migration justice literature about immigration and poverty but shows that the context of climate change alters the moral landscape of such debates—in particular, by making it possible to reach fairly strong conclusions on the basis of only fairly minimal normative commitments. The paper also draws on arguments about fairness in distributing the costs of tackling climate change but shows that such arguments have further reach than is sometimes assumed—in particular, they are relevant not only for disagreements about how entitlements to emit should be distributed but can also be “integrated” into debates in other domains, such as migration policy (Caney Reference Caney2012). The paper thus not only confronts an important practical problem but also sheds theoretical light on the ways in which different issues in global justice relate to each other.

The form of migration that I focus on here—international labor migration—is only one part of the broader phenomenon of climate-related migration and displacement. The evidence suggests that most migration relating to climate change will take place within state borders (Piguet, Pécoud, and de Guchteneire Reference Piguet, Pécoud and de Guchteneire2011). Researchers have also distinguished a number of different ways in which climate change may drive migration and displacement, which include extreme weather events that cause reactive displacement; factors such as sea level rise that gradually make villages, cities, and perhaps even entire small island states uninhabitable; and pressures on resource and food security that amplify existing sources of political instability and conflict (Kälin Reference Kälin and McAdam2010). Each of these different forms of migration and displacement are likely to raise different moral considerations from those that arise in relation to international labor migration.

The reason I focus on international labor migration here is twofold. First, the extent of other forms of climate-related migration and displacement will depend not only on the nature, severity, and scale of climate change impacts that unfold over time but also on the opportunities for international migration that are made available in the first place. Fewer opportunities for international labor migration may mean that more of those affected engage in internal migration instead, or a lower adaptive capacity may lead to more displacement resulting from climate change. Therefore, it is important to know what opportunities should be made available in the first place. Second, international labor migration raises important questions about the duties of states in the international order and merits critical attention even if it ultimately represents only a small share of all climate-related movement.

I also make two background assumptions in the arguments that I develop. First, I assume what Joseph Carens (Reference Carens2013, 11) calls the “conventional view” on immigration: that “states are morally free to exercise considerable discretionary control over the admission and exclusion of immigrants.” This right is not unlimited—states may be required to admit some persons, such as refugees—but until such limitations are established, I assume that states have a discretionary right to exclude would-be immigrants. Second, I assume that states have duties to facilitate adaptation to climate change as part of a collective international project of tackling climate change. States’ primary duties are to prevent adverse climate change impacts from occurring by engaging in mitigation—and the more mitigation we undertake, the less adaptation will be required—but some adverse climate change impacts are already occurring, and some are locked in due to the inertia of the climate system. This means that adaptation will be part of any plausible attempt to tackle climate change (Caney Reference Caney2010, 204).

I adopt these assumptions because it is against the background of these assumptions that moral questions concerning the justifiability of labor migration policy as an instrument of climate change adaptation arise. If states were morally required to adopt an open-borders policy or had no duties to facilitate adaptation to climate change, then whether or not they may permissibly discharge their duties to facilitate adaptation to climate change by expanding opportunities for labor migration would be a moot point. These assumptions also reflect widely shared normative commitments in the contemporary international order—or at least normative commitments that states often profess. Adopting these background assumptions thus helps us to navigate the normative questions about climate change and labor migration that confront us in the here-and-now.

First, I set out the proposal for using labor migration policy as a tool for adaptation and the social scientific evidence that underpins that proposal. Then, I argue that states may discharge their duties to facilitate adaptation by expanding opportunities for labor migration, and they may even have a duty to do so, but that they must also provide acceptable alternative options for adaptation in situ. Finally, I argue that states may not offer restrictive terms to labor migrants when labor migration is used as a tool for climate adaptation.

Labor Migration Policy as a Tool for Climate Change Adaptation

Climate change adaptation, in the most generic sense of the term, is simply “the process of adjustment to actual or expected climate and its effects” (IPCC Reference Field, Barros, Dokken, Mach, Mastrandrea, Bilir and Chatterjee2014, 5). This could cover a broad range of actions such as the construction of levees and sea walls, the subsidization of flood insurance, the development of early warning systems for typhoons, and so on. But one common strategy of climate change adaptation is to make those who face those effects more resilient—that is, better able to protect themselves against the harms associated with climate impacts (see Folke Reference Folke2006).

We know that differences in vulnerability to climate harms are widely attributable to socioeconomic status and that those in poverty are especially at risk of harmful outcomes (IPCC Reference Field, Barros, Dokken, Mach, Mastrandrea, Bilir and Chatterjee2014, 6–8). Therefore, one way to make people more resilient is to make them better off. Those who are better off are often able to leverage the resources that they have available to them to avoid the harms of climate impacts—for example, by using capital to invest in irrigation systems that make them less dependent on particular patterns of rainfall. Indeed, one of the reasons why poverty and disadvantage are so troubling is that they inhibit our ability to enjoy secure “functionings” under conditions of risk and insecurity (Sen Reference Sen1999, 87–110; Wolff and De-Shalit Reference Wolff and De-Shalit2007, 63–73). This link between poverty and vulnerability helps to explain why climate adaptation goals often overlap with broader development and poverty eradication goals (Ayers and Dodman Reference Ayers and Dodman2010; Schelling Reference Schelling1992).

We have clear evidence that labor migration from low- to high-income states is effective in reducing poverty (Oberman Reference Oberman2015). At the household level, labor migration can work as a strategy for increasing incomes and spreading risk. Those who move from a low- to a high-income state can increase their own income, and the remittances they send to family members can make them better off, free up resources for investment in productive assets, and provide a stable income stream (Massey et al. Reference Massey, Arango, Hugo, Kouaouci, Pellegrino and Taylor1993; Stark Reference Stark1991; Stark and Bloom Reference Stark and Bloom1985). Remittances may also indirectly benefit nonmigrant households—for example, by stimulating local economic activity (Taylor Reference Taylor1999). Temporary and “circular” forms of labor migration are often particularly effective in promoting poverty reduction and development, partly because migrants who plan on returning tend to remit a higher proportion of their income (Dustmann and Mestres Reference Dustmann and Mestres2010).Footnote 2

Of course, labor migration is not a silver bullet for poverty reduction and development, and it does raise some important concerns. Some concerns, such as concerns that remittances are largely spent on conspicuous consumption rather than development, are often overstated (De Haas Reference de Haas2005, 1274–5; Oberman Reference Oberman2015, 242–3). But one important concern is that the emigration of those with highly valued skills or who provide important care services may create a “brain drain” (Docquier and Rapoport Reference Docquier and Rapoport2012) or “care drain” (Isaksen, Devi, and Hochschild Reference Isaksen, Devi and Hochschild2008) among those who stay behind. This is a real concern, especially in certain sectors and contexts, but as a general phenomenon it is less widespread than is often assumed (de Haas Reference de Haas2005, 1272–3). Skilled emigration is also often accompanied by a “brain gain” (Stark, Helmenstein, and Prskawetz Reference Stark, Helmenstein and Prskawetz1997), where remittances enable investments in education or where returning migrants share knowledge. There is also a range of policies—such as raising domestic salaries for skilled workers, encouraging diasporic networks, and investing in the provision of institutional care services—that can limit the costs of brain and care drain without sacrificing the benefits of migration (Gheaus Reference Gheaus2013, 15–20; Kapur and McHale Reference Kapur and McHale2005).

