Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-mzp66 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-10T10:59:44.207Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rationality and Time Bias

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  09 January 2025

Abelard Podgorski
Affiliation:
National University of Singapore

Summary

We often care not only about what happens to us, but when it happens to us. We prefer that good experiences happen sooner, rather than later, and that our suffering lies in our past, rather than our future. Common sense suggests that some ways of caring about time are rational, and others are not, but it is surprisingly challenging to provide justifying explanations for these tendencies. This Element is an opinionated, non-technical guided tour through the main philosophical issues about the relevance of the temporal location of our experiences to our desires and our choices, and the major arguments for and against different kinds of so-called time bias.
Get access
Type
Element
Information
Online ISBN: 9781009216920
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication: 16 January 2025

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Ahmed, A. (2018). Rationality and Future Discounting. Topoi, 39(2), 245256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ainslie, G. & Haslam, N. (1992). Hyperbolic Discounting. In Loewenstein, G. & Elster, J. (eds.), Choice Over Time. Russell Sage Foundation, 5792.Google Scholar
Baker, C. & Maguire, B. (2020). The Alienation Objection to Consequentialism. In Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. Oxford University Press, 477491.Google Scholar
Braddon-Mitchell, D. (2004). How Do We Know It Is Now Now? Analysis, 64, 199203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bransen, J. (2015). Self-Knowledge and Self-Love. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 18(2), 309321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brink, D. O. (2011). Prospects for Temporal Neutrality. In Callender, Craig (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time. Oxford University Press, 353381.Google Scholar
Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through Reasoning. Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchak, L. (2013). Risk and Rationality. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callender, C. (2023). Temporal Neutrality Implies Exponential Temporal Discounting. Philosophy of Science. Advance Online Publication.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Callender, C. & Suhler, C. (2012). Thank Goodness That Argument Is Over: Explaining the Temporal Value Asymmetry. Philosophers’ Imprint, 12, 116.Google Scholar
Caruso, E. M., Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2008). A Wrinkle in Time Asymmetric Valuation of Past and Future Events. Psychological Science, 19(8), 796801.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Casati, R. & Torrengo, G. (2011). The Not So Incredible Shrinking Future. Analysis, 71(2), 240244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caspar, H. (2013). Time – The Emotional Asymmetry. In Dyke, Heather & Bardon, Adrian (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Time. Chichester, UK: Wiley, 507520.Google Scholar
Charvet, J. (1995). The Idea of an Ethical Community. Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Christensen, D. (1996). Dutch-Book Arguments Depragmatized: Epistemic Consistency for Partial Believers. Journal of Philosophy, 93(9), 450479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Correia, F. & Rosenkranz, S. (2018). Nothing to Come: A Defence of the Growing Block Theory of Time. Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Deng, N., Latham, A. J., Miller, K., & Norton, J. (forthcoming). There’s No Time Like the Present: Present-Bias, Temporal Attitudes and Temporal Ontology. In Knobe, J. and Nichols, S. (eds.), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dorsey, D. (2019). A Near‐Term Bias Reconsidered. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 99(2), 461477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, T. (2011). On Whether to Prefer Pain to Pass. Ethics, 121(3), 521537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, T. (2015). Future Bias and Practical Reason. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15.Google Scholar
Douglas, T. (2019). Parental Partiality and Future Children. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 15(1), 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ericson, K. M. & Laibson, D. (2019). Intertemporal Choice. In Bernheim, B. D., DellaVigna, S., & Laibson, D., (eds.), Handbook of Behavioral Economics: Applications and Foundations, Vol. 2, chapter 1. Elsevier, 167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, P. (2004). The Real but Dead Past: A Reply to Braddon-Mitchell. Analysis, 64(4), 358362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frederick, S., Loewenstein, G., & O’Donoghue, T. (2002). Time Discounting and Time Preference: A Critical Review. Journal of Economic Literature, 40(2), 351401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, P. & Sullivan, M. (2015). Against Time Bias. Ethics, 125(4), 947970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greene, P., Latham, A. J., Miller, K., & Norton, J. (2022). Capacity for Simulation and Mitigation Drives Hedonic and Non-hedonic Time Biases. Philosophical Psychology, 35(2), 226252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gustafsson, J. (2022). Money-Pump Arguments. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halevy, Y. (2015). Time Consistency: Stationarity and Time Invariance. Econometrica, 83(1), 335352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hansson, B. (1988). Risk-Aversion as a Problem of Conjoint Measurement. In Gärdenfors, P. and Sahlin, N.-E. (eds.), Decision, Probability, and Utility. Cambridge University Press, 136158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, C. (2007). Self-Bias, Time-Bias, and the Metaphysics of the Self and Time. Journal of Philosophy, 104(7), 350373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, C. (2008). A Puzzle about Other-Directed Time-Bias. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86(2), 269277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heathwood, C. (2008). Fitting Attitudes and Welfare. Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 3, 4773.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heathwood, C. (2016). Desire-Fulfillment Theory. In Fletcher, G. (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Well-Being. Routledge, 135147.Google Scholar