These results give us good reason to believe that labor migration can function as a mechanism of climate change adaptation (Bardsley and Hugo Reference Bardsley and Hugo2010; Gemenne and Blocher Reference Gemenne and Blocher2017; Tacoli Reference Tacoli2009). Those who are vulnerable to climate impacts are often vulnerable because of their poverty and disadvantage, so we can expect that if labor migration helps to alleviate poverty and disadvantage, then it will also help to make people more resilient to climate impacts. The direct relationship between labor migration and resilience to climate impacts has been studied less extensively than the relationship between migration and development, but studies in Ethiopia (Gray and Mueller Reference Gray and Mueller2012), Vietnam (Adger et al. Reference Adger, Kelly, Winkels, Huy and Locke2002), Mexico (Hunter, Murray, and Riosmena Reference Hunter, Murray and Riosmena2013), the Philippines (Yang and Choi Reference Yang and Choi2007), across South Asia (Maharjan et al. Reference Maharjan, de Campos, Singh, Das, Srinivas, Bhuiyan and Ishaq2020), and in cross-national contexts (Warner and Afifi Reference Warner and Afifi2014) have all demonstrated that labor migration can have this adaptive function, at least in some circumstances. These results are not unambiguous, but overall, they lend support to the idea that labor migration can work as a strategy of adaptation to climate change. Researchers working on the climate-migration nexus increasingly argue that migration is a form of climate adaptation, precisely because it can make those vulnerable to climate change impacts more resilient (Black, Bennett, et al. Reference Black, Stephen, Thomas and Beddington2011; McLeman and Smit Reference McLeman and Smit2006).

As a result of this body of social scientific evidence, some have argued that high-income states should expand opportunities for labor migration in order to promote adaptation to climate change. In a report for the World Bank, Michael Webber and Jon Barnett (Reference Webber and Barnett2010, 32) have argued that developed states should enable the adaptive function of labor migration by reducing barriers to entry, recruiting from among those vulnerable, reducing the transaction costs of remittances, and providing housing and employment assistance to labor migrants. Similarly, the Asia Development Bank (2012, 72–3) stresses that “international migration can play a key role in fostering the resilience of households and communities.” They recommend that governments negotiate regional or bilateral freedom of movement agreements and expand opportunities for both permanent and temporary labor migration. In a report for the UK government, Richard Black, Adger, et al. (Reference Black, Adger, Arnell, Dercon, Geddes and Thomas2011, 175–6, 183–5) have recommended that circular migration schemes between low- and high-income countries be expanded and that labor migration policies support those most at risk of being “trapped” in place due to environmental changes and poverty.

Under all of these proposals, high-income states would open their borders to greater numbers of those most vulnerable to climate change impacts in order to promote the resilience of their households and communities. We can expect that individuals who take up opportunities for labor migration would remit a portion of their increased income to their families and communities, enabling them to better protect themselves from the adverse consequences of climate change—though no labor migrant would be obliged to do so. The most defensible versions of the proposal will also involve high-income states adopting more active policies—such as encouraging recruitment from climate-vulnerable areas, financing skills training programs, providing housing and employment assistance to labor migrants, paying for travel costs, and capping fees on remittance transfers—to promote the adaptive function of labor migration. They will also require receiving states to finance policies that limit the effect of brain or care drain where that is a concern, so that significant costs are not imposed on stayee communities.Footnote 3 Different configurations of policies will likely be appropriate in different contexts, depending on (among other things) the different dynamics of labor markets in receiving states and communities affected by climate change and the extant policy frameworks that regulate labor migration. And different configurations will also be more or less demanding for the receiving state, depending on the costs that they impose. But in general, these more demanding policy packages promise to better fulfill states’ duties to facilitate adaptation to climate change.

In order to serve the purpose of facilitating adaptation to climate change, labor migration policies would also need to be targeted toward communities that are vulnerable to climate change impacts and stand to benefit from labor migration. The empirical evidence suggests that climate change impacts are often intertwined with preexisting social, economic, demographic, environmental, and political drivers of migration in complex ways, which means that it is difficult to identify particular individuals whose migration can be attributed to climate change (Black, Kniveton, and Schmidt-Verkerk Reference Black, Kniveton and Schmidt-Verkerk2011; McLeman and Hunter Reference McLeman and Hunter2010). This means that it would be unwise to make eligibility for labor migration programs conditional on individuals proving that they need to move because of climate change, as such a requirement would be effectively impossible to meet. A more promising approach would be to identify and target particular geographical and sectoral “hotspots” for climate pressures that could be alleviated through labor migration (De Sherbinin Reference de Sherbinin2014). Such an approach may prove to be overinclusive in some cases, but labor migration has three important advantages that should negate any concerns about overinclusivity.

First is that labor migration is likely to be a particularly effective tool for adaptation. The resources that labor migration can generate are significant in scale—the World Bank estimates that remittance flows are three times higher than official development assistance (World Bank 2016, 17)—and translate into significant reductions in poverty (Adams and Page Reference Adams and Page2005). If those benefits travel to the context of adaptation—as we have good reason to expect them to, given the similar causal mechanisms at work—then they are likely to be similarly significant (Gemenne and Blocher Reference Gemenne and Blocher2017, 342–3). Labor migration may also be less likely to be maladaptive than other interventions. Top-down adaptation interventions are often maladaptive because of phenomena such as elite capture and inequitable participation in planning (Eriksen et al. Reference Eriksen, Schipper, Scoville-Simonds, Vincent, Adam, Brooks and Harding2021). Labor migration decisions taken at the household level are a form of bottom-up “autonomous adaptation,” which means that they may be less liable to becoming maladaptive in this way (Fankhauser, Smith, and Tol Reference Fankhauser, Smith and Richard1999).

Second is that labor migration is likely to be a particularly cheap strategy of adaptation. It costs little to open borders to those vulnerable to climate impacts, and even the more demanding elements of the proposal are likely to be relatively low in cost compared with other adaptation measures such as climate-proofing infrastructure (Narain, Margulis, and Essam Reference Narain, Margulis and Essam2011, 1009). In fact, the costs may even prove to be negative because states often derive benefits from opening their borders to labor migrants, who may fill skill shortages in the host state’s labor market or sustain an ageing population (Asia Development Bank 2012, 55; Black, Adger, et al. Reference Black, Adger, Arnell, Dercon, Geddes and Thomas2011, 183–4). Thus, proponents of labor migration often describe it as a “win-win” or “triple-win” strategy, given that it will often benefit migrants, sending states, and receiving states (Black, Adger, et al. Reference Black, Adger, Arnell, Dercon, Geddes and Thomas2011, 183; de Moor Reference de Moor2011, 13–5).Footnote 4

Third is that labor migration is likely to be a “no-regrets” form of climate adaptation (Heltberg, Sigel, and Jorgensen Reference Heltberg, Siegel and Jorgensen2009). As we have seen, labor migration from low- to high-income states can help to achieve other morally important goals, such as development and poverty alleviation. Of course, a labor migration policy that is tailored toward climate change adaptation may look quite different from a labor migration policy that is tailored toward poverty alleviation or development, given the different goals of such policies and the moral constraints that arise in the context of climate change adaptation. But this feature of labor migration means that even if it is overinclusive or proves to be ineffective in reducing vulnerability to climate change in some contexts, it is nonetheless likely to yield significant benefits in these other domains.

The Place of Labor Migration in Climate Change Adaptation

If labor migration policy can function as a tool for adaptation, as the evidence appears to suggest, then it is important to know what role it should play within the project of adaptation to climate change. In answering this question, it is instructive to turn to an analogous debate about the role of labor migration policy in the project of tackling global poverty. This debate provides a useful entry point for our analysis, but as we will see, the context of climate change alters its moral terrain.

Political theorists tend to agree that there is a duty to alleviate global poverty, though many disagree about the grounds, character, and extent of that duty. In debates about the relevance of this duty for immigration policy, Kieran Oberman (Reference Oberman2011; Reference Oberman2015) has argued that states may not permissibly use immigration policy as a means of addressing global poverty because doing so would involve violating a “right to stay” held by those who would need to migrate in order to alleviate their (or their household’s) poverty. As Oberman (Reference Oberman2011, 258–60) points out, we often have a powerful interest in remaining where we are, which is underpinned by at least three values: freedom of movement (including the freedom not to move), cultural membership, and the attachments that we have to the territory in which we live. These values capture the importance of our ties to the people and places that are significant in our lives. If we use immigration policy to address poverty, then we force people to migrate in order to alleviate their poverty and thereby to sacrifice these morally important interests, which amounts to a violation of their right to stay.

If Oberman is right, then something similar could be said of using labor migration policy as a tool for climate change adaptation: using labor migration policy as a tool for climate change adaptation is impermissible because it violates the rights to stay held by those vulnerable to climate impacts. Here, however, I argue that this conclusion does not follow from a closer examination of Oberman’s argument. Oberman’s argument can be upheld in the context of climate adaptation. But properly understood, it does not rule out using labor migration policy as a tool for climate adaptation.

In its original context, Oberman’s argument relies on a claim that is likely to be controversial: that high-income states discharging their duty to alleviate poverty abroad are constrained by the right to stay. To say that this claim is likely to be controversial is not to say that it is incorrect—I remain agnostic on that point here—but it is nonetheless important to draw out this feature of Oberman’s argument because it bears on the prospects for the success of his argument when applied to the context of climate change adaptation. Although Oberman’s argument faces an important challenge in its original context, that challenge does not arise within the context of climate change adaptation, which means that it can be upheld.

The basic interests that Oberman argues underlie the right to stay—freedom of movement, cultural membership, and territorial attachment—clearly have significant moral weight. In my view, Oberman is right to suggest—as theorists of territorial rights have recently pointed out—that we have powerful and nonsubstitutable interests in being able to remain in the places where we form and pursue our life plans (Draper Reference Draper2021; Moore Reference Moore2015, 36–46; Stilz Reference Stilz2019, 33–59). The important question for our purposes, however, concerns what duties those interests impose on would-be admitting states. For Oberman, the right to stay is a human right, which is violated when people have no reasonable alternative apart from migrating (Oberman Reference Oberman2011, 258; Reference Oberman2015, 246–7). He takes this to mean that all states, including those contemplating how to discharge their duties to the global poor, have positive duties to ensure that the right to stay is fulfilled (Oberman Reference Oberman2015, 260–2).

For some political theorists, however, Oberman’s claim that these interests ground a human right will appear too strong, at least if a “human right to stay” means that outsiders are under a positive duty to enable those in poverty to stay where they are rather than a mere negative duty not to expel or remove them. On at least some views, there is an important “division of labor” between states when it comes to human rights protection (Beitz Reference Beitz2009, 106–17). In the first instance, states are responsible for protecting and fulfilling the human rights of their own members. The failure of a state to protect and fulfil the rights of its members is a matter of “international concern” that may give rise to pro tanto duties on the part of the international community to act—for example by assisting states that lack capacity (Beitz Reference Beitz2009, 109). But other states in the international order are not themselves required to protect and fulfil the rights of citizens abroad—only to respect those rights by not violating negative duties that stem from them (Blake Reference Blake2020, 70–1). If we adopt this view, then states that offer those in poverty an opportunity to migrate in order to alleviate their poverty do not violate the right to stay. Those in poverty are already in a situation where they do not have any reasonable options, after all. States that offer those in poverty the opportunity to migrate do not, in so doing, create or exacerbate the conditions of poverty facing the would-be migrant. So, they do not abrogate a negative duty that stems from the right to stay by offering opportunities to migrate.

Still, we might think that if states have a duty of justice to alleviate poverty, they must discharge that duty in ways that pay due regard to the interests of the global poor. If states are to discharge their duties of justice to the global poor, they should do so in ways that do not require the global poor to sacrifice some morally important interests, such as their interests in staying where they are. After all, duties of justice are duties to give their beneficiaries something that they are owed by right, not duties that can be made conditional on their beneficiaries sacrificing other morally important interests. Even if the right to stay is not a human right, or even if a human right to stay does not entail that states have positive duties to enable the global poor to stay where they are, the fact that poverty alleviation is a duty of justice means that states must discharge that duty in a way that does not require the global poor to sacrifice morally important interests.

This response explains why rich states may not require the global poor to sacrifice their interests in staying where they are, but it leaves Oberman’s argument open to an important challenge. This challenge comes from those who claim that our duties to the global poor are only duties of justice, rather than duties of charity, when we are responsible for their plight (Miller Reference Miller2007, 247–9; Valentini Reference Valentini2013). The distinction between duties of justice and duties of charity is itself a matter of disagreement, but one popular gloss is that duties of charity are imperfect duties, meaning that we have some discretion about when and how they are to be performed, and they do not provide grounds for complaint when they are not discharged (Buchanan Reference Buchanan1987). If we take this view, then, at least where they are not responsible for it, rich states should enjoy some discretion about how to discharge their duties to alleviate global poverty. The poor do not have grounds for complaint if rich states only offer them opportunities to alleviate their poverty through migration, as their poverty alleviation is not something that is owed to them by rich states as a matter of justice.

If these two claims—first, that states do not violate the human right to stay by offering opportunities for migration, and second, that states are entitled to exercise discretion about how and when to discharge their duties to the global poor—are correct, then states may well be morally permitted to choose to address global poverty through immigration policy (and only through immigration policy). That being said, it remains an open question whether Oberman’s argument ultimately succeeds or fails because there are important counterarguments available to him. For instance, he might argue that using immigration policy to tackle global poverty goes beyond the limits of the discretion that imperfect duties afford us. Or he might contest the claim that we only have duties of justice to the global poor when we are responsible for their plight. Or he might argue that rich states are responsible for global poverty, at least in many cases—perhaps because of the history of colonial exploitation that has structured development processes (see Acemoglu, Johnson, and Robinson Reference Acemoglu, Johnson and Robinson2001) or the role of rich states as “rule-makers” in a global economic order that keeps some states chronically underdeveloped (Pogge Reference Pogge2002).Footnote 5 The important point here is not the ultimate success of Oberman’s argument but rather that it is open to contestation on the grounds that the would-be admitting states are not responsible for the conditions of poverty that face the global poor.

This is important because in the case of climate adaptation, it is not plausible to maintain that the would-be admitting states do not bear responsibility. It is a basic feature of adaptation that it only arises as a need in response to the threats and risks associated with climate change, which are produced collectively by the actions of high-emitters (Paavola and Adger Reference Jouni and Adger2006). Unlike in the case of poverty, there is no real empirical debate to be had about whether the causes of the need for adaptation are endogenous or exogenous. Those most vulnerable to climate change are, by and large, those least responsible for it—Stephen Gardiner (Reference Gardiner2011, 31) calls this the fact of “skewed vulnerabilities”—which means that those who need to adapt to climate change are responding to conditions imposed upon them by others. The upshot of this is that the moral duty to facilitate adaptation to climate change is a duty of justice, not a duty of charity, even on those views that maintain that we only have duties of justice when we are responsible for the plight of those who need our assistance. Whatever its prospects for success in the case of poverty, when it is applied to the case of climate change adaptation, Oberman’s argument can be upheld. In the context of climate change, then, this fairly strong conclusion can be reached on the basis of only fairly minimal commitments about the requirements of global justice.