Heathwood, C. (2019). Which Desires Are Relevant to Well‐Being? Noûs, 53(3), 664688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hedden, B. (2015a). Time-Slice Rationality. Mind, 124(494), 449491.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hedden, B. (2015b). Options and Diachronic Tragedy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 423451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hedden, B. (2016). Does MITE Make Right?: On Decision-Making under Normative Uncertainty. In Shafer-Landau, R. (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, 11, 102128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hubin, D. (1991). Irrational Desires. Philosophical Studies, 62(1), 2344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. (1739). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kagan, S. (1986). The Present-Aim Theory of Rationality. Ethics, 96(4), 746759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kahneman, D., Fredrickson, B. L., Schreiber, C. A., & Redelmeier, D. A. (1993). When More Pain Is Preferred to Less: Adding a Better End. Psychological Science, 4(6), 401405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Karhu, T. (2022). What Justifies Our Bias toward the Future? Australasian Journal of Philosophy. Advance online publication.Google Scholar
Keller, S. (2006). Four Theories of Filial Duty. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(223), 254274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kiesewetter, B. (2020). Rationality as Reasons-Responsiveness. Australasian Philosophical Review, 4(4), 332342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. (1985). Kant’s Formula of Universal Law. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66(1–2), 2447.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latham, A. J., Miller, K., & Norton, J. (2023). Against a Normative Asymmetry between Near- and Future-Bias. Synthese, 201(3), 131.Google Scholar
Levi, I. (2002). Money Pumps and Diachronic Books. Philosophy of Science, 69(3), 235247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loewenstein, G. & Prelec, D. (1993). Preferences for Sequences of Outcomes. Psychological Review, 100(1), 91108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lowry, R. & Peterson, M. (2011). Pure Time Preference. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 92(4), 490508.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMahan, J. (2002). The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McTaggart, J. M. E. (1908). The Unreality of Time. Mind, 17, 457474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, K. (2021). What Time-Travel Teaches Us about Future-Bias. Philosophies, 6(38), 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moller, D. (2002). Parfit on Pains, Pleasures, and the Time of Their Occurrence. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 32(1), 6782.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, R. (1969). Newcomb’s Problem and Two Principles of Choice. In Rescher, N. (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel. Reidel, 114146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Derek., Parfit (1984). Reasons and Persons. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Paul, L. (2014). Transformative Experience. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2019). Choosing for Changing Selves. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettigrew, R. (2020). Dutch Book Arguments. Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pigou, A. C. (1920). The Economics of Welfare. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Plato. (1992). Protagoras. Translated by Lombardo, S., & Bell, K. Hackett.Google Scholar
Podgorski, A. (2016). A Reply to the Synchronist. Mind, 125(499), 859871.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Prior, A. (1959). Thank Goodness That’s over. Philosophy, 34(128), 1217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, P. (1984). Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 13(2), 134171.Google Scholar
Saad, B. (2023). The Sooner the Better: An Argument for Bias toward the Earlier. Journal of the American Philosophical Association.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, H. (1884). The Methods of Ethics. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Street, S. (2009). In Defense of Future Tuesday Indifference: Ideally Coherent Eccentrics and the Contingency of What Matters. Philosophical Issues, 19(1), 273298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strotz, R. H. (1955). Myopia and Inconsistency in Dynamic Utility Maximization. The Review of Economic Studies, 23(3), 165180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sullivan, M. (2018). Time Biases: A Theory of Rational Planning and Personal Persistence. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tarsney, C. (2017). Thank Goodness that’s Newcomb: The Practical Relevance of the Temporal Value Asymmetry. Analysis, 77(4), 750759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Titelbaum, M. G. (2015). Rationality’s Fixed Point (or: In Defense of Right Reason). In Gendler, T. Szabó and Hawthorne, John (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, Volume 5. Oxford University Press, 253294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Urminsky, O. (2017). The Role of Psychological Connectedness to the Future Self in Decisions over Time. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 26(1), 3439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (1991). Well‐Being and Time. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 72(1), 4877.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wang, M., Rieger, M. O., & Hens, T. (2016). How Time Preferences Differ: Evidence from 53 Countries. Journal of Economic Psychology, 52, 115135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weatherson, B. (2019). Normative Externalism. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Żuradzki, T. (2016). Time-Biases and Rationality: The Philosophical Perspectives on Empirical Research about Time Preferences. In Stelmach, J., Brożek, B., & Kurek, Ł (eds.), The Emergence of Normative Orders. Copernicus Press, 149187.Google Scholar

Save element to Kindle

To save this element to your Kindle, first ensure no-reply@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Rationality and Time Bias
Available formats
×

Save element to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Rationality and Time Bias
Available formats
×

Save element to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Rationality and Time Bias
Available formats
×