To get a full sense of what this implies for the proposal to promote labor migration as a strategy of climate change adaptation, however, we need to distinguish between a strong and a weak interpretation of Oberman’s argument. At some points, Oberman makes the strong claim that it is impermissible for states to use immigration policy as a tool for poverty alleviation at all, at least where there are possible alternatives. He writes, for example, that “immigration should not be used to address poverty when there are alternatives available” (Oberman Reference Oberman2015, 248). At other points, however, he makes the weaker claim that it is impermissible for states to structure the options available to the global poor such that they have no reasonable poverty-alleviating alternatives to migration. For example, he claims that “a migration-based approach to global poverty that does not seek to assist desperately poor people in their home state … violates the human right to stay” (Oberman Reference Oberman2011, 260, emphasis added) and that “when rich states rely on migration to address poverty, instead of searching for alternatives” (Oberman Reference Oberman2015, 247, emphasis added) they violate the right to stay.

These claims are importantly different, and only the weaker claim follows from Oberman’s argument. The right to stay imposes constraints on the behavior of would-be receiving states, but it does not always rule out using immigration policy to tackle global poverty. This is because of the sense in which the poor are forced to migrate. They are forced to migrate not in the sense that they are subject to direct threats of coercion but rather in the sense that they lack acceptable alternatives to migration (Oberman Reference Oberman2011, 260). Those who are put in a position where they must migrate in order to alleviate their poverty have no effective choice but to do so. Now, strictly speaking, it is possible for a would-be migrant to choose to migrate voluntarily even if they lack acceptable alternatives if the reason that they choose to migrate is not because they lack acceptable alternatives (Olsaretti Reference Olsaretti2004, 138–9). But unless would-be migrants have acceptable alternative options, we cannot know whether or not they would have otherwise chosen to migrate. The criterion that there should be acceptable alternatives thus provides an important “political” and publicly verifiable standard for judgements about when migration is forced (Ottonelli and Torresi Reference Ottonelli and Torresi2013, 792–801).

The upshot of this is that Oberman’s argument does not rule out using labor migration policy as a tool for climate adaptation. It only means that states must also provide acceptable alternative options such that the vulnerable are not forced to migrate to successfully adapt. So long as states provide acceptable alternative options that enable the vulnerable to stay where they are if they so choose, they can permissibly also offer opportunities to migrate. In other words, the right to stay only rules out making adaptation conditional on taking up opportunities for labor migration. It is violated when states structure the options available to the vulnerable such that they do not have acceptable alternatives to migration that enable them to adapt where they are. But this does not rule out using labor migration policy as one tool among many in the project of climate adaptation. This is important because some of those affected may actually prefer to take up opportunities for labor migration rather than to stay where they are. For many would-be migrants, what Ottonelli and Torresi (Reference Valeria and Torresi2012) call a “migration project” is a central part of a broader life plan. Adopting labor migration policies that seek to address vulnerability to climate change, among other alternatives, could be one way of enabling such projects.

Of course, exactly when the alternatives are “acceptable” is difficult to establish. For one thing, there are a variety of different adaptation interventions that may be relevant to contexts in which labor migration is a viable option—such as encouraging crop diversification, expanding employment opportunities, putting in place social safety nets, expanding access to credit, and even direct cash transfers—and the heterogeneity of climate impacts and the circumstances of vulnerable communities make it difficult to determine in the abstract which options are appropriate. For another, different theories of justice in adaptation will set different normative standards for adaptation policy: for example, they will tell us whether adaptation must protect certain capabilities, meet certain standards of procedural justice, make those vulnerable to climate impacts as well-off as they would have been in the absence of climate change, and so on (see Heyward Reference Heyward, Gardiner and Thompson2017).

Even in the absence of such a theory, however, we can establish a rough critical standard for judgements about when alternatives are acceptable. Alternative adaptation options need not be fully just—only sufficiently just—for us to treat labor migration decisions as voluntary decisions and thus for using labor migration policy as a tool for adaptation to be permissible. A standard of full justice is far too demanding as a general standard for assessing the voluntariness of decisions; such a standard would render all decisions made against a background of injustice involuntary, which—if we believe that contemporary societies involve widespread injustices—would effectively render all decisions involuntary (Ottonelli and Torresi Reference Ottonelli and Torresi2013, 798–800). This is implication is highly implausible and should lead us to adopt a more minimal standard for making judgements of voluntariness. Ottonelli and Torresi (Reference Ottonelli and Torresi2013, 800) and Serena Olsaretti (Reference Olsaretti2004, 140) both suggest a standard of basic needs. In my view, we should understand “basic needs” fairly capaciously here so as to count as involuntary cases where decisions are made to avoid having to sacrifice morally important interests—interests such as preserving family and community ties, cultural membership, and so on—rather than merely survival needs.Footnote 6 This standard captures the sense in which those who are put in a position where they must choose between sacrificing such morally important interests and foregoing successful adaptation to climate change are “forced” to migrate. On this standard, states must ensure that there is some alternative option available to would-be migrants that does not require them to sacrifice any basic needs, understood in these broad terms.Footnote 7

Where does this leave us with respect to the place of labor migration policy in climate change adaptation? Labor migration policy, we know, can be an effective tool for adaptation. But Oberman’s argument shows that states cannot permissibly use only labor migration policy to facilitate adaptation to climate change. Doing so would fail to pay due regard to the morally important interests that those vulnerable to climate change have in remaining in place. This does not rule out using labor migration as a tool for climate change adaptation—but it means that if labor migration is to be used as a tool for climate change adaptation, then those vulnerable to climate change must be offered alternative opportunities for adaptation in situ that do not require them to sacrifice morally basic interests.

Beyond this, however, I also want to make a more tentative, positive claim: that high-income states are not only permitted to use labor migration policy as a tool for climate change adaptation (so long as they also provide in situ alternatives) but further that they may have a duty to do so, at least in some circumstances. The justification for this claim stems from the fact that, as we have seen, labor migration may be a particularly cheap and effective form of adaptation to climate change.

If we assume that the overall budget for adaptation is limited, then it seems reasonable to suggest that adaptation interventions should be designed to be cost-effective, in the sense that the overall package of adaptation interventions that we adopt should be targeted toward the maximal fulfilment of our duties of justice to facilitate adaptation. Given that labor migration appears to be a particularly cheap and effective form of adaptation to climate change, we can expect that it will take up relatively little of any overall budget for adaptation interventions while providing fairly significant adaptive benefits. The more opportunities for labor migration are taken up, the less need there will be for other more expensive and less effective forms of climate adaptation. Thus, in the context of a scarcity of adaptation finance, high-income states have a pro tanto duty to offer opportunities for labor migration as a form of adaptation to climate change. They have this duty because offering opportunities for labor migration will take up relatively little of the overall budget, so it will enable states to discharge more fully their more general duties to facilitate adaptation to climate change.Footnote 8

It should be stressed, however, that the claim that states have a duty to use labor migration policy as a tool for climate adaptation claim depends on three conditions. First, it depends on the claim that labor migration is cost effective holding true. Given what we know about the way in which labor migration reduces poverty, the links between poverty alleviation and resilience to climate change, and the costs and pathologies of other forms of adaptation, we do have good reason to believe that labor migration will be cost effective. But ultimately, research on the direct relationship between labor migration and climate adaptation is still in its infancy, and further research will be needed to determine how confidently we can make this claim.

Second, it depends on the claim that other moral values do not override considerations of cost effectiveness. Cost effectiveness is an important consideration when it comes to selecting policies, but other moral values will also bear on which policies are acceptable. For example, we ought to ensure that policies targeted at ameliorating the condition of those affected by climate impacts do not express disrespect or compromise their standing as equals (Wolff Reference Wolff1998). It is for this reason that the duty to promote labor migration is only a pro tanto duty.

Finally, the third condition is that there is a scarcity of adaptation finance. The overall costs of adaptation are difficult to measure, but one review suggests that they are likely to be somewhere between $25 billion and $100 billion per year, with some estimates being even less optimistic (Fankhauser Reference Fankhauser2010; Narain, Margulis, and Essam Reference Narain, Margulis and Essam2011). Although significant pledges for adaptation finance have been made—the international community has pledged $100 billion annually through the Green Climate Fund—actual contributions have fallen significantly short. Only around $10 billion has been contributed in total since the fund’s inception in 2010 (Callies and Moellendorf Reference Callies and Moellendorf2021, 132), meaning there is a significant scarcity of adaptation finance.Footnote 9

Of course, the scarcity of the overall budget for adaptation is not itself a fixed constraint but is rather an artifact result of the unwillingness of high-income states to contribute enough to adaptation finance. Regardless of their attitude toward using labor migration as a tool for climate change adaptation, states clearly have a duty to increase their contributions to adaptation funding such that they are able to discharge their duties of justice to those vulnerable to climate change impacts. But if states were willing to radically increase their contributions such that there was no longer a scarcity of adaptation finance at all, then perhaps it would be permissible for them to ignore considerations of cost effectiveness and exercise discretion about whether or not to offer opportunities for labor migration as a form of adaptation (at least on the assumption that states have a more general discretionary right to exclude).

If this is correct, then the duty that high-income states have is a disjunctive duty: they have a duty either to offer opportunities for labor migration as a form of adaptation (alongside in situ alternatives), borne of considerations of cost effectiveness that bind them within a context of scarcity, or to increase the overall budget for adaptation to a degree that they no longer need be constrained by considerations of cost effectiveness. But until and unless states do radically increase their contributions, they have at least a pro tanto duty to offer opportunities for labor migration as a form of climate change adaptation (alongside in situ alternatives).

Fair Terms for Labor Migration as Climate Change Adaptation

If the foregoing arguments are correct, then labor migration policy may play an important role in adaptation to climate change. And as we have seen, labor migration is also likely to be attractive from the point of view of states that seek to fill labor shortages in key sectors or sustain an ageing population. But part of the reason that labor migration is attractive to receiving states is that they can impose restrictive terms on labor migrants, which ensure that they derive the benefits of labor migration without incurring associated costs. Receiving states may, for example, restrict migrant workers’ labor rights such that they are unable to join trade unions or change employer; restrict access to social rights such as social security, pensions, and public health care; and restrict access to family reunification (Lenard and Straehle Reference Lenard and Straehle2011, 212–3; Ruhs Reference Ruhs2013, 65–71).

This section examines whether it is permissible for states to impose restrictive terms on labor migration when it is used as a tool for climate change adaptation. I argue that receiving states may not restrict the rights of labor migrants in order to make labor migration less costly from their point of view. This is not because would-be migrants cannot voluntarily accept such terms but because, in the context of climate change adaptation, such restrictions represent an unfair attempt to shift the costs of adaptation onto the most vulnerable.

My focus here is on temporary labor migration in particular, for two reasons. First, temporary labor migration is particularly relevant for the context of climate change adaptation, as the climate impacts that generate the need for adaptation are often seasonal or intermittent in nature (Black, Adger, et al. Reference Black, Adger, Arnell, Dercon, Geddes and Thomas2011, 184; de Moor Reference de Moor2011, 8–9; Tacoli Reference Tacoli2009, 520–1). Second, restrictive terms are often seen as most justifiable in the case of temporary labor migration, as permanent migrants are usually thought to acquire a claim to equal citizenship at least after some period (Carens Reference Carens2013). If my argument can demonstrate that restrictions cannot be justified even in the case of temporary labor migration, then this gives us good reason to think that restrictions will be unjustifiable in other cases as well.

Empirical research on migration policy suggests that there is a trade-off between the rights that temporary migrant workers enjoy and the overall number of temporary workers that are accepted: the more expansive the set of rights, the lower the number of temporary workers (Ruhs Reference Ruhs2013; Ruhs and Martin Reference Ruhs and Martin2008). Given the contribution to poverty alleviation and development made by labor migration, some have argued that trade-offs between rights and numbers can be justified, though they vary in the trade-offs that they find acceptable. Eric Posner and Glen Weyl’s rather extreme proposal is that we should “make the U.S. more like Qatar” and accept the existence of a “caste system” between migrant workers and citizens (Posner and Weyl Reference Posner and Weyl2014; see also Weyl Reference Weyl2018). Branko Milanovic makes the more moderate claim that some rights restrictions, including the introduction of lower tiers of citizenship, are justifiable (Milanovic Reference Milanovic2016, 147–54). Perhaps the most modest version of the proposal comes from Martin Ruhs (Reference Ruhs2013, 172–6; see also Brock Reference Brock2020, 156–64), who argues that some limited restrictions on means-tested benefits can be justified, that employment may be restricted to a particular sector (but not to a particular employer), and that rights to family reunion can be restricted if temporary migrants cannot meet a minimum earnings threshold.Footnote 10

In my view, some restrictions are unlikely to be justifiable in any context because they expose temporary workers to significant risks of abuse. Abuse is widespread within many temporary migration schemes—for example, live-in caregivers in Canada face wage theft and violence and construction workers in Gulf states under the Kafala system have their passports removed and are extorted for “debts” owed to recruitment agencies (Brickner and Straehle Reference Brickner and Straehle2010; Brock Reference Brock2020, 143–5)—and is facilitated by the fact that temporary migrant workers occupy a position of vulnerability (Anderson Reference Anderson2010; Lenard and Straehle Reference Lenard and Straehle2010, 287–8). Some rights, such as core labor rights, will need to be safeguarded if temporary migrant workers are to be protected against abuses such as these (Brock Reference Brock2020, 161–2).

We need not determine precisely which rights must be guaranteed here, however, because the claim that I defend here would preclude even more minimal restrictions. That claim is that in the context of climate adaptation, it is impermissible for states to restrict the rights of temporary workers in order to make accepting greater numbers less costly for themselves. I remain agnostic here on whether some trade-offs may be justified in other contexts, but in the context of climate adaptation, even more minimal trade-offs of the kind that Ruhs suggests cannot be justified.

Ordinarily, the debate about restrictions on the rights of temporary migrant workers focuses on whether temporary migrants can voluntarily accept the terms offered to them. Economists often appeal to the “revealed preferences” of temporary migrants who are willing to accept such terms (e.g., Milanovic Reference Milanovic2016, 153; Rodrik Reference Rodrik2011, 269). The problem with such an appeal is that the willingness of temporary migrants to accept such terms is often a result of the fact that the alternatives available to them—such as a life of desperate poverty—are so dire (Bertram Reference Bertram2019). As we have seen, this does not mean that it is not possible for choices to be made voluntarily. But against a background of unacceptable alternatives, it is unreasonable to interpret the willingness of labor migrants to accept such terms as an expression of voluntary choice. But in situations in which migration really is voluntary, perhaps would-be migrants can waive at least some rights. On Robert Mayer’s view, for example, so long as would-be temporary migrants “negotiate from a position of sufficiency,” then “yielding certain rights in exchange for better pay and adventure” is unobjectionable (Mayer Reference Mayer2005, 319).

How does this bear on the situation of those adapting to climate change? At first glance, it appears that those vulnerable to climate impacts are akin to those in poverty in that they need to migrate in order to ameliorate the dire conditions they face. Their choice is made against a background of unacceptable alternatives, so we cannot presume that it is voluntary. But if, as I have argued that they must, states provide real opportunities for adaptation in situ, then labor migrants would no longer be in circumstances where they lack acceptable alternative options. Under such conditions, perhaps those vulnerable to climate impacts really can voluntarily waive some rights. Temporary labor migration, even under restrictive conditions, may well be chosen voluntarily, given that for at least some would-be migrants, the migration project that figures in their life plan is explicitly temporary in character and oriented toward the home state rather than the receiving state (Ottonelli and Torresi Reference Valeria and Torresi2012). The upshot of all of this is that where they have acceptable alternative options, it at least is possible that some of those adapting to climate change really could voluntarily accept restricted regimes of rights.

Whether or not restrictive terms are voluntarily accepted, however, is not the only basis on which we can determine whether they are unjust. Another standard is that of fairness. In my view, considerations of fairness better explain why it is impermissible for states to offer restrictive terms to temporary labor migrants, at least where temporary migration schemes are a tool for climate adaptation.

The duty to facilitate climate change adaptation is, as we have seen, a duty of justice that arises as a result of the actions of high-emitting agents who have brought about the problem of climate change. The costs of the duty to facilitate climate change adaptation, including through labor migration, should be shared on fair terms. Of course, what terms are “fair” is a matter of significant disagreement. Some argue that the costs of adaptation should be distributed according to historic responsibility for climate change (Baer Reference Baer, Neil Adger, Paavola, Huq and Mace2006; Grasso Reference Grasso2010), some argue that they should be distributed according to ability to bear those costs (Moellendorf Reference Moellendorf2014, 186–9), some argue that they should be distributed according to a (qualified) beneficiary pays principle (Baatz Reference Baatz2013), and some argue that some kind of hybrid approach is appropriate (Jagers and Duus-Otterstrom Reference Jagers and Duus-Otterstrom2008).Footnote 11

Fortunately, for our purposes, we need not settle these debates. This is because as a matter of midlevel principle, these competing views generate what Henry Shue (Reference Shue2015) has called a “core practical convergence” on who should bear the costs of adaptation. Of course, there will be some “peripheral theoretical divergence” (Shue Reference Shue2015, 8) about exactly which states are required to bear which costs for adaptation, depending on which principle, or combination of principles, we adopt. But on any plausible conception of fairness, the high-income states that are candidates for accepting labor migrants will be required to bear the lion’s share of the costs—whether because of their disproportionate responsibility for climate change, the significant benefits they have derived from it, or simply their ability to bear those costs. Those most vulnerable to the impacts of climate change, by contrast, will be required to bear at most minimal burdens—whether because of their lack of responsibility for climate change, the relatively few benefits that they have derived from it, or their relative inability to bear those costs. This convergence is not accidental—it arises because contribution, benefit, and capacity often travel together: “those who contributed to the problem of excessive emissions thereby both benefitted more than others and became better able to pay than most others” (Shue Reference Shue2015, 16). According to one (admittedly somewhat crude) attempt to quantify how the burdens of adaptation should be shared on the basis of a combination of these principles, the Least Developed Countries should only be required to bear 1.8% of the costs of adaptation collectively, even on the conservative assumption that states should not be held responsible for emissions before 1990 (Dellink et al. Reference Dellink, den Elzen, Aiking, Bergsma, Berkhout, Dekker and Gupta2009).

With this standard of fairness in mind, it is easy to see why states that offer restrictive terms to would-be migrant workers to reduce the burdens that they face act wrongly. By restricting the rights available to migrant workers, receiving states shift the costs of adaptation onto the most vulnerable, who must themselves bear significant costs—for example, the costs of the risk of facing unemployment without social insurance or the costs of using their own financial resources to support family members who would otherwise be eligible for public benefits. Given that states have duties to share the costs of adaptation on fair terms and that competing conceptions of fairness converge on the principle that high-income states should bear the overwhelming share of the costs of adaptation, shifting the costs of adaptation onto the most vulnerable is patently unfair. Note that this does not mean that those vulnerable to climate change impacts cannot be required to bear any costs—I leave open the question of precisely what costs they can be required to bear here. But imposing costs upon the least advantaged in order that the most advantaged can reduce their own burden violates the demands of any reasonable view of fairness. It would, to borrow a phrase from Shue (Reference Shue2014, 46), be akin to asking the poor to pawn their blankets so that the rich can keep their jewelery. Restrictive terms for labor migration as a form of adaptation can thus be ruled out on grounds of fairness.

Conclusion

This paper has examined a pressing normative issue that sits at the intersection of climate and migration justice: the role of labor migration in adaptation to climate change. First, I argued that states may permissibly use labor migration as a tool of climate change adaptation and that they may even have a duty to do so, but they must also offer alternative options for adaptation in situ. If they fail to do so, they force those vulnerable to climate change to take up opportunities for labor migration, thereby jeopardizing their morally significant interests in being able to remain where they are. Second, I argued that states may not restrict the rights of migrant workers in order to make accepting would-be migrant workers less costly from their point of view. These arguments not only help us to address an important practical problem but also illustrate the ways in which integrating different debates can shed greater theoretical light on the moral terrain of issues in global justice.

If the arguments that I have presented in this paper are correct, then the labor migration policies that meet standards of justice will look quite different from those that have been proposed by international institutions, policy makers, and academics thus far. High-income states are likely to complain that labor migration policy as a tool for adaptation under such constraints will be costly—or at least costlier than anticipated. But high-income states have no right that enabling climate adaptation change be cost free. Fair opportunities for adaptation to climate change are something that high-income states owe to the most vulnerable, not something that they can make conditional on their deriving benefits from it.

Acknowledgments

This paper was presented at the XI Braga Meetings on Ethics and Political Philosophy at the University of Minho, and I thank the audience for the helpful suggestions. I also thank Rufaida Al Hashmi, Samuel Bagg, Jacob Barrett, Chris Bertram, Rob Jubb, Cécile Laborde, Alex McLaughlin, Kieran Oberman, Anthony Taylor, Patrick Tomlin, and four anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.

Conflict of Interest

The author declares no ethical issues or conflicts of interest in this research.

Ethical Standards

The author affirms this research did not involve human subjects.

Footnotes

1 For overviews, see Moellendorf (Reference Moellendorf2015) and Fine (Reference Fine2013) respectively.

2 “Circular” migration here refers to iterated forms of temporary migration.

3 In contexts where the costs of brain or care drain cannot be effectively limited, then this should count against the proposal and may even make it impermissible. This only limits the scope of labor migration, however, rather than undermining the proposal altogether.

4 This does not mean that it will not lead to some costs within the state. But where those costs fall unevenly, redistributive policies can also be used to ensure that the least advantaged do not suffer disproportionate burdens.

5 Oberman (Reference Oberman2011, 262) himself points toward this latter strategy.

6 My argument is consistent with those vulnerable to climate change being required to sacrifice some less basic interests in order to adapt to climate change. I leave open the question of precisely where the boundaries should be drawn here.

7 Adopting this standard does not mean that we should not work toward full justice in adaptation, only that we should not treat decisions made in the absence of full justice as involuntary.

8 An anonymous reviewer worries that it would be unfair if some states were able to discharge their share of adaptation duties through low-cost measures such as facilitating labor migration but others were not. However, if states’ contributions to adaptation are judged not in terms of how much adaptation they facilitate but in terms of how much of the net costs of adaptation they bear—as most work on fairness in adaptation assumes—then admitting states would not be unfairly credited for a greater share of adaptation than others.

10 For other versions of this trade-off argument, see Bell and Piper (Reference Bell, Piper, Kymlicka and He2005) and Rodrik (Reference Rodrik2011, 266–72).

11 For an overview of these debates, see Hartz-Nicholls (Reference Hartz-Nicholls2011).

References

Acemoglu, Daron, Johnson, Simon, and Robinson, James A.. 2001. “The Colonial Origins of Comparative Development: An Empirical Investigation.” The American Economic Review 91 (5): 13691401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Richard H. Jr. and Page, John. 2005. “Do International Migration and Remittances Reduce Poverty in Developing Countries?World Development 33 (10): 1645–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adger, W. Neil, Kelly, P. Mick, Winkels, Alexandra, Huy, Luong Quang, and Locke, Catherine. 2002. “Migration, Remittances, Livelihood Trajectories and Social Resilience.” AMBIO: A Journal of the Human Environment 31 (4): 258–66.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Anderson, Bridget. 2010. “Migration, Immigration Controls, and the Fashioning of Precarious Workers.” Work, Employment and Society 24 (2): 300–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aredo, Dejene. 2010. “The Iddir: an Informal Insurance Arrangement in Ethiopia.” Savings and Development 34 (1): 5372.Google Scholar
Asia Development Bank. 2012. “Addressing Climate Change and Migration in Asia and the Pacific.” Report. March 2012. https://www.adb.org/publications/addressing-climate-change-and-migration-asia-and-pacific.Google Scholar
Ayers, Jessica, and Dodman, David. 2010. “Climate Change Adaptation and Development I: the State of the Debate.” Progress in Development Studies 10 (2): 161–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baatz, Christian. 2013. “Responsibility for the Past? Some Thoughts on Compensating Those Vulnerable to Climate Change in Developing Countries.” Ethics, Policy & Environment 16 (1): 94110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baer, Paul. 2006. “Adaptation: Who Pays Whom?” In Fairness in Adaptation to Climate Change, eds. Neil Adger, W., Paavola, Jouni, Huq, Saleemul, and Mace, M. J., 131–53. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bardsley, Douglas K., and Hugo, Graeme J.. 2010. “Migration and Climate Change: Examining Thresholds of Change to Guide Effective Adaptation Decision-Making.” Population and Environment 32 (2–3): 238–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 2009. The Idea of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bell, Daniel, and Piper, Nicola. 2005. “Justice for Migrant Workers? The Case of Foreign Domestic Workers in Hong Kong and Singapore.” In Multiculturalism in Asia, eds. Kymlicka, Will and He, Baogang, 196222. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bertram, Chris. 2019. “The Openness-Rights Trade-Off in Labor Migration: Claims to Citizenship, and Democratic Justice.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 22 (2): 283–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Black, Richard, Kniveton, Dominic, and Schmidt-Verkerk, Kerstin. 2011. “Migration and Climate Change: Towards an Integrated Assessment of Sensitivity.” Environment and Planning A: Economy and Space 43 (2): 431–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Black, Richard, Stephen, R. G. Bennett, Thomas, Sandy M., and Beddington, John R.. 2011. “Migration as Adaptation.” Nature 478 (7370): 447–49.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Black, Richard, Adger, W. Neil, Arnell, Nigel, Dercon, Stefan, Geddes, Andrew, and Thomas, David. 2011. “Foresight: Migration and Global Environmental Change,” Foresight Reports. London: The Government Office for Science. https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/287717/11-1116-migration-and-global-environmental-change.pdf.Google Scholar
Blake, Michael. 2020. Justice, Migration and Mercy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brickner, Rachel, and Straehle, Christine. 2010. “The Missing Link: Gender, Immigration Policy and the Live-in Caregiver Programme in Canada.” Policy and Society 29 (4): 309–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brock, Gillian. 2020. Justice for People on the Move: Migration in Challenging Times. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 1987. “Justice and Charity.” Ethics 97 (3): 558–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callies, Daniel, and Moellendorf, Darrel. 2021. “Assessing Climate Policies: Catastrophe Avoidance and the Right to Sustainable Development.” Politics, Philosophy and Economics 20 (2): 127–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caney, Simon. 2010. “Climate Change and the Duties of the Advantaged.” Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 13 (1): 203–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caney, Simon. 2012. “Just Emissions.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 40 (4): 255300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carens, Joseph. 2013. The Ethics of Immigration. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dellink, Rob, den Elzen, Michel, Aiking, Harry, Bergsma, Emmy, Berkhout, Frans, Dekker, Thijs, and Gupta, Joyeeta. 2009. “Sharing the Burden of Financing Adaptation to Climate Change.” Global Environmental Change 19 (4): 411–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Haas, Hein. 2005. “International Migration, Remittances and Development: Facts and Myths.” Third World Quarterly 26 (8): 1269–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
de Moor, Nicole. 2011. “Labor Migration for Vulnerable Communities: A Strategy to Adapt to a Changing Environment.” COMCAD Working Papers 101. https://www.ssoar.info/ssoar/handle/document/38064.Google Scholar
de Sherbinin, Alex. 2014. “Climate Change Hotspots Mapping: What Have We Learned?Climatic Change 123 (1): 2337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deressa, Temesgen Tadesse, and Hassan, Rashid M.. 2009. “Economic Impact of Climate Change on Crop Production in Ethiopia: Evidence from Cross-Section Measures.” Journal of African Economies 18 (4): 529–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Docquier, Frédéric, and Rapoport, Hillel. 2012. “Globalization, Brain Drain, and Development.” Journal of Economic Literature 50 (3): 681730.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Draper, Jamie. 2021. “Justice and Internal Displacement.” Political Studies. https://doi.org/10.1177/00323217211007641.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dustmann, Christian, and Mestres, Josep. 2010. “Remittances and Temporary Migration.” Journal of Development Economics 92 (1): 6270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eriksen, Siri, Schipper, E. Lisa F., Scoville-Simonds, Morgan, Vincent, Katharine, Adam, Hans Nicolai, Brooks, Nick, Harding, Brian, et al. 2021. “Adaptation Interventions and their Effect on Vulnerability in Developing Countries: Help, Hindrance, or Irrelevance?World Development 141: 105383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ezra, Markos, and Kiros, Gebre-Egzaibher. 2001. “Rural Out-Migration in the Drought-Prone Areas of Ethiopia: A Multilevel Analysis.” International Migration Review 35 (3): 749–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fankhauser, Samuel. 2010. “The Costs of Adaptation.” Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 1 (1): 2330.Google Scholar
Fankhauser, Samuel, Smith, Joel B., and Richard, S. J. Tol. 1999. “Weathering Climate Change: Some Simple Rules to Guide Adaptation Decisions.” Ecological Economics 30 (1): 6778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Sarah. 2013. “The Ethics of Immigration: Self-Determination and the Right to Exclude.” Philosophy Compass 8 (3): 254–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Folke, Carl. 2006. “Resilience: The Emergence of a Perspective for Social–Ecological Systems Analyses.” Global Environmental Change 16 (3): 253–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardiner, Stephen M. 2011. A Perfect Moral Storm: The Ethical Tragedy of Climate Change. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gemenne, François, and Blocher, Julia. 2017. “How Can Migration Serve Adaptation to Climate Change? Challenges to Fleshing Out a Policy Ideal.” The Geographical Journal 183 (4): 336–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gheaus, Anca. 2013. “Care Drain: Who Should Provide for the Children Left Behind?Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 16 (1): 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grasso, Marco. 2010. “An Ethical Approach to Climate Adaptation Finance.” Global Environmental Change 20 (1): 7481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gray, Clark, and Mueller, Valerie. 2012. “Drought and Population Mobility in Rural Ethiopia.” World Development 40 (1): 134–45.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hartz-Nicholls, Lauren. 2011. “Responsibility for Meeting the Costs of Adaptation.” Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 2 (5): 687700.Google Scholar
Heltberg, Rasumus, Siegel, Paul Bennett, and Jorgensen, Steen Lau. 2009. “Addressing Human Vulnerability to Climate Change: Towards a ‘No-Regrets’ Approach.” Global Environmental Change 19 (1): 8999.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heyward, Clare. 2017. “Ethics and Climate Adaptation.” In The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics, eds. Gardiner, Stephen M. and Thompson, Allen, 474–86. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hunter, Lori M., Murray, Sheena, and Riosmena, Fernando. 2013. “Rainfall Patterns and U.S. Migration from Rural Mexico.” International Migration Review 47 (4): 874909.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). 2014. Climate Change 2014: Impacts, Adaptation and Vulnerability. Part A: Global and Sectoral Aspects. Contribution of Working Group II to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change, eds. Field, Christopher B., Barros, Vincente R., Dokken, David J., Mach, Katharine J., Mastrandrea, Michael D., Bilir, T. Eren, Chatterjee, Monalisa, et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Isaksen, Lise Widding, Devi, Sambasivan Uma, and Hochschild, Arlie Russell. 2008. “Global Care Crisis: A Problem of Capital, Care Chain, or Commons?American Behavioural Scientist 52 (3): 405–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jagers, Sverker C., and Duus-Otterstrom, Göran. 2008. “Dual Climate Change Responsibility: On the Moral Divergences between Mitigation and Adaptation.” Environmental Politics 17 (4): 576–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kälin, Walter. 2010. “Conceptualizing Climate-Induced Displacement.” In Climate Change and Displacement: Multidisciplinary Perspectives, ed. McAdam, Jane, 81104. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Kapur, Devesh, and McHale, John. 2005. Give Us Your Best and Brightest: The Global Hunt for Talent and Its Impact on the Developing World. Washington DC: Centre for Global Development.Google Scholar
Lenard, Patti Tamara, and Straehle, Christine. 2010. “Temporary Labor Migration: Exploitation, Tool of Development, or Both?Policy and Society 29 (4): 284–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lenard, Patti Tamara, and Straehle, Christine. 2011. “Temporary Migration, Global Redistribution and Democratic Justice.” Politics, Philosophy and Economics 11 (2): 206–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Little, Peter D., Stone, M. Priscilla, Tewodaj Mogues, A. Peter Castro, and Negatu, Workneh. 2006. “‘Moving in Place’: Drought and Poverty Dynamics in South Wollo, Ethiopia.” The Journal of Development Studies 42 (2): 200–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maharjan, Amina, de Campos, Ricardo Safra, Singh, Chandni, Das, Shouvik, Srinivas, Arjun, Bhuiyan, Mohammad Rashed Alam, Ishaq, Sultan, et al. 2020. “Migration and Household Adaptation in Climate-Sensitive Hotspots in South Asia.” Current Climate Change Reports 6: 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Massey, Douglas, Arango, Joaquin, Hugo, Graeme, Kouaouci, Ali, Pellegrino, Adela, and Taylor, J. Edward. 1993. “Theories of International Migration: A Review and Appraisal.” Population and Development Review 19 (3): 431–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, Robert. 2005. “Guestworkers and Exploitation.” The Review of Politics 67 (2): 311–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLeman, Robert, and Smit, Barry. 2006. “Migration as an Adaptation to Climate Change.” Climatic Change 76 (1–2): 3153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McLeman, Robert, and Hunter, Lori. 2010. “Migration in the Context of Vulnerability and Adaptation to Climate Change: Insights from Analogues.” Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 1 (3): 450–61.Google ScholarPubMed
Milanovic, Branko. 2016. Global Inequality: A New Approach for the Age of Globalization. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
Miller, David. 2007. National Responsibility and Global Justice. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moellendorf, Darrel. 2014. The Moral Challenge of Dangerous Climate Change: Values, Poverty, and Policy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moellendorf, Darrel. 2015. “Climate Change Justice.” Philosophy Compass 10 (3): 173–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moore, Margaret. 2015. A Political Theory of Territory. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Narain, Urvashi, Margulis, Sergio, and Essam, Timothy. 2011. “Estimating the Costs of Adaptation to Climate Change.” Climate Policy 11 (3): 1001–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oberman, Kieran. 2011. “Immigration, Global Poverty, and the Right to Stay.” Political Studies 59 (2): 253–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oberman, Kieran. 2015. “Poverty and Immigration Policy.” American Political Science Review 109 (2): 239–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Olsaretti, Serena. 2004. Liberty, Desert, and the Market: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Valeria, Ottonelli, and Torresi, Tiziana. 2012. “Inclusivist Liberal Egalitarianism and Temporary Migration: A Dilemma.” Journal of Political Philosophy 20 (2): 202–24.Google Scholar
Ottonelli, Valeria, and Torresi, Tiziana. 2013. “When is Migration Voluntary?International Migration Review 47 (4): 783813.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jouni, Paavola, and Adger, W. Neil. 2006. “Fair Adaptation to Climate Change.” Ecological Economics 56 (4): 594609.Google Scholar
Piguet, Etienne, Pécoud, Antoine, and de Guchteneire, Paul. 2011. “Migration and Climate Change: An Overview.” Refugee Survey Quarterly 30 (3): 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. 2002. World Poverty and Human Rights. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Porter, Catherine. 2012. “Shocks, Consumption and Income Diversification in Rural Ethiopia.” Journal of Development Studies 48 (9): 1209–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Posner, Eric, and Weyl, Glen. 2014. “A Radical Solution to Global Income Inequality: Make the U.S. More like Qatar.” The New Republic, November 7. https://newrepublic.com/article/120179/how-reduce-global-income-inequality-open-immigration-policies.Google Scholar
Rodrik, Dani. 2011. The Globalization Paradox: Why Global Markets, States, and Democracy Can’t Coexist. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Ruhs, Martin. 2013. The Price of Rights: Regulating International Labor Migration. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Ruhs, Martin, and Martin, Philip. 2008. “Numbers vs. Rights: Trade-Offs and Guest-Worker Programs.” International Migration Review 42 (1): 249–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schelling, Thomas C. 1992. “Some Economics of Global Warming.” The American Economic Review 82 (1): 114.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shue, Henry. 2014. Climate Justice: Vulnerability and Protection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Shue, Henry. 2015. “Historical Responsibility, Harm Prohibition, and Preservation Requirement: Core Practical Convergence on Climate Change.” Moral Philosophy and Politics 2 (1): 731.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stark, Oded. 1991. The Migration of Labor. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stark, Oded, Helmenstein, Christian, and Prskawetz, Alexia. 1997. “A Brain Drain with a Brain Gain.” Economics Letters 55 (2): 227–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stark, Oded, and Bloom, David. 1985. “The New Economics of Labor Migration.” The American Economic Review 75 (2): 173–78.Google Scholar
Stilz, Anna. 2019. Territorial Sovereignty: A Philosophical Exploration. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tacoli, Cecilia. 2009. “Crisis or Adaptation? Migration and Climate Change in the Context of High Mobility.” Environment & Urbanization 21 (2): 513–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, J. Edward. 1999. “The New Economics of Labor Migration and the Role of Remittances in the Migration Process.” International Migration 37 (1): 6388.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Valentini, Laura. 2013. “Justice, Charity and Disaster Relief: What Do We Owe to Haiti, New Zealand and Japan?American Journal of Political Science 57 (2): 491503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Warner, Koko, and Afifi, Tamer. 2014. “Where the Rain Falls: Evidence from 8 Countries on How Vulnerable Households Use Migration to Manage the Risk of Rainfall Variability and Food Insecurity.” Climate and Development 6 (1): 117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Webber, Michael, and Barnett, Jon. 2010. Accommodating Migration to Promote Adaptation to Climate Change. Washington, DC: The World Bank.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weyl, Glen. 2018. “The Openness-Equality Trade-off in Global Redistribution.” The Economic Journal 128 (612): F1F36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, Jonathan. 1998. “Fairness, Respect, and the Egalitarian Ethos.” Philosophy & Public Affairs 27 (2): 97122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, Jonathan, and De-Shalit, Avner. 2007. Disadvantage. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Bank. 2016. Migration and Remittances Factbook 2016, 3rd edition. Washington DC: World Bank.Google Scholar
Yang, Dean, and Choi, HwaJung. 2007. “Are Remittances Insurance? Evidence from Rainfall Shocks in the Philippines.” The World Bank Economic Review 21 (2): 219–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Submit a response

Comments

No Comments have been published for this article